Download Three Views of Two Degrees - Climate Emergency Institute

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts

Low-carbon economy wikipedia , lookup

Stern Review wikipedia , lookup

Myron Ebell wikipedia , lookup

Michael E. Mann wikipedia , lookup

Climate resilience wikipedia , lookup

Climatic Research Unit email controversy wikipedia , lookup

Heaven and Earth (book) wikipedia , lookup

ExxonMobil climate change controversy wikipedia , lookup

Mitigation of global warming in Australia wikipedia , lookup

German Climate Action Plan 2050 wikipedia , lookup

Soon and Baliunas controversy wikipedia , lookup

Economics of climate change mitigation wikipedia , lookup

Effects of global warming on human health wikipedia , lookup

2009 United Nations Climate Change Conference wikipedia , lookup

Climate change denial wikipedia , lookup

Global warming hiatus wikipedia , lookup

Global warming controversy wikipedia , lookup

Fred Singer wikipedia , lookup

General circulation model wikipedia , lookup

Climate change adaptation wikipedia , lookup

Climate engineering wikipedia , lookup

Climate sensitivity wikipedia , lookup

Climatic Research Unit documents wikipedia , lookup

Global warming wikipedia , lookup

Climate change in Tuvalu wikipedia , lookup

Climate change and agriculture wikipedia , lookup

Instrumental temperature record wikipedia , lookup

Climate governance wikipedia , lookup

Citizens' Climate Lobby wikipedia , lookup

Economics of global warming wikipedia , lookup

Effects of global warming wikipedia , lookup

Climate change feedback wikipedia , lookup

Solar radiation management wikipedia , lookup

Attribution of recent climate change wikipedia , lookup

United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change wikipedia , lookup

