* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download William Moran Ethics: Virtue Dr. Faulders Character It is often said
Lawrence Kohlberg wikipedia , lookup
Neeti Sastra wikipedia , lookup
Morality and religion wikipedia , lookup
Moral disengagement wikipedia , lookup
Lawrence Kohlberg's stages of moral development wikipedia , lookup
Ethical intuitionism wikipedia , lookup
Moral development wikipedia , lookup
Consequentialism wikipedia , lookup
Morality throughout the Life Span wikipedia , lookup
Ethics in religion wikipedia , lookup
School of Salamanca wikipedia , lookup
Moral relativism wikipedia , lookup
Moral responsibility wikipedia , lookup
Potentiality and actuality wikipedia , lookup
Thomas Hill Green wikipedia , lookup
Critique of Practical Reason wikipedia , lookup
Alasdair MacIntyre wikipedia , lookup
De (Chinese) wikipedia , lookup
Secular morality wikipedia , lookup
Aristotelian ethics wikipedia , lookup
William Moran Ethics: Virtue Dr. Faulders Character It is often said that a man is judged by his character. Martin Luther King fought for the day when a man be judged by his character and not the color of his skin. John Adams said “The people "have a right, an indisputable, unalienable, indefeasible, divine right to that most dreaded and envied kind of knowledge-- I mean of the character and conduct of their rulers”. And the Bible says;”By his inclinations a child is known, if his works be clean and right” ( KJV, Proverbs 20:11). The Oxford dictionary defines character as the mental and moral qualities distinctive to an individual. Simply put the character of a person is how he or she thinks and subsequently how they act in accordance with those thoughts. Aristotle emphasized the importance of developing excellence or virtue of character (Greek "ethikē aretē"), as the way to achieve what is finally more important, excellent activity (Greek energeia). As Aristotle argues in Book II of the Nicomachean Ethics, the man who possesses character excellence does the right thing, at the right time, and in the right way. According to its etymology the word virtue (Latin virtus) signifies manliness or courage. "Appelata est enim a viro virtus: viri autem propria maxime est fortitudo" ("The term virtue is from the word that signifies man; a man's chief quality is fortitude"; Cicero, "Tuscul.", I, xi, 18). Taken in its widest sense virtue means the excellence or perfection of a thing, just as vice, its contrary, denotes a defect or absence of perfection due to a thing. In its strictest meaning, however, as used by moral philosophers and theologians, it signifies a habit super-added to a faculty of the soul, disposing it to elicit with readiness acts conformable to our rational nature.(Catholic Encyclopedia, 472) In his book on Catholic theology titled Theology and Sanity, Frank Sheed says; “the soul has two functions one is the ability to love and the other is the intellect”. (8) Often overlooked, intellectual virtue can help lead us to correct moral judgments. Contrary to this is relying solely on the part of the soul that deals with feelings and love. Both parts need the other to properly guide the formation of the man with good character. Like many ethicists, Aristotle regards excellent activity as pleasurable for the man of virtue. For example, Aristotle thinks that the man whose appetites are in the correct order actually takes pleasure in acting moderately. Man finds in himself natural inclinations some of which care considered good and some of which poor. If a man has the natural inclination to be generous then this is not a virtue because it he is simply following his natural inclination. However if the same man has a natural inclination to be selfish and fights against this inclination and performs acts of charity then he is thought to be virtuous. Virtue is moving in the opposite direction of our natural inclinations. For that reason a rock unlike a man cannot go against its inclinations, and therefore must always fall to the ground when dropped. It cannot be trained, educated or convinced in any manner to not fall to the ground. Humans however, posses the unique ability to move away or towards inclinations for either good or bad reasons. Like any other craft we must learn to virtuous and this should start at a young age. If a child’s moral growth does not keep pace with his physical growth there may soon be no child. Could this explain why the most common age for suicide today is adolescence?...However to practice morality, we must first know it. To be men and women of virtue, not vice we must know what virtue and vice mean. (Peter Kreeft) Man can use his properly trained intellect to see what is true and use this knowledge to inform his thoughts and not rely on feelings. Feelings are indeed real and need not be discarded but they must not be the sole guide of our actions. For example: if I feel cold and it is the middle of summer with temperatures in the 90 degree range my feelings would indicate I may have an illness and I should seek medical attention. To ignore the feeling of cold in high temperatures would be negligent and most likely result in a more serious illness. Likewise if I have a feeling to act in a certain manner I