* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download 1 Darrel Moellendorf Forthcoming in Dominic Roser and Jennifer
Climate change mitigation wikipedia , lookup
Global warming wikipedia , lookup
2009 United Nations Climate Change Conference wikipedia , lookup
Attribution of recent climate change wikipedia , lookup
German Climate Action Plan 2050 wikipedia , lookup
Climate engineering wikipedia , lookup
Climate change and agriculture wikipedia , lookup
Climate change feedback wikipedia , lookup
Climate change in Tuvalu wikipedia , lookup
Low-carbon economy wikipedia , lookup
Citizens' Climate Lobby wikipedia , lookup
Climate governance wikipedia , lookup
Solar radiation management wikipedia , lookup
Climate change adaptation wikipedia , lookup
Media coverage of global warming wikipedia , lookup
Economics of global warming wikipedia , lookup
Scientific opinion on climate change wikipedia , lookup
Climate change in the United States wikipedia , lookup
Effects of global warming on humans wikipedia , lookup
Paris Agreement wikipedia , lookup
Mitigation of global warming in Australia wikipedia , lookup
Carbon Pollution Reduction Scheme wikipedia , lookup
Effects of global warming on Australia wikipedia , lookup
Climate change, industry and society wikipedia , lookup
Public opinion on global warming wikipedia , lookup
Surveys of scientists' views on climate change wikipedia , lookup
Politics of global warming wikipedia , lookup
Economics of climate change mitigation wikipedia , lookup
Climate change and poverty wikipedia , lookup
1 Darrel Moellendorf Forthcoming in Dominic Roser and Jennifer Heyward eds. Climate Change and Non-Ideal Theory, Oxford University Press Taking UNFCCC Norms Seriously We are urgently in need of a comprehensive climate change mitigation treaty.1 This urgency affects the kind of moral guidance we should expect and can reasonably propose to others. To which norms and ideals can we, should we, appeal to guide the development of a comprehensive climate change treaty? Due to the decidedly non-ideal circumstances of climate change, perhaps the development of a nonideal theory guided by an ideal account of justice is appropriate. I shall argue that that is not the case. Insofar as nonideal theory is dependent on an account of ideal theory, which it serves, nonideal theory is ill-suited to offer practical moral guidance in light of the urgency of the circumstances. That claim does not entail, however, that climate change policy must be morally blind. Instead, I argue that the United Framework Convention on Climate Change (UNFCCC) is an important source of moral norms. There are very good normative and prudential reasons to take these norms seriously. The normative background provided by the treaty is a significant good for the collective effort of international cooperation. But also given the likely costs if the force of the background were to become significantly weakened, it is reasonable for each state to want to see the UNFCCC remain in force and therefore also not to erode it through non-compliance. The strongest moral reasons to comply with the norms of the UNFCCC, however, are the promissory obligation that a state assumes by ratifying the convention and the duty of fairness in an international system of energy use that appropriately responds to climate change. This chapter proceeds as follows. The next section discusses two reasons to believe that a comprehensive international climate change mitigation treaty is an urgent matter. The 2 second section argues that nonideal theory, at least as it presented in the monumental work of John Rawls, is impractical in light of the urgency of the matter. The third section rejects a view that holds that as a matter of feasibility the primary norm guiding the construction of a climate change treaty should be a measure of efficiency. The fourth section presents the arguments based on a promissory obligation and on fairness to respect the right to sustainable development, a fundamental norm of the UNFCCC. The fifth section considers and responds to a criticism of the right to sustainable development. And the final substantive section defends the view that proposals should adhere to UNFCCC norms because of both the collective good that the UNFCCC serves and the long-term interests of the member states. The upshot is a set of strong reasons to take the norms of the UNFCCC seriously. Urgency Mitigation policy seeks to reduce the negative effects of climate change. This is done by reducing emissions of greenhouse gasses, so as to halt the increase of their build up in the atmosphere. According to the current scientific consensus, by any reasonable judgment of the aims of mitigation we have very little time to get serious. In 2010 at the 16th Conference of the Parties of the UNFCCC, the member states decided to accept the mitigation goal of limiting mean surface temperature increase to 2°C above pre-industrial times. The most recent report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC) summarizes the current understanding of the relationship between temperature targets and cumulative carbon emissions. Because of the long residence time of CO2 in the atmosphere, atmospheric concentrations of it should be considered a function of total anthropogenic emissions