Climate change in the United States wikipedia , lookup

Politics of global warming wikipedia , lookup

Media coverage of global warming wikipedia , lookup

Effects of global warming on humans wikipedia , lookup

Carbon Pollution Reduction Scheme wikipedia , lookup

Scientific opinion on climate change wikipedia , lookup

Climate change and poverty wikipedia , lookup

Business action on climate change wikipedia , lookup

Public opinion on global warming wikipedia , lookup

Climate change, industry and society wikipedia , lookup

Surveys of scientists' views on climate change wikipedia , lookup

IPCC Fourth Assessment Report wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
Three Views of Two Degrees
Carlo C. Jaeger
Julia Jaeger
ECF Working Paper 2/2010
European Climate Forum – Mission
ECF initiates and performs high-class research on climate change in close interaction with stakeholders. We provide a pluralistic communication platform in the
emerging global field of researchers, governments, local authorities, businesses,
and social movements. This field lies beyond the traditional linkage between academic institutions and the nation state hosting them. It requires a capability to
learn from each other in situations where consensus is impossible, perhaps not
even desirable. As a key requisite for addressing the climate challenge in this spirit,
ECF contributes to a new economic theory that will enhance our capability to
manage climate risks.
European Climate Forum e.V.
P.O. Box 600648
D-14406 Potsdam - Germany
[email protected]
www.european-climateforum.net
ECF Working Paper 2/2010
Title: Three Views of Two
Degrees
Authors: Carlo C. Jaeger1,
Julia Jaeger2
Design: Katherina Heil
1Potsdam Institute for Climate Impact Research, European Climate Forum and
Beijing Normal University
2European Climate Forum
ISBN: 978-3-941663-08-4
Three Views of Two Degrees
Carlo C. Jaeger, Julia Jaeger
ECF Working Paper 2/2010
Abstract
Limiting global warming to 2° Celsius above global mean temperature in pre-industrial times has become a widely debated possible goal for climate policy. It has been
supported by many scientists, the European Union, the G8 and larger international
bodies. However, some claim that it is way too stringent, others that it is not sufficient to avoid major climate risks. We show how the limit emerged out of a marginal
remark in an early paper about climate policy and distinguish three possible views
of it. The catastrophe view sees it as the threshold separating a domain of safety
from a domain of catastrophe. The cost-benefit view sees it as a strategy to optimize
the relation between the costs and benefits of limiting greenhouse gas emissions.
And the focal point view sees it as a solution to a complex coordination problem.
We assess these three views, including a philosophical reflection on some conceptual
confusion concerning value judgments, and conclude that the focal point view is the
most appropriate. It leads to an emphasis on implementing effective steps towards a
near-zero emissions economy and to accept that in the course of time the focal point
may be redefined on the basis of practical experiences.
3
4
Introduction
The climate conference of Copenhagen in 2009 marks a turning point in the
history of climate policy. After this experience, the chances that a binding global
agreement will reduce global greenhouse gas emissions anytime soon are definitely low. The summit was unable to reach a common decision, and remained vague
or silent on key questions of climate policy like national commitments to emissions
reduction, compensation for climate damages, and more. It did, however, further
enhance the visibility of the 2° target: the benchmark that requires climate policy
to limit global warming to 2° Celsius above pre-industrial levels.
The disappointing Copenhagen conference could lead to a healthy rethinking of
major assumptions often taken for granted in climate policy. Perhaps it is quite
useful to lower the expectations towards international climate policy while developing other opportunities for action in parallel with it. In many areas, international
diplomacy needs gestation periods of many years in order to prepare a next breakthrough. The opportunity for such breakthroughs in turn may depend on actions
taking place in other arenas. The 2° target can help to orient both international
climate policy and other actions for tackling the challenge of climate change. But
why 2°? Answering this question is the topic of the present paper.
A useful starting point is given by the following statement in the Copenhagen Accord: “To achieve the ultimate objective of the Convention to stabilize greenhouse
gas concentration in the atmosphere at a level that would prevent dangerous anthropogenic interference with the climate system, we shall, recognizing the scientific
view that the increase in global temperature should be below 2 degrees Celsius,
on the basis of equity and in the context of sustainable development, enhance our
long-term cooperative action to combat climate change” (UNFCCC 2010, p.5).
The Copenhagen Accord was prepared at the 2009 Conference of the Parties to
the United Nations framework Convention on Climate Change in Copenhagen;
the parties agreed to take note of the document, but it is not a legally binding text.
In this respect, it is similar to the statement by the G8 governments: “We recognize the scientific view that the increase in global average temperature above preindustrial levels ought not to exceed 2 degrees C” (G8 2009, p. 19) and a similar
statement by the “Major Economies Forum”, representing 16 countries and the
European Union (Major Economies Forum 2009).
Even if these are no legally binding statements, they strengthen an important argument about how to interpret a text that is legally binding: §2 of the UN Framework Convention on Climate Change. That well-known paragraph states that the
convention has the “ultimate objective to prevent dangerous anthropogenic interference with the climate system“ (UNFCCC 1992, §2). The convention has been
5
ratified by countries all over the world, not only those that have ratified the Kyoto
protocol. It is valid international law. And while the force of international law is
much less obvious than the one of national law, the old Roman saying “pacta sunt
servanda” – agreements must be kept – is a rule on which the society of nations
can and does rely most of the time, despite quite a few exceptions. How to interpret the phrase “dangerous anthropogenic interference with the climate system”,
then, is by no means trivial. And the Copenhagen Accord along with statements
like those of the G8 and the Major Economies Forum lends force to the claim it
should be understood as anthropogenic global warming of more than 2° Celsius
above pre-industrial levels.
How to interpret the phrase on dangerous interference has been the subject of
intense debate (Dessai et al. 2004, Hare 2003, Oppenheimer and Alley 2005,
Schellnhuber et al. 2006, Schneider 2001). While it is unclear whether a canonical interpretation will ever be established, the 2° target has emerged as the most
prominent interpretation in the debate.
We discuss this emergent property of the climate debate as follows. The 2° target
was first introduced by a marginal remark in one of the early papers on climate
risks. It was then taken up in a perspective of catastrophe theory as a possibility to
delimit a domain of safety in order to avoid climate catastrophes. We call this the
catastrophe view, in contrast to the cost-benefit view. The latter justifies the limit
by comparing benefits of avoiding climate damages – expressed as percentage
points of GDP – with costs of reducing economic growth. We argue that while
both views contribute important insights, none of them provides a clear rationale
for why the 2° target should be more appropriate than a series of conceivable
alternatives. We then claim that the debate about the 2° target suffers from a
conceptual confusion that can be overcome with the help of recent insights from
philosophy: the influential dichotomy between facts and values can and must be
relativized by a more careful look at the descriptive and normative uses of words.
With that background, we propose a view of the 2° target as a possible focal point
in a coordination game, and argue that it is good enough for that purpose. The
debate should now focus on how to reach a new coordination equilibrium of the
world economy characterized by near-zero emissions.
6
A First Intuition
Surprisingly, perhaps, the first suggestion to use 2° Celsius as a critical limit for
climate policy was made by an economist, W.D. Nordhaus, in a graph published
in a discussion paper of the prestigious Cowles foundation (figure 1).
There he claimed: “As a first approximation, it seems reasonable to argue that
the climatic effects of carbon dioxide should be kept within the normal range of
long-term climatic variation. According to most sources the range of variation
between distinct climatic regimes is in the order of 5°C, and at the present time
the global climate is at the high end of this range. If there were global temperatures more than 2 or 3° above the current average temperature, this would take
the climate outside of the range of observations which have been made over the
last several hundred thousand years” (Nordhaus 1977, p.39-40; see also Nordhaus
1975, p.22-23, where the same words are to be found, but without the suggestive
diagram).
Figure 1 settles an important question about the history of the 2° target. As Oppenheimer and Petsonk (2005, p.195-6) say: “In the climate change context, the
history of an idea matters. History may illuminate the intended meaning of Article 2, and it could make apparent what notions of danger were cast aside during
the debate over Article 2, and which notions have been omitted altogether. A
clear understanding of the process through which the concept has evolved could