need to evaluate that feeling to compare it to the reality around me. If I find in myself the feeling to have an ice-cream bar and have no means to acquire the ice-cream I may find a feeling to just take one, steal it. My natural inclination maybe to take the ice-cream but hopefully if I have developed the correct virtues I go against such an inclination. And so the man of character is the man who has developed his thoughts and actions to act in accordance with correct moral choices. Aristotle thought there to be two kinds of virtue intellectual and moral. The former we acquire through education and the latter through habit. Aristotle identifies ethical virtue as "a habit, disposed toward action by deliberate choice, being at the mean relative to us, and defined by reason as a prudent man would define it" (1107a). A crucial distinction exists between being virtuous and acting virtuously. To qualify as virtuous, one must not merely act virtuously, but also know he is acting virtuously, intend to do what he does for its own sake, and act with certainty and firmness (1105b). Acting virtuously, however, is the primary means to becoming virtuous. For, according to Aristotle, "virtues arise in us neither by nature nor contrary to nature; but by our nature we can receive them and perfect them by habituation" (1103a). Aristotle proposes three criteria to distinguish virtuous people from people who behave in the right way by accident: first, virtuous people know they are behaving in the right way; second, they choose to behave in the right way for the sake of being virtuous; and third, their behavior manifests itself as part of a fixed, virtuous disposition. In his attempt to explain the theory of moral virtue and, for that matter, the central goal, eudaimonia, Aristotle describes the important concept of finding middle ground in one’s life or, achieving a balance. In line with the theory of moral virtue Aristotle contends that to achieve these aims and reach eudaimonia, one of the most important lessons Aristotle teaches in the theory of moral virtue is strike a balance, or hit a mean between extremes in behavior, thought, and action. In the theory of moral virtue, Aristotle states that we must act knowingly and do the right thing because it is right, not because there is a personal stake in terms of the future possibility of pleasure or pain. In short, in this theory, what is morally right or wrong is something we understand in an intellectual sense and we apply this knowledge of moral behavior through our practice and habituation of moral virtues. Drawing from Aristotle St. Thomas Aquinas defined the cardinal virtues of human life as being prudence, temperance, justice, and fortitude. These virtues are revealed in nature and make up the foundations of natural law. To Aquinas, humanity naturally strives to achieve ends through the use of reason. Because of innate imperfection, these qualities are not always adhered to but are necessary for facilitating a rising standard of living. Without temperance, the present is indulged to rather than the future. In The Abolition of Man C.S. Lewis writes: “There is something which unites magic and applied science (technology) while separating them from the “wisdom” of earlier ages. For the wise men of old, the cardinal problem of human life was how to conform the soul to objective reality, and the solution was wisdom, self discipline, and virtue. For the modern, the cardinal problem is how to conform reality to the wishes of man, and the solution is a technique” Aristotle would probably be found standing on his head today as modernity has rapidly departed from his idea that we can move away from our natural inclinations towards a mean and develop virtue and therefore become men and women of character. Modernity attempting to comport to some form of morality rejects the idea either in whole or in part that we can or should move away from inclinations. It asks that we instead embrace our inclinations and then defines the man of character as man that is “good”. And good is left to each individual to define for themselves and therefore a constantly changing subjective idea, i.e. relativism. It subjugates men to that of the flames of fire reaching for the sky which are no better suited to fall to the ground then the rock dropped from our hand. Modern psychology and philosophy say we cannot ask a fire or a rock to violate its natural inclinations nor should we expect man to violate his own inclinations of selfishness, greed and the rest… Instead of asking man to wrestle with his inclinations we should be tolerant of each individual’s behavior. Where exactly the line of tolerance is drawn remains fuzzy and without any objective ideas of good and bad to draw from will remain that way despite the modern mans attempt at some scientific answer to our ethical questions. As G.K. Chesterton put it “tolerance is the virtue of the man without convictions”. The Catholic Encyclopedia volume 15 Robert Appleton company 1912 http://www.catholic.com/encyclopedia/virtue C.S. Lewis, The Abolition of Man ( New York: Macmillan, 1943), 87-88 Kreeft, Peter; Back to Virtue 1992 Ignatius Press, San Francisco Sheed Frank Theology and Sanity Ignatius press