* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download File - Tallis English & Philosophy
J. Baird Callicott wikipedia , lookup
Role-taking theory wikipedia , lookup
Ethics of eating meat wikipedia , lookup
Utilitarianism wikipedia , lookup
Thomas Nagel wikipedia , lookup
Kantian ethics wikipedia , lookup
Euthyphro dilemma wikipedia , lookup
Ethics in religion wikipedia , lookup
Individualism wikipedia , lookup
Divine command theory wikipedia , lookup
Internalism and externalism wikipedia , lookup
Bernard Williams wikipedia , lookup
Moral psychology wikipedia , lookup
John McDowell wikipedia , lookup
Consequentialism wikipedia , lookup
The Moral Landscape wikipedia , lookup
Ethics of artificial intelligence wikipedia , lookup
The Sovereignty of Good wikipedia , lookup
Alasdair MacIntyre wikipedia , lookup
Lawrence Kohlberg wikipedia , lookup
Morality and religion wikipedia , lookup
Moral disengagement wikipedia , lookup
Lawrence Kohlberg's stages of moral development wikipedia , lookup
Morality throughout the Life Span wikipedia , lookup
Moral development wikipedia , lookup
Moral responsibility wikipedia , lookup
Ethical intuitionism wikipedia , lookup
Thomas Hill Green wikipedia , lookup
Moral relativism wikipedia , lookup
The denial of moral truth: Emotivism Or, the "hurrah/boo!" theory Where it fits in • A non-cognitivist theory: morality is non-propositional, and so can’t be known to be true or false. • If moral judgments aren’t true or false, we can’t reason about basic moral principles. • “X is good” simply means “Hurrah for X!” • so goodness and immorality are limited to our (societal?) preferences. – For example, the death penalty makes me feel nasty. – So it’s wrong Origins • popular in C18. • Hume defends (subjectivist?) emotivism: “Tis not contrary to reason to prefer the destruction of the whole world to the scratching of my finger” • Later in his life he defends a kind of Impartial Observer theory: what would we feel when faced with a moral choice? • Hence, Hume’s “Is/Ought Gap”, or “Fact/Value Distinction” – you can't go from a factual statement (an "is") to a moral one (an "ought"), as facts don’t motivate actions (he thinks) • C20 view – facts (primary qualities) give rise to reasons (secondary qualities) for us to act • Remember the primary/secondary quality distinction we worked on last summer? • Is/ought gap means that ‘sentiment’ or emotion is the only ground for our moral judgements – as it makes us act – Because it is the source of our feeling of right and wrong.. Modern emotivists • Emotivism defended C20 by A.J. Ayer on logical positivist grounds: Verification Principle… • Classic formulation of view in ch. 6 of ‘Language, Truth and Logic’ (1936) – ‘Stealing money is wrong‘…expresses no proposition which can be either true or false.’ It is as if I had written 'Stealing money!!' where the shape and thickness of the exclamation marks show…a special sort of moral disapproval.’ Ayer’s arguments for Emotivism: • To be meaningful, a proposition must be empirically verifiable or analytically true. – ‘My favourite trousers are Lycra’ (verifiable) – “Married people are partnered” (analytic) • A C20 restatement of ‘Hume’s Fork’ – if not ‘matter of fact’ or ‘relation of idea’, then meaningless. • Moral opinions – neither factually verifiable – Or reducible to tautologies – So are meaningless (as are religious, aesthetic, metaphysical claims) • E.g “There is a God”, “Tyler’s haircut is bitchin’”, “Terrorism is wrong”, ‘There are objects that exist without being perceived’. Ayer’s conclusions • Moral arguments are just expressions of feeling. • Ethical statements and moral judgements are emotive responses: they seek to arouse feelings or express pain. • So moral judgements are persuasive, but they are not factual. • They might look like they assert truth-claims (moral statements resemble declarative, testable statements)…but… • They assert an emotion, that’s all. Emotivism isn’t subjectivism • Mind! Emotivism isn’t subjectivism: • Emotivism: “X is good” means “Hurrah for X!” • Subjectivism: “X is good” – This means “I like X” – A verifiable proposition – hence T/F – hence meaningful as a psychological not ethical claim (according to Ayer) • We could test if you liked X… Why be an emotivist? Part 1 • Does away with worrying feeling that morality needs a more complex justification (i.e. complex Kantian/Utilitarian theories etc. • Simple yet explains a good deal (strength of our ethical feelings, their shared nature etc) • Offers clear criterion for sense vs. nonsense. • Sociological analyses do seem to show that goodness and immorality are limited to our preferences. • doesn’t appeal to mysterious entities (God, the transcendental…) that make morality mysterious • explains why we can’t define “good”, why we can’t prove moral beliefs… Why be an emotivist? Part 2 • explains how people disagree about morality, and why they agree • chimes with view that we can’t reason about basic moral principles and makes space for emotion to play a prominent role (as clearly it does) • we can reason about morality if we assume a shared system of values. • but we can’t establish the correctness of any system of values • Stresses importance of persuasive language and emotion in the expression of moral sentiment. Issues with emotivism Part 1 • The logical positivist argument for emotivism is flawed: in particular, the claim that any meaningful proposition is either verifiable or tautologous is self-contradictory, hence inconsistent (key example: ‘the claim that…’ is not itself verifiable or tautologous…) • Emotivism can’t explain unemotional moral judgments, which surely we do have? Indeed, cool and levelheaded moral assessment is something that we value. • We do reason about moral judgments. The claim that they are merely expressions of emotion seems odd (Ayer: here we are reasoning about the meaning of our moral terminology rather than its application) • Are our responses to atrocities like genocide, rape and murder just matters of feeling? Issues with emotivism Part 2 • Our moral feelings aren’t subjective or personal, necessarily. They are natural, and shared…common reactions to horrific crimes (e.g. the holocaust) suggests the possibility of a reasonable basis for moral behaviour. • reduces moral discussions to a shouting match if we can’t reason about basic moral principles. • Many uses of “good” and “bad” are difficult to translate into exclamations. – “Hurrah for good people!” – “If lying is bad, then getting your brother to lie is bad.” – “This is neutral (neither good nor bad).” • Is this a truth claim or an exclamation: “A view is better if it’s simpler and explains more”? We do use ethical claims evaluatively with a clear sense of their meaning!