help shape current efforts to reach a consensus interpretation.” According to Tol
(2007), the 2° target was first raised in a statement of the German Advisory Council for Global Change (WBGU 1995). That statement was a comment on the first
Conference of the Parties of the UNFCCC, held in Berlin and chaired by Angela
Merkel, then German minister of the environment. Tol mentions that according
to Oppenheimer and Petsonk (2005) the 2° target was introduced by Nordhaus
already in the 1970s, but denies this referring to Nordhaus (1991). The latter paper discusses the idea of optimal climate policy without mentioning the 2° target
at all.
7
6
Past and Projected
Change in Global
Mean Temperature,
degrees Centigrade
5
4
Estimated maximum experienced over last 100,000 years
3
Normal range of variation
in given climatic regime
2
1
0
1900
1920
1940
1960
1980
2000
2020
2040
2060
2080
Figure 1. Past and projected global mean temperature related to 1850-84 mean. Solid curve up to
1970 is actual temperature. Broken curve from 1970 is projection using 1970 actual as a base and
adding the estimated increase due to uncontrolled buildup of atmospheric carbon dioxide.
Figure 1, however, taken from the original paper of Nordhaus (1977) along with
the corresponding quote from Nordhaus (1975, p. 22-23) clarifies that the 2° target is indeed more than two decades older than Tol assumes. Moreover, as we will
see below, AGGG (1990) is another important step between Nordhaus (1975) and
WBGU (1995). The real importance of the German advisory board – and specifically its later chairman, Hans Joachim Schellnhuber – in this matter lies elsewhere: by convincing Angela Merkel of the 2° target, it did indeed trigger the political
process that fifteen years later led to the global visibility conferred to the 2° target
by the G8, the Major Economies Forum, and the Conference of the Parties held
in 2010 in Copenhagen.
Figure 1: The first suggestion
of 2° Celsius as a critical limit
(Nordhaus, 1977, p.3).
8
Atmospheric CO2 in ppm
Variation in temperature in C°
400
20
15
350
10
300
5
CO2
250
Figure 2: Estimates of past
temperature and CO2 concentration (von Weizsäcker et
al. 1998,
p.226, based
on Jouzel 1987).
0
200
-5
Temperature
150
160 000
130 000
110 000
89 000
-10
67 000
44 000
13 000
today
In 1975, Nordhaus thought that 2° warming was roughly equivalent to doubling
pre-industrial CO2 concentrations, and took the latter benchmark as a preliminary standard – as would the vast majority of climate modellers who in the subsequent years fed the IPCC with estimates of climate impacts at double CO2 concentration. Introducing the 2° target was by no means a major point in Nordhaus’
intentions, but then the image of an invisible hand became a hugely influential
metaphor after having been introduced by another economist as a minor remark
in his work on the wealth of nations.
Nordhaus just expressed a preliminary intuition and did not support his claims by
data or references. He admitted freely “that the process of setting standards used
in this section is deeply unsatisfactory” (Nordhaus 1977, p.41). A decade later,
however, data from the Vostok ice core made better estimates of past temperatures possible (figure 2). And the newer data did support the claim that global mean
temperatures much higher than 2° higher above those around 1800 were hardly
ever experienced during the last 100,000 years, and probably much longer.
The Catastrophe View
For over a decade, Nordhaus’ first intuition played no significant role in the climate policy debate. The 2° limit, however, reemerged as an important issue in 1990,
the year when IPCC published its first assessment report. Remarkably, perhaps,
the 2° limit was not discussed there, and it has never been since then in any IPCC
document. Rather, the 2° limit was forcefully introduced into the climate debate
by the influential report of the so-called AGGG, the WMO/ICSU/UNEP Advisory Group on Greenhouse Gases ” (Rijsberman, Swart, 1990).
However, while Nordhaus had argued for a 2° Celsius limit with the argument of
a natural range – which also entails an ice-covered Europe, sea level variations of
over 100 m or temperature changes over Greenland of up to 16° Celsius within
decades (Lang et al. 1999) – the new proponents argued for the same number by
treating it as a threshold beyond which catastrophe looms. The AGGG report
claimed that a 2° Celsius increase was “an upper limit beyond which the risks of
grave damage to ecosystems, and of non-linear responses, are expected to increase rapidly” (Rijsberman, Swart, 1990).
Clearly, the two arguments do not exclude each other, and the German Advisory
Council on Global Change supported both lines of thinking in 1995. It considered the late Quaternary, i.e. the period of the last 800,000 or so years, and claimed: “This geological epoch has shaped our present-day environment, with the
lowest temperatures occurring in the last ice age (mean minimum around 10.4
°C) and the highest temperatures during the last interglacial period (mean maximum around 16.1 °C). If this temperature range is exceeded in either direction,
dramatic changes in the composition and function of today’s ecosystems can be
expected. If we extend the tolerance range by a further 0.5 °C at either end, then
the tolerable temperature window extends from 9.9 °C to 16.6 °C. Today’s global
mean temperature is around 15.3 °C, which means that the temperature span to
the tolerable maximum is currently only 1.3 °C” (WBGU 1995, p. 7). By adding
0.7° C for the increase from pre-industrial levels to 1995, this is equivalent to the
2° limit (as re-iterated in WGBU 1997, p. 13-14).
In 1996, the Council of the European Union officially adopted the 2° limit as a
standard of climate policy: „Given the serious risk of such an increase and particularly the very high rate of change, the Council believes that global average
temperatures should not exceed 2 degree above pre-industrial level” (European
Union Council, 1996, item no. 6).
9
10
Figure 3: A catastrophe landscape.
Black line: stable equilibria;
red disk: tipping point.
The claim according to which there is a temperature limit beyond which important risks increase rapidly has encouraged talk of a „climate catastrophe“. While
the emotional connotations of this expression are quite clear, there is also an important technical side to it, related to mathematical catastrophe theory (e.g. Castrigiano and Hayes 2004). This theory analyses non-linear dynamical systems for
which continuous change of critical parameters can have minor effects on the
behaviour of the system for a certain parameter range, while leading to abrupt
change beyond a well-defined tipping point. Figure 3 illustrates this situation by
representing the so-called fold catastrophe: a valley providing a set of stable equilibria – as long as a parameter defining where in the valley the system sits does not
exceed the tipping point.
11
1.5
THC
1.0
0.5
Abrupt change
Figure 4: The catastrophe
structure of the thermohaline
circulation (Alley et al. 2003,
p. 2007). Green / blue: noncatastrophic relation between
freshwater forcing and THC;
Yellow / red: relation in the
catastrophic domain
0.0
-0.5
0
0.1
0.2
0.3
0.4
0.5
0.6
Freshwater forcing
With this background, the concept of abrupt climate change gained prominence
in the climate policy debate (Alley et al. 2003). Even more visibility was achieved
by the concept of tipping points (Lenton et al. 2008), in part due to the widespread
sociological use of the concept introduced by Gladwell (2000).
A major example of a link between climate change and catastrophe theory is what
Thual and McWilliams (1992) have called „the catastrophe structure of thermohaline convection”. Oceanographers have produced a large literature about the
possibility that anthropogenic global warming may lead to so much freshwater
flowing into the North Atlantic that an important pattern of ocean currents would
break down (figure 4). This pattern, known as the Atlantic thermohaline circulation (THC for short) is not identical to the gulf stream, but has a similar warming
effect on the surrounding regions – its breakdown could compensate or over-compensate the effects of global warming in those regions.
12
Figure 5: Climate risk assessment according to Parry et al.
(2001, p. 182).
Purple: coastal flooding, red:
hunger, yellow: malaria, blue:
water shortage.
A less mathematical, but equally influential assessment of the idea that there
might be an important non-linear relation between global mean temperature and
climate impacts was developed in the study „millions at risk“ (Parry et al. 2001). It
provided an estimate of how many people would be exposed to various risks from
climate change (figure 5). Although the probabilities involved are less than clear,
a claim of a strong non-linear effect is made for water shortages – and it seems
to justify a limit not even of 2, but of 1.5° C („seems“: as Tol, 2007, has noticed,
the effect is based on a first approximation that squarely neglects the capacity of
people to respond to challenges).
Hare (2003) worked in a similar spirit, concluding: “Above 2° C the risks increase very substantially involving potentially large extinctions or even ecosystem
collapses, major increases in hunger and water shortage risks as well as socioeconomic damages, particularly in developing countries” (p.89). The German Advisory Council on Global Change (WBGU 2003) combined its earlier arguments
(WBGU 1995 and 1997) with those of Parry et al. (2001) and Hare (2003) to
reinforce its support of the 2° limit.
13
In 2005, a worldwide effort to bring together decision makers and scholars led
to the so-called International Climate Change Taskforce recommending that a
‘‘long-term objective be established to prevent global average temperature from
rising more than 2° C (3.6° F) above the pre-industrial level’’ (ICCF, 2005) on the
basis of the arguments advanced by Parry et al. (2001) and WBGU (2003).
The Cost-Benefit View
14
In 1996, Nobel prize winner Ken Arrow and an eminent group of economists
and policy analysts published a paper in Science magazine (Arrow et al. 1996)
arguing that sound environmental policy – and sound risk management in other
fields as well – should systematically rely on cost-benefit analysis (CBA). This line
of thinking assumes that different policy options can be evaluated by associating
monetary measures of aggregate costs and aggregate benefits to policy variables,
and it requires policy to maximize the difference that results if one subtracts the
cost number from the benefits number. One of the most fundamental results of
contemporary economics then shows that a necessary condition of optimal decisions is that its marginal costs must be equivalent to its marginal benefits. CBA starts
with monetary effects, translates non-monetary effects (including uncertainties)
into monetary ones so that the two can be added and subtracted, somehow forms
a weighted average of the different preferences held by different people, and finally assumes that there is only one optimal policy.
3.0
Base
2.5
Optimal
E90
2.0
2 x CO2
T < 2.5 deg C
1.5
1.0
0.5
Figure 6: Searching for optimal climate change (Nordhaus and Boyer 2000, p.140).
0.0
1995
2005
2015
2025
2035
2045
2055
2065
2075
2085
2095
2105
In the case of climate policy, this requires an analysis of how much a small change
of policy changes the aggregate costs and benefits one associates with them. This
is what Nordhaus had in his mind all the time, and therefore he moved from his
15
first intuition of a critical limit towards the study of optimal temperature trajectories. As figure 6 shows, this led him to consider a trajectory as optimal that would
go beyond 2° towards the end of the 21st century – and would keep increasing
thereafter.
Although several arguments have been advanced against the use of CBA for climate policy (e.g. Baer and Spash, 2008), and Arrow himself had once proved a
major theorem according to which no meaningful aggregation of given preferences is possible in many cases (Arrow 1950), the cost-benefit approach profoundly
changed the climate policy debate.
Some proponents of the 2° limit reacted by suggesting that this limit did in fact
meet the criterion of cost-benefit analysis. In 2005, the Council of the European
Union reiterated its previous decision: “On the basis of the 2nd Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPPC) the EU Council of Ministers stated in 1996 that it ’believes that global average temperatures
should not exceed 2 ºC above pre-industrial level’ ” (CEU 2005, p. 3). It then went
on to claim: “There is increasing scientific evidence that the benefits of limiting
the global average temperature increase to 2 °C outweigh the costs of abatement
policies (for detailed summaries see Annexes 1 and 2). If temperatures continue to
rise beyond 2 °C a more rapid and unexpected response of the climate becomes
more likely and irreversible catastrophic events may occur” (CEU 2005, p.4).
Quoting the relevant chapter of the IPCC Second Assessment Report (Pearce et
al. 1996) the Council addressed the benefits of its proposed climate policy by assessing the order of magnitude of the damages that it can avoid: „a 2.5°C rise in
global temperature could cost as much as 1.5 to 2.0 % of global GDP in terms of
future damage“ (CEU 2005, p.14). It addressed the costs of the policy by quoting
relevant material from the more recent IPCC Third Assessment Report (Pachauri
et al. 2001, p.61) trying to assess a whole range of mitigation policies: „on average,
over the period 1990 to 2100, world GDP growth would be slowed by 0.003% per
year; the maximum reduction (to reach a very ambitious target in a high growth
scenario) was 0.06% per year“ (CEU 2005, p. 15).
If a 2.5° C temperature rise leads to a 2% loss of GDP in 2100, then a 2° limit
may lead to a 1.5% loss, so that marginal benefits would be 0.5% of GDP in 2100.
If on the other hand a 2.5° limit leads to a reduction of annual growth by 0.003%,
then a 2° limit may lead to a reduction of annual growth by 0.0006%, and so to
marginal costs of 0.07% of GDP in 2100. This, however would imply that a 2°
limit is way to loose, and the optimal policy would be to aim for 1 or even 0.5°.
Things look different if one introduces discounting (which CEU 2005 does not)
16
and makes additional assumptions about the temporal distribution of costs and
benefits – but then Nordhaus’ results become plausible again. The least one can
say is that the figures CEU (2005) quotes – somewhat haphazardly, but correctly
– from IPCC hardly support the 2° limit it advocates.
The most comprehensive attempt to propose a cost-benefit analysis justifying a
temperature trajectory somewhat close to the 2° limit has been the one by Stern
(2007). Discussing the huge literature commenting the Stern review lies beyond
the scope of this paper (for some related arguments see Jaeger, Schellnhuber and
Brovkin, 2008), our concern here is its relation to the 2° limit. The review advocates stabilizing atmospheric concentration of greenhouse gases at about 550ppm
of CO2 equivalent. As mentioned above, there was a time when this was considered to be roughly equivalent to the 2° limit. Meanwhile, however, a series of
studies has shown that it implies a considerably higher expected value for temperature (Meinshausen et al. 2009).
As is well known, the Stern Review claims that the benefits of its target are in the
range of 5-20% of GDP per year, while the costs are around 1%. What really
matters, however, are marginal costs and marginal benefits. Figure 7 illustrates
this point. Assume with Stern that a limit of about 3° C would lead to expected costs of about 1% of GDP per year while avoiding anthropogenic climate
change would avoid expected benefits of about 15% of GDP per year. Suppose
that business as usual would lead to 5° C of warming and that returning to preindustrial CO2-concentrations over a century would cost somewhat more than
10% a year (a conservative estimate compared with the cost estimates for stopping
CO2-emissions and removing CO2 from the atmosphere suggested e.g. by Keith,
Ha-Duong, Stolaroff 2006, and Hansen et al. 2008). Then at any temperature
benefits exceed costs, trivially also at the one implied by Stern. There is an optimal
limit, though, and in this case it sits at 2.1° C.
17
Figure 7: The relevance of
marginal costs and benefits.
Percent_GDP means average
GDP loss (purple) or gain
(blue) per year.
blue: benefits; purple: costs;
tangents: marginal costs and
benefits.
The numbers have been chosen for illustrative purpose.
Even if one accepts all of Stern’s numbers, however, functions for costs and benefits are not defined, and so no optimal target for climate policy can be derived
from his review. His achievement is to have helped convince opinion leaders and
decision makers worldwide that rapid action on climate change would be a good
thing – not to have provided a cost-benefit analysis for a particular stabilization
goal.
A Descent into the Maelström
18
In order to develop the focal point view to be discussed below, it is important to
reflect on the image of a climate catastrophe. In his story about surviving the
horror of the maelström, Edgar Allan Poe (1841) praises the willingness to observe and analyse what looks like the ultimate disaster. With regard to the risk of
a thermohaline catastrophe, this has been tried by Kuhlbrodt et al. (2009). Two
findings stand out.
First, experts that were asked to provide their subjective probability of a THC
breakdown this century gave numbers between 0 and 80%, and computer simulations suggest that a breakdown can be avoided if global mean temperature does
not increase by more than 2.5° Celsius. For larger increases, it would be unreasonable to rule out a breakdown.
Second, socio-economic impacts of a THC breakdown seem to be much smaller
than suggested by the word catastrophe.
1.
About fishery, where the impact would be greatest: „Since fishery ac
counts for about 2% of the Norwegian gross national product and 6% of the exports, economic losses from unprofitable cod fishery are within the usual macro-economical fluctuations and hence do not appear to be serious“ (no page numbers given in online first publication).
2.
Agriculture: „Overall, according to our simulations, the effect of reduced global warming and additional precipitation in some parts of Europe due to a THC breakdown could be positive because of the increased potential profits from agriculture.“
3.
Sea level rise (to be expected from a THC breakdown): „an additional SLR of 50 cm by the 2080s would cause costs of 670 million USD/year for Europe as a whole (in prices of 1995). These costs are small in terms of the gross national product.“
4.
Conceivable effects of a THC breakdown on weather patterns in the Southern hemisphere are mentioned, but not analysed by Kuhlbrodt et al. (2009). As for non-monetary impacts like the threats posed by climatic change to the beauty of coral reefs, in the case of a THC breakdown they are hardly prominent.
This assessment suggests that catastrophe theory is useful to study THC dynamics,
but that this dynamics does not provide the kind of tipping point that might justify
the 2° limit.
Hansen et al. (2008), however, claim that a significantly lower limit is in fact war-
19
ranted because of a different kind of catastrophe: „Continued growth of greenhouse gas emissions, for just another decade, practically eliminates the possibility
of near-term return of atmospheric composition beneath the tipping level for
catastrophic effects“ (p.17 in open access preprint).
(a)
CO2
(ppm)
CO2, CH4 and Sea Level
CH4 SL
(ppb) (m)
CO2
CH4
Sea Level
300
700
0
250
500
200
800
600
500
(b)
1
400
300
200
100
0
200
100
0
-100
Climate Forcing
Surface Albedo
Greenhouse Gases
0
F (W/m2)
700
300
-50
-1
-2
-3
-4
800
700
600
400
300
Temperature Change
T (°C)
(c)
500
800
700
600
500
400
300
200
100
0
Time (ky BP)
Several findings deserve special attention (see figure 8 and Hansen et al. 2008):
1.
During the past 800.000 years, global mean temperature has never been more than 3° warmer than today, and it has nearly always been conside-
rably lower (up to 5° less) than today. Over the same period, CO2-con-
centration has never been higher than 300ppm.
2.
Sea level has fluctuated with temperature at a rate of about 20m per degree Celsius. Changes of about hundred meters have happened several times in a time-span of less than ten thousand years.
Figure 8: Long-term estimates of the variation of temperature, seal level, and further
variables (Hansen et al. 2008,
Supplementary Material, p.
xvi).
20
3.
2° of global warming may lead to sea level rise of more than 30m over the next millennia.
Before this background, Hansen et al. (2008) claim: „If humanity wishes to preserve a planet similar to that on which civilization developed and to which life on
Earth is adapted, paleoclimate evidence and ongoing climate change suggest that
CO2 will need to be reduced from its current 385 ppm to at most 350 ppm, but
likely less than that“ (p.1 in open access preprint).
TAR (2001) Reasons for Concern
Large
Increase
Negative
for Most
Regions
Net
Negative
in All
Metries
Higher
Risks to
Many
Large
Increase
Negative
for Most
Regions
4
Net
Negative
in All
Metries
Higher
5
4
3
3
Future
Figure 9: Impacts of global
warming – an attempt at
synthesis (Smith et al. 2009 p.
4134).
Risks to
Some
Increase
Negative
for Some
Regions;
Positive
for
Others
Positive
or
Negative
Market
Impacts;
Majority
of People
Adversely
Affected
2
1
Very
Low
0
Risks to
Some
Increase
Negative
for Some
Regions;
Positive
for
Others
Positive
or
Negative
Market
Impacts;
Majority
of People
Adversely
Affected
2
1
Very
Low
0
Past
-0.6
-0.6
Risks to
Risk of Distribution Aggregate Risk of
Risks to
Risk of Distribution Aggregate Risk of
Unique
Large
Unique
Large
Extreme of Impacts Impacts
Extreme of Impacts Impacts
and
Scale
and
Scale
Weather
Weather
Threatened Events
Discontinuities Threatened Events
Discontinuities
Systems
Systems
That statement needs to be seen in the context of Rohling et al. (2009), who claim:
„Our results imply that even stabilization at today’s CO2 levels may cause sealevel rise over several millennia that by far exceeds existing long-term projections“
(p. 500). More specifically, they argue that current greenhouse gas concentrations
already imply a sea-level rise of about 25m. Taken at face value, the Hansen argument then does not justify 350, but 280ppm.
Compared with these stern warnings, the famous „burning embers“ graph (figure
9) looks like an innocuous exercise. Still, three key facts must not be overlooked.
First, science as we know it is an on-going process of inquiry – in a decade or a
century the claims by Hansen or Rohling may be superseded by other insights. Se-
Increase in Global Mean Temperature above circa 1990 (°C)
Risks to
Many
Updated Reasons for Concern
5
21
cond, the processes they discuss happen on time scales of centuries and millennia,
not decades and years. And third, it is impossible to know what technological and
social skills relevant for climate policy humans will have a few centuries from now.
Investigating the maelström of oceanic catastrophes does not settle the debate
about the 2° limit. The THC assessment suggests a higher limit, the sea-level
argument a lower one. Again, the burning embers give a whole menu of more or
less plausible limits. Nor does cost-benefit analysis provide a convincing closure
to the debate, as we have seen. So what are we to make of the „scientific view“
recognized by the EU in 1995 and by the G8 in summer 2009?
Perhaps we should ponder Schellnhuber’s (2008) description of the „burning embers diagram“ as providing „a direct scientific way to gauge the political target of
limiting global mean temperature (GMT) rise to less than 2°C“ (p. 14239, his emphasis). It seems that for decades European politicians – and more recently many
of their partners from all over the world – have tried to orient their decisions on a
guideline they perceived as expressing a scientific view, while scientists – who did
introduce the 2° limit into the climate debate – treat that guideline as a political
issue.
22
The Art of Inquiry
It is surprising how well a statement Wittgenstein (1953) made long ago about
the psychological research of his times fits important aspects of contemporary
research on climate change: „there are experimental methods and conceptual
confusion [...] The existence of the experimental method makes us think we have
the means of solving the problems which trouble us; though problem and method
pass one another by” (p. 232).
So where might we have entangled ourselves in conceptual confusion? A good
point to start looking for an answer is one of the most famous paragraphs in the
“Treatise of Human Nature”, offered to the public in 1740 by David Hume. He
there distinguishes between “is-sentences” and “ought-sentences” and criticizes
lines of argument that start with the former only and end with the latter only: “In
every system of morality, which I have hitherto met with, I have always remark‘d,
that the author proceeds for some time in the ordinary ways of reasoning, and
establishes the being of a God, or makes observations concerning human affairs;
when of a sudden I am surpriz‘d to find, that instead of the usual copulations of
propositions, is, and is not, I meet with no proposition that is not connected with
an ought, or an ought not. This change is imperceptible; but is however, of the last
consequence. For as this ought, or ought not, expresses some new relation or affirmation, ‚tis necessary that it shou‘d be observ‘d and explain‘d; and at the same
time that a reason should be given; for what seems altogether inconceivable, how
this new relation can be a deduction from others, which are entirely different from
it.” (Hume, 1740, 3.1.1.27)
Hume’s argument has been used again and again to form an image of science as
studying facts, not values. In the words of a philosopher who helped shaping this
image like few others: “The grounds on which scientific hypotheses are accepted
or rejected are provided by empirical evidence, which may include observational
findings as well as previously established laws and theories, but surely no value
judgments” (Hempel 1965, 91).
It is this image that leads Michael Oppenheimer in his thoughtful investigation
about “Defining dangerous anthropogenic interference: the role of science, the limits of science“ to ask: “Where does science end and value judgment begin?” (Oppenheimer 2005, p. 1400.) Or, as Schneider and Lane (2006, p.14, their emphasis)
put it: „it is a common view of most natural and social scientists that it is not the
direct role of the scientific community to define what ‚dangerous’ means. Rather,
it is ultimately a political question because it depends on value judgments“. And it
is the same image that Moss (1995) presupposes in his comment on a workshop in
which IPCC tried to address the question of what might constitute dangerous in-
23
terference with the climate system. That comment was entitled: „Avoiding ‘dangerous’ interference in the climate system: The roles of values, science and policy“,
and the image is clear: science deals with facts, values are for policy.
There is wisdom in this image. If scientists give in to the temptation of trying to
impose their views on a particular policy question they risk to deprive the decision
process of important insights by other people – and to deprive non-scientists of
the opportunity to shape their own destiny.
And there is wisdom in the distinction between describing a situation without
suggesting any particular course of action about it and expressing a call for action
with regard to some situation. The point of Poe’s tale of the maelström is precisely that sometimes it is important not to give in to what seems to be a compelling emotion – shock and panic in the face of the maelström, or even of climate
change – but to spend some time trying to describe and understand the situation
in order to discover new possibilities for action.
But what could be taken from Hume as a helpful distinction between a description-oriented and an action-oriented use of words has gradually become a harmful
dichotomy. In Hume’s own words, “This change is imperceptible; but is however,
of the last consequence.” If we scholars claim that our quest for reliable knowledge is possible only because we restrict ourselves to “pure” facts, leaving value
judgments aside, we implicitly suggest that the quest for reliable knowledge about
ethical matters is illusory. And by then declaring that value judgments are a matter
for policy, we foster the risk that policy becomes a meaningless power struggle,
where debates do not generate insights but reproduce endless battles between various forms of fundamentalism and more or less sophisticated forms of cynicism.
As many of us nevertheless do feel that climate change requires action, we tend to
come up with presumed facts that do imply the kind of action we deem appropriate. So we use catastrophe talk to share our sense of urgency with decision makers
and the wider public, or we optimize cost-benefit differences to share our sense
of responsibility with the same audiences. And we are surprised and irritated that
even among scholars we cannot reach an agreement about what should be done.
No wonder “society” does not do what we think it should be doing – our thoughts
are fraught with conceptual confusion that our familiar methods cannot alleviate.
“A picture held us captive. And we could not get outside it, for it lay in our language and language seemed to repeat it to us inexorably” (Wittgenstein 1953, p. 115).
Blending the traditions of pragmatist philosophy and logical analysis, recent work
by philosophers like Putnam (2004) can help us to listen to our language more
24
carefully. While there is a rich tradition of arguments to the effect that scientific
inquiry is always embedded in normative contexts, we are at best seeing the first
seeds of a global civilization that will be capable to effectively assess practical problems without the need to split them in a descriptive and a normative component.
The climate challenge is a case in point.
To gain a new view of the fact/value dichotomy, it is useful to notice that our use
of words sometimes is mainly descriptive, sometimes mainly normative, but that
in general it has both of these aspects, and many more. To say that a friend is sick
describes a situation, but somebody who does not realize what kinds of action
are warranted in such a situation does not understand the description. The same
is true for the statement that an explanation is misleading, or that an exercise is
healthy. The fact/value dichotomy collapses and gives way to a rich landscape of
language games, including describing a work of art, criticising a mathematical
theorem, guessing future sea level, sharing a sense of gratitude, coordinating a
team effort, etc.
Trying to distil a system of purely descriptive sentences out of human language is
a futile exercise, as is the attempt to concoct a system of purely normative ones.
This insight creates the space for policy to evolve as the – sometimes painful,
sometimes exhilarating – process of inquiry of a political community. The long
history of the still unwritten British constitution is a case in point, as is the history
of race relations in the U.S. In the coming decades, tackling climate change will
become an important element in inquiries very different communities are engaged in – nations, churches, academic networks, professional associations, ethnic
groups, and more. The fact-value dichotomy was quite essential for the historical
triumph of Western civilization, a reason for its amazing strength, but also for its
unprecedented destructive potential.
Letting go of this dichotomy in favor of a culture of pluralistic debate may foster
the global dialogue required to meet the challenge of climate change. Inquiries
about a value judgment are not fundamentally different from inquiries about a
judgment of fact or about any of the normal judgments with both descriptive and
normative connotations: The relevant judgment is expressed in some language,
and that language comes with statements nobody has doubts about. Starting from
these statements, somebody advances a claim creating bridges of similarity leading towards the judgment under investigation. The bridges may be accepted or
contested by others, tentative actions relying on them may be undertaken. If the
actions are successful and few doubts are expressed, the bridges become well established, and in the course of time the judgment at their other end gets accepted.
25
In the process, other judgments may be put in doubt, including some that were
taken for granted at the beginning. But if everything were put in doubt simultaneously, there would be no language anymore – as would be the case if all questions
had been answered.
What then can and should scientists say about the 2° limit?
1.
First, we can acknowledge that the limit was – sometimes inadvertently, sometimes consciously – introduced into the policy debate not by policy makers but by some of us.
2.
Second, we can make it clear that there is nothing wrong with that: making suggestions as to how to address problems we know something about is one of our tasks as researchers. The fact that IPCC as an orga-
nization operates under the constraint of being policy neutral does not mean that the language used by IPCC could be sanitized of all norma-
tive aspects, or that science as such should be policy neutral. It only means that IPCC is not allowed by the governments financing it to tell those governments what they have to do.
3.
Third, and here it becomes a bit more difficult, we can make explicit why some of us think the 2° limit is a valuable proposal, and why others dis-
agree in various ways (this is one of the purposes of the present paper).
4.
Finally, to those that complain because we do not offer a single final truth, we can say that the very variety of suggestions coming from different researchers is a major resource for society at large. And we can say that an answer to the climate challenge that has been elaborated jointly by the plurality of relevant actors is likely to lead to better results than any scheme designed by scientists alone.
26
The ‘Focal Point’ View
The plurality of relevant actors not only makes it undesirable to restrict an inquiry
about the 2° limit to scientific communities alone. It also offers a clue as to why
that particular limit has gradually gained acceptance and why this may be useful.
Consider the following classical problem from game theory. A dozen people from
all over the world who do not know each other are told that next Saturday they
will all be flown to Paris. If they manage to meet Sunday at noon, each one of
them gets a million dollars and a business ticket back; if not, they get nothing and
must find their own way home. What would you do in that situation?
The chances that the group will meet under the Eiffel tower are remarkably high.
In Paris, the Eiffel tower is what game theorists call a focal point. The concept
was introduced by Schelling (1960, see also Sugden 1995) and has given origin
to a rich literature. Problems with a similar structure are known as coordination games, their solutions as coordination equilibria. Without a focal point, such
problems are often hard to solve, because there are many possible coordination
equilibria and the players do not have a plausible strategy to select one of them.
As a less fanciful coordination game consider speed limits in car traffic, e.g. the 50
km/h limit in many European cities. Why is it 50 and not 47 or 53? The reason is
obvious: 50 is a focal point. And why is there a uniform limit and not several limits
differentiated by the skills of drivers, the power of cars, etc.? Again the reason is
obvious: with a uniform limit, there will be less accidents. And why is the limit 50
and not 10 or 100? The lower number would make car traffic meaningless, the upper one would make it too dangerous. But there is no need to decide about upper
and lower bounds for speed limits, it is sufficient to pick one such limit, implement
it, and if the need arises learn from experiences with it. Finally, what is the role of
scientists in decisions about speed limits? They may produce statistics of different
kinds of accidents with different speed limits, develop theories about how various
features of traffic change with various limits and other circumstances, they may sit
on committees proposing speed limits, and their voices may be heard in debates
about them.
Through several decades of intuitions, criticism, struggles, insights, and guesses,
the 2° limit has become a focal point of the climate debate. The reasoning that
it marks the upper range of climatological conditions humankind has ever experienced in its history gives salience to the number 2. And 2 is a much better focal
point than, say, 1.5, or than a combination with temperature increase per decade
or further indicators. Moreover, temperature has much stronger intuitive appeal
than, say, ppm of some molecule equivalents. Finally, and this may be the most
important point at the present time, the 2° limit is a strong call for action, and it
27
is understood as such.
None of this is a compelling reason that would lead to the 2° limit as the only
possible focal point. 3 or 2° Fahrenheit might have worked as well, and 2° may still
be superseded by some other focal point. But for the time being, the key question
is whether or not there is a focal point motivating action on climate change now.
Granted, the 2° limit does not describe individual actions the way a speed limit
does. But it implies a collective narrative involving much more effective actions
than the world has witnessed so far. The many declarations of intent abounding in
climate policy can remind one of the “old joke about a music lover who would do
anything to play the violin—except practice” (The Economist, 2009). The 2° limit
provides a focus that can motivate and structure practical steps by a multitude of
agents, including governments, but by no means limited to governments. It may
well take a whole century of great creativity and perseverance to secure a 2° limit.
The only way to do so will be to reach near-zero emissions. Otherwise concentrations will keep increasing for millennia until the oceans will have absorbed the
bulk of man-made CO2 (Matthews and Caldeira, 2008).
This also means that if greenhouse gas emissions should not be reduced fast
enough to stay below the 2° limit, it will be necessary to remove CO2 from the air
artificially. Hansen et al. (2008) discuss various possibilities to do so, e.g. producing
biochar in agriculture and forestry or burning biofuels from marginal land in power plants and capturing the CO2. They estimate a cost of no more than 40 Euro
to remove a ton of CO2. In any case, the fact that we may well overshoot the 2°
limit – emphasised e.g. by Victor (2009) – is no argument against that limit, just
as the possibility of driving faster than a given speed limit is no argument against
the latter.
It is useful to have an estimate for the shortest time that may be necessary to reach
a state of near-zero anthropogenic emissions starting from today’s level of about 8
gt of carbon. As a preliminary illustration – not a proposal – consider the possibility of capturing CO2 from power plants. A high-end estimate of the pure investment costs required for that purpose is about 600.000 Euro per MW of electricity
produced (Kuuskraa 2007, p.17). This is net production, i.e. without the energy
needed for the CCS operation itself. Operating costs are not included, because
maximum deployment speed depends essentially on investment constraints. Total
energy use by humankind is currently in the order of 10.000 GW. To produce
half of it from fossil fuels with carbon captured would require investing about 3
trillion Euro. Spread over 10 years, this leads to annual investment of about 0.3
trillion Euro.
28
The point of this computation is not to advocate the technology considered, but
to get a benchmark on the time required for drastic emissions reductions. For this,
the required investment must be seen in relation to overall investments. Global
GDP is currently in the order of 50 trillion Euro, the global capital stock is about
150 trillion, global gross investment about 10 trillion, military expenditure a bit
more than 1 trillion. Under these conditions, increasing gross investment by 10%
is not economically prohibitive. A benchmark for phasing out coal and a sizeable
fraction of oil and gas, then, is just about a decade. 0.3 trillion per year to eliminate CO2-emissions from fossil fuel use in power plants then would still leave 0.7
trillion to expand renewables, increase energy efficiency and develop electric cars
and other transport systems. In ten years this amount of investment could bring
down emissions by at least 70%. The task grows the later it starts, however the
economic and technological resources available for the task grow as well. Two decades then are a reasonable benchmark for bringing down emissions to near zero
levels. Global deployment of renewables, a worldwide surge in energy efficiency
or really large-scale use of nuclear energy can hardly happen faster. But from
a purely economic and engineering point of view, two decades would probably
suffice.
A benchmark, however, is not a policy proposal. To say that it would be technically
and economically feasible to dismantle all nuclear weapons on Earth in about a
decade is probably true, but this does not mean that there is the slightest chance
of a nuclear weapons free world being reality by 2020. Still, such benchmarks are
important in order to understand where the real inertias come from.
Figure 10: A one-equilibrium
system.
29
The capacity of the market economy to absorb shocks and meet challenges is often underestimated. An instructive historical analogue is given by the switch of the
Detroit car factories from regular car production to the production of tanks, jeeps,
etc. during World War II. That switch was successfully completed within less than
a year, and without either reducing economic growth or accelerating inflation to
dangerous levels (Clive 1979). More recent example are known from information
technology: the spread of the internet, the introduction of cell phones in Africa,
and more.
Nowadays, there are about 4 billion people on Earth with the ability to perform
economically productive work in the setting of the global economy. Of these, no
more than 2 billion are actually engaged in doing so. This means that the world
economy has enormous spare capacity that can be tapped. The real problem is
how to do so.
The widespread view of the economy as a one-equilibrium system (figure 10) is
quite misleading here. This picture leads to the idea that addressing the climate
challenge requires a global authority that will move the incentive structure of the
world economy in such a way that it reaches the optimal path of greenhouse gas
emissions (figures 6 and 7). In figure 10 this is represented by the dashed line. The
larger the emissions cut, the larger the expected costs. And in order for the economy to incur these costs, a high carbon price must be established and maintained.
Figure 11: A multi-equilibrium
system.
30
But this picture only arises because of completely unwarranted assumptions that
do not become less misleading by being widespread. The Sonnenschein-MantelDebreu theorem well-known to mathematical economists (Saari 1995) shows how
even a model fulfilling all the far-fetched assumptions of general equilibrium theory – convexity of preferences and production sets, perfect competition, futures
markets for all goods and services – can have any number of equilibria.
So we should rather think in terms of a picture like figure 11, with some equilibria
having high emissions and other ones having low emissions. To move from a highemissions to a low-emission equilibrium rising carbon prices may be necessary or
at least helpful, after the transition their level may be higher or lower than before.
The basic pattern is that of a coordination game, and this is why the existence of
a focal point is so important. And the 2° limit is a focal point that can drive the
search process for a near-zero emissions equilibrium.
Once the world economy will move on a near-zero emissions path, further experience may show whether there is a need to look for another focal point. Perhaps
data and improved understanding will suggest that a still lower limit will be appropriate in order to avoid major sea level rise in the centuries to come, or perhaps
they will indicate that there are good reasons to set a less stringent limit. But in
order to gather such data and understanding, decades of experience with effective
climate policies will be necessary.
In the short run, even more important than experiences with the impacts of climate change on glaciers, oceans, and living beings will be experiences with the
impacts of climate policies on national economies. In the present world, no major
economy can be expected or for that matter forced to seriously curb emissions if
it fears that this will disrupt its economy. And it is simply naïve to imagine that
a coalition of nations would be willing to take that risk just because everybody
expects others to disrupt their economies, too. Fortunately, the multiple equilibria
structure of actual economies means that at least some nations can successfully reduce emissions even if their competitors do not do the same (Jochem et al., 2008,
have shown this with a detailed analysis for the German case). Only if some nations successfully assume that leadership role can the inertia that keeps the global
economy on its current high-emissions path be overcome.
Azar (2007) has made the important point that the abolition of slavery may be a
useful analogue for global climate policy. There, a combination of religious and
moral sensibilities (like those of the Quakers) with slave rebellions (like the one of
1791 in Haiti) lead to partial steps towards the abolition of slavery being undertaken in a haphazard way in various places. As the fear that this would undermine
31
the competitiveness of the leading regions and nations proved to be unfounded,
the abolitionist movement could succeed.
The abolition of slavery also highlights the risks that even the most well-intentioned efforts can generate. A social catastrophe like the American civil war is
nothing one should take lightly, even in the name of a great ideal like the abolition
of slavery. Reaching near-zero global emissions is certainly possible, but the risk
that the corresponding reconfiguration of the global economy will involve violent
social conflicts deserves more attention than it currently receives. The 2° limit,
then, is not only a focal point that can help trigger the transition to a low-emissions
equilibrium. It is also a call for responsible action in a world where the impacts of
a changing climate are by no means the only risks.
32
Conclusion
The 2° limit has emerged nearly by chance, and it has evolved in a somewhat contradictory fashion: policy makers have treated it as a scientific result, scientists as a
political issue. It has been presented as a threshold separating a domain of safety
from one of catastrophe, and as an optimal strategy balancing costs and benefits.
We propose to use it as a focal point in a coordination game, where a multitude
of actors need to find a new coordination equilibrium in the face of climate risks.
The key challenge then is to start showing by pioneering examples that nations,
cities, industries can reduce emissions so as to improve their economic condition,
and to let a global regime leading to near-zero emissions evolve as a complex,
multi-level system combining global agreements with regional and local initiatives.
In the course of time, the focal point may then be redefined on the basis of experience. But to gather the necessary experience, working towards a 2° limit provides
as good a focus as is currently needed.
34
References
Alley, R., Marotzke, J., Nordjaus, W., Overpeck, J., Peteet, D., Pielke, R., Pierrehumbert, R., Rhines, P., Stocker, T., Talley, L., Wallace, J. (2003) Abrupt Climate
Change. Science 299: 2005-2010.
Arrow, K. J. (1950) A Difficulty in the Concept of Social Welfare. Journal of Political Economy 58, 328–346.
Arrow, K. J., Cropper, M.L., Eads, G.C., Hahn, R.W., Lave, L.B., Noll, R.G.,
Portney, P.R., Russell, M., Schmalensee, R., Smith, V.K., Stavins, R.N. (1996) Is
there a role for benefit-cost analysis in environmental, health and safety regulation? Science 272, 221-222.
Azar, C. (2007) Bury the chains and the carbon dioxide. Review of ’Bury the
Chains: Prophets and Rebels in the Fight to Free an Empire’s Slaves’. Climatic
Change 85, 473-475.
Baer, P., Spash, C.L. (2008) Cost-Benefit Analysis of Climate Change: Stern Revisited. CSIRO Working Paper 2008-07.
Banuri, T, Barker, T., Bashmakov, I., Blok, K., Christensen, J., Davidson, O.,
Grubb, M., Halsnaes, K., Jepma, C., Jochem, E., Kauppi, P., Krankina, O. Krupnick, A., Kuijpers, L., Kverndokk, S., Markandya, A., Metz, B., Moomaw, W.,
Moreira, J.R., Morita T., Pan, J., Price, L., Richels R., Robinson, R., Sathaye, J.,
Swart, R., Tanaka, K., Taniguchi, T., Toth, R., Taylor, T., Weyant, J., and Pachauri, R. (2001) Technical Summary. Climate Change 2001: Mitigation. Contribution of Working Group III to the Third Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change. Metz, B., Davidson, O., Swart, R., Pan, J. (eds)
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
Castrigiano, D., Hayes, S. (2004) Catastrophe Theory. Boulder, Co., Westview
Press.
CEU (2005) Communication from the Commission to the Council, the European
Parliament, the European Economic and Social Committee and the Committee
of the Regions. Winning the Battle Against Global Climate Change. Brussels,
Commission of the European Communities.
Clive, A. (1979) State of War: Michigan in World War II. Ann Arbor, University
of Michigan Press.
35
Dessai , S., Adger, W.N., Hulme, M., Turnpenny, J., Köhler, J., Warren, R. (2004).
Defining and experiencing dangerous climate change. Climatic Change 64, 1125.
European Union Council (1996) Community strategy on climate change – Council
conclusions. In: 1939th Council Meeting Environment, Document Nr. 8518/96.
http://ue.eu.int/ueDocs/cms_Data/docs/pressData/en/envir/011a0006.htm
(10.7.2010).
G8 (2009) G8 Leaders Declaration: Responsible Leadership for a Sustainable Future, 8.-10.7.09, online: www.g8italia2009.it/G8/Home/Summit/G8-G8_Layout_locale-1199882116809_Atti.htm (14.7.2010).
Gladwell, M. (2000) The Tipping Point. Boston, Ma., Little, Brown and Company.
Hansen, J., Sato, M., Kharecha, P., Beerling, D., Berner, R., Masson-Delmotte,
V., Pagani, M., Raymo, M., Royer, D.L, Zachos, J.C. (2008) Target atmospheric
CO2: Where should humanity aim? Open Atmospheric Science Journal 2, 217231.
Hare, W. (2003) Assessment of Knowledge on Impacts of Climate Change - Contribution to the Specification of Art. 2 of the UNFCCC. Berlin, WBGU - German Advisory Council on Global Change.
Hempel, C. (1965) Aspects of Scientific Explanation and other Essays in the Philosophy of Science. New York, Free Press.
Hume, D. (1740 / 2000). A Treatise of Human Nature. Oxford, Clarendon Press.
ICCF (2005) Meeting the Climate Challenge - Recommendations of the International Climate Change Taskforce. London, Washington DC, Canberra, Institute
for Public Policy Research, Center for American Progress and Australia Institute.
Jaeger, C. C., Schellnhuber, H.J., Brovkin, V. (2008) Stern’s Review and Adam`s
Fallacy. Climatic Change 89, 207-218.
Jochem, E., Jaeger, C.C., Battaglini, A., Bradke, H., Cremer, C., Eichhammer, W.,
Förster, H., Haas, A., Henning, E., Idrissova, F., Kasper, B., Köhler, J., Köwener,
36
D., Krause, J., Lass, W., Lilliestam, J., Mannsbart, W., Meißner, F., Müller, M.,
Pflüger, B., Radgen, P., Ragwitz, M., Rauschen, M., Reitze, F., Riffeser, L., Saure,
K., Schade, W., Sensfuss, F., Toro, F., Walz, R., Wietschel, M. (2008) Investments
for a climate friendly Germany. Berlin, German Federal Ministry for the Environment, Nature Conservation and Nuclear Safety.
Jouzel, J.C., Lorius, J.R., Petit, C., Genthon, N.I., Barkov, V.M., Kotlyakov, V.M.,
Petrov, V.M. (1987). Vostok ice core: a continuous isotope temperature record over
the last climatic cycle. Nature 329, 403-408.
Keith, D., Ha-Duong, M., Stolaroff, J. (2006) Climate Strategy with CO2 Capture
from the Air. Climatic Change 74, 17-45.
Kuhlbrodt, T., Rahmstorf, S., Zickfeld, K., Vikebo, F.B., Sundby, S., Hofmann,
M. Link, P.M., Bondeau, A., Cramer, W., Jaeger, C.C. (2009) An Integrated Assessment of Changes in the Thermohaline Circulation. Climatic Change 96, 489537.
Kuuskra, V. (2007) A Program to Accelerate the Deployment of CO2 Capture
and Storage (CCS): Rationale, Objectives, and Costs. Washington, DC, Pew Center on Global Climate Change.
Lang, C., Leuenberger, M., Schwander, J., Johnsen, S. (1999) 16°C Rapid Temperature Variation in Central Greenland 70,000 Years Ago. Science 286, 934-937.
Lenton, T., Held, H., Kriegler, E., Hall, J., Lucht, W., Rahmstorf, S., Schellnhuber,
H.J. (2008) Tipping elements in the Earth`s climate system. PNAS 105, 1786-93.
Major Economies Forum (2009) Declaration of the Leaders. The Major Economies Forum on Energy and Climate, 9.7.09, online: http://www.whitehouse.gov/
the_press_office/Declaration-of-the-Leaders-the-Major-Economies-Forum-onEnergy-and-Climate (4.7.2010).
Matthews, H., Caldeira, K. (2008) Stabilizing climate requires near-zero emissions. Geophys. Res. Lett. 35(L04705).
Meinshausen, M., Meinshausen, N., Hare, W., Raper, S.C.B., Frieler, K., Knutti,
R., Frame, D.J., Allen, M.R. (2009). Greenhouse-gas emission targets for limiting
37
global warming to 2°C. Nature 458, 1158-1162.
Moss, R. (1995) Avoiding ‚dangerous‘ interference in the climate system: The roles
of values, science and policy. Global Environmental Change 5, 3-6.
Nordhaus, W.D. (1975) Can we control carbon dioxide? Laxenburg, IIASA.
Nordhaus, W.D. (1977) Strategies for the Control of Carbon Dioxide. Connecticut, Cowles Foundation for Research in Economics at Yale University.
Nordhaus, W.D. (1991) To slow or not to slow: the economics of the greenhouse
effect. Economic Journal 101 (1991) 920–937.
Nordhaus, W., Boyer, J. (2000) Warming the World: Economic Models of Global
Warming. Cambridge, MA, MIT Press.
Oppenheimer, M. (2005) Defining dangerous anthropogenic interference: the role
of science, the limits of science. Risk Analysis 25, 1399-407.
Oppenheimer, M., Alley, R.B. (2005) Ice Sheets, Global Warming, and Article 2
of the UNFCCC. Climatic Change 68, 257-267.
Oppenheimer, M. Petsonk, A. (2005) Article 2 of the UNFCCC: Historical Origins, Recent Interpretations. Climatic Change 73, 175–226.
Parry, M., Arnell, N., McMichael, T., Nicholls, R., Martens, P., Kovats, S.,
Matthew, L., Rosenweig, C., Iglesias, A., Fischer, G. (2001) Millions at risk: defining critical climate change threats and targets Global Environmental Change
11, 181-183.
Pearce, D. W., Achanta, A.N., Cline, W.R., Fankhauser, S., Pachauri, R., Tol, R.S.J.,
Vellinga, P. (1996) The social costs of climate change: greenhouse damage and
the benefits of control. In: Bruce, J.P., Lee, H., Haites, E.F. (eds) Climate Change
1995: Economic and Social Dimensions of Climate Change — Contribution of
Working Group III to the Second Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental
Panel on Climate Change (chapter 6). Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
Poe, E.A. (1841 / 1966) A Descent into the Maelstrom. In: Complete Stories and
38
Poems of Edgar Allan Poe. New York, Doubleday.
Putnam, H. (2004) The Collapse of the Fact/Value Dichotomy and Other Essays.
Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press.
Rijsberman, F., Swart, R. (1990) Targets and Indicators of Climate Change. Report of Working Group II of the Advisory Group on Greenhouse Gases. Stockholm, Stockholm Environmental Institute.
Rohling, E., Grant, K., Bolshaw, M., Roberts, A, Siddall, M., Hemleben, C., Kucera, M. (2009) Antarctic temperature and global sea level closely coupled over
the past five glacial cycles. Nature Geoscience 2, 500-504.
Saari, D. (1995) Mathematical Complexity of Simple Economics. Notices of the
AMS 42: 222-230.
Schelling, T. (1960) The Strategy of Conflict. Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press.
Schellnhuber, H. J. (2009) Global warming: Stop worrying, start panicking? PNAS
105, 14239–14240.
Schellnhuber, H.J., Cramer, W., Nakicenovic, N. (eds) (2006) Avoiding Dangerous
Climate Change. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
Schneider, S.H. (2001) What is Dangerous Climate Change? Nature 411, 17-19.
Schneider, S. H., Lane, J. (2006) An overview of „dangerous“ climate change. In:
Schellnhuber, H.J., Cramer, W., Nakicenovic, N. (eds) Avoiding Dangerous Climate Change. Cambridge, UK, Cambridge University Press.
Smith, J. B., Schneider, S.H., Oppenheimer, M., Yohe, G.W., Hare, W., Mastrandrea, M.D., Patwardhan, A., Burton, I., Corfee-Morlot, J., Magadza, C.H.D.,
Füssel, H.-M., Pittock, A.B., Rahman, A., Suarez, A., van Ypersele, J.-P. (2009)
Assessing dangerous climate change through an update of the Intergovernmental
Panel on Climate Change (IPCC) ‘‘reasons for concern’’. PNAS 106, 4133-37.
Stern, N. (2007) The Economics of Climate Change: The Stern Review. Cam-
39
bridge University Press.
Sugden, R. (1995) Towards a theory of focal points. Economic Journal 105: 533–
550.
The Economist (2009) A modest step. World leaders aspire to limit climate change,
but they offer few details of how to do so. The Economist (July 10).
Thual, O., McWilliams, J. (1992) The catastrophe structure of thermohaline convection in a two-dimensional fluid model and a comparison with low-order box
models. Geophysical and Astrophysical Fluid Dynamics 64, 67-95.
Tol, R. (2007). Europe’s long-term climate target: A critical evaluation. Energy
Policy 35, 424-432.
UNFCCC (2010) Report of the Conference of the Parties on its fifteenth session,
held in Copenhagen from 7 to 19 December 2009. Addendum, part two: Action
taken by the Conference of the Parties at its fifteenth session, 30.3.2010, online:
http://unfccc.int/documentation/documents/advanced_search/items/3594.
php?rec=j&priref=600005735#beg (14.7.2010).
UNFCCC (1992) The United Nations Framework Convention on Climate
Change, online: unfccc.int/resource/docs/convkp/conveng.pdf (14.7.2010).
Victor, D. G. (2009). Global Warming: Why the 2 °C Goal is a Political Delusion.
Nature 459, 909.
WBGU (1995) Scenario for the derivation of global CO2 reduction targets and
implementation strategies. Statement on the occasion of the First Conference of
the Parties to the Framework Convention on Climate Change in Berlin. Bremerhaven, WBGU - German Advisory Council on Global Change.
WBGU (1997) Targets for Climate Protection 1997. A Statement for the Third
Conference of the Parties to the Framework Convention on Climate Change in
Kyoto. Bremerhaven, WBGU - German Advisory Council on Global Change.
WBGU (2003) Climate Protection Strategies for the 21st Century: Kyoto and Beyond. Berlin, WBGU - German Advisory Council on Global Change.
Weizsäcker, E.U. von, Lovins, A.B., Lovins, L.H. (1998). Factor Four. Doub-
40
ling Wealth, Halving Resource Use - A Report to the Club of Rome. London,
Earthscan.
Wittgenstein, L. (1953) Philosophical Investigations. London, Basil Blackwell.
ISBN: 978-3-941663-08-4
European Climate Forum e.V.
P.O. Box 600648 - D-14406 Potsdam – Germany
www.european-climate-forum.net