of CO2 since the beginning of the Industrial Revolution. For any given temperature increase there is then a corresponding threshold of cumulative emissions. In order to have better than 66 percent chance of limiting warming to 2°C, total historical emissions of carbon would have to be limited to one trillion tons. (IPCC 2014) We have already used more than half of that 3 budget. At the time of writing, total emissions are 581 billion tons and climbing; and given current emissions, the date the trillionth ton will be emitted is Thursday, 15th March, 2040 (Trillionth Tonne). But we are not emitting at a steady rate. On the contrary, despite the reductions in industrialized countries, global emissions are increasing. Thus, the date at which we will emit the trillionth ton is coming ever closer. Consult http://trillionthtonne.org/ to see the date at the time at which you are reading. Whether the 2°C temperature limit is reasonable is a complicated moral judgment that depends upon the effects of the mitigation plan on the global poor, who have a reasonable claim to increase their energy use so as to pull themselves out of poverty (Moellendorf 2014). Poverty eradication requires increased energy use; and currently billions of people live in energy poverty. 1.4 people have no access to electricity, and 3 billion burn biomass on crude indoor stoves. The resulting indoor pollution is responsible for over 1.45 million premature deaths annually. More children under age 5 die from disease caused by indoor pollution than die from malaria and tuberculosis (IEA 2010). Any temperature goal will have to limit total cumulative emissions. The goal of 3°C requires limiting total carbon emission to around 1.5 trillion tons, the date for which is currently Friday, 28th July 2058, but moving closer. To achieve a 4°C limit we would need to cap all emissions at two trillion tons, which at the time of this writing would be Sunday 15th February 2071 (Trillionth Tonne). A credible mitigation plan would initiate a schedule of reductions in global emissions in order to push further into the future the deadline after which the economy must be carbon-free to maintain the goal. The need to implement a schedule of reductions in order to postpone the final transition to a carbon-free economy is urgent, all the more so if we assume the 2°C goal. The uncertainty of irreversible, and possibly cataclysmic, events adds to the urgency of the mitigation project. In the cold depths of the arctic waters a massive amount of methane in the form of hydrate crystals has settled. Methane is also stored in the frozen lakes and 4 tundra of the far north. Methane is 25 times more powerful than CO2 as a greenhouse gas. As a result of warming waters and thawing tundra it is being released into the atmosphere at unprecedented rates (Science Daily 2008). Due to the thermal inertia of the oceans this release will continue even after we arrest atmospheric warming. From ice core samples we know that atmospheric concentrations of methane are currently higher than they have been in 400,000 years. Sufficiently high levels of methane in the atmosphere would be capable of producing abrupt and irreversible (on any time scale that matters to us) climate change. Paleo-scientists believe that warming 635 million years ago resulted in methane hydrate release that warmed the planet abruptly and ended one of the most severe ice ages in the history of the planet (Kennedy 2008). The current release is a trickle in comparison to what might occur. The consequences of a massive release would be cataclysmic for human life. We are uncertain of the threat of such a massive a release. This is uncertainty in the technical sense, the understanding of which we owe to the pioneering work of economist Frank H. Knight (Knight 1921). It would be inaccurate to say that massive methane release is a low probability but high impact event because we cannot establish probabilities of its occurrence based on our understanding of the frequency of analogous cases. We have no understanding of sufficiently analogous cases. Uncertainty does not in general supply us with a reason to act. The mere fact that we do not know whether there will be a massive and devastating release of methane does not render urgent the mitigation project that might prevent it. More needs to be said about why uncertainty of the possibility of such an event establishes reason to believe the mitigation project is urgent. Rather than arguing in great detail, I will merely sketch an account of when uncertainty provides reason to take precautionary action. I have discussed this at greater length elsewhere (Moellendorf 2014). Four conditions are collectively sufficient to warrant 5 precautionary action against an outcome. (1) We have very good reasons to avoid the outcome. (2) The opportunity costs of avoidance seem minor in comparisons to the reasons that we have to avoid it. (3) The outcome’s occurrence is in general terms consistent with our understanding of how the world works, even though the details in the particular case are not well understood. And, (4) some of the causal antecedents of the outcome are in place. This last condition requires that our general understanding of the events that would produce the outcome include understanding of at least some of the causal antecedents. In conditions such as these it would be reasonable to take precautionary action to avoid the outcome. This is roughly the situation we are in with respect to methane release. Nonideal Theory The need to reform institutions governing the use of energy in order to mitigate climate change might suggest that the relevant moral considerations are a matter of nonideal theory since the point of nonideal theory is transitional. Discussion of nonideal theory entered into contemporary political philosophy through the work of John Rawls, who in A Theory of Justice holds that, ‘Nonideal theory…is worked out after an ideal conception of justice has been chosen.’ (Rawls 1999a, p. 216) He characterizes the priority of ideal theory to nonideal theory more clearly in The Law of Peoples. Nonideal theory asks how this long-term goal [of ideal theory] might be achieved, or worked toward, usually in gradual steps. It looks for policies and courses of action that are morally permissible and politically possible as well as likely to be effective. So, conceived, nonideal theory presupposes that ideal theory is already on hand. For until the ideal is identified, at least in outline—and that is all we should expect—nonideal theory lacks an objective, an aim, by references to which its queries can be answered (Rawls 1999b, p. 89-90). 6 The Rawlsian view then is that ideal theory provides the compass for nonideal theory. Nonideal theory judges the merits of any recommendation in terms of its moral permissibility, political possibility, and effectiveness in the transition to the ideally just arrangement.2 Effectively mitigating climate change requires international cooperation. An ideal theory of justice that might serve as the aim for such cooperation would state the claims of states in the international systems or the claims of the people of the world. But the aim of climate change mitigation would not be complete without an account of the claims of future generations for whose sake prior generations are mitigating. The first step then in formulating a Rawlsian nonideal theory of climate change justice would be the defense of accounts of ideal global and intergenerational justice. That’s a hugely ambitious task. Perhaps instead one could pursue the more modest goal of accounts of ideal global and intergenerational justice merely in relation to climate change. But given the far ranging effects of energy policy and climate change on social institutions and human well-being, it seems doubtful that one would get the ideal principles of climate change justice right without coordinating them in the broader context of the general ideal principles of global and intergenerational justice.3 Could the principles of ideal justice governing climate change could simply be settled first in isolation from all other considerations of ideal global and intergenerational justice and then be fit into broader accounts of global and intergenerational justice? Such an approach seems methodologically suspect and inconsistent with respect to how Rawls approaches justice. Generally, the methodological problem concerns the ability to know what the ideal theory of climate justice could be absent knowing what as a matter of ideal theory is owed to future generations and non-compatriots. Climate change institutions would have dramatic effects on people’s wellbeing far into the future and around the globe. There could be little confidence in the provisional claims of the ideal theory of justice in climate change, given the need to reconcile it with the larger ideal theory. 7 Rawls holds that some matters of justice have priority over others, such as for example the priority of liberty over distributive justice (Rawls 1999a, p. 214-220 & p. 474-480). Perhaps if principles of climate change justice had priority over other principles of justice, an ideal theory of climate change justice could be decided in isolation from the broader concerns of ideal global and intergenerational justice. The other principles would have to fit with the principles of climate change justice rather than seeking to make the latter fit into the broader ideal theory. To claim that an ideal theory of climate change has priority over other matters of global and intergenerational justice would require considerable argument; and given that the concerns of climate change on people’s wellbeing are similar to other considerations of justice, it seems doubtful that the claims of the ideal theory of climate change could have such priority. Nor on Rawlsian grounds does it seem likely that we can give a reasonably definitive account of the institutions that would satisfy ideal theory by considering only the effects of climate change on human wellbeing. According to Rawls it is the complete institutional background arrangement, not any one institution that is relevant to considering whether distributive principles of justice are satisfied. For example, neither the price system of the labour market, nor non-market institutions guaranteeing a ‘suitable minimum’ are judged in isolation when considering the justice of distributive shares (Rawls 1999a, p. 244-245). Rather, Rawls judges whether the difference principle is met only ‘once the whole family of policies is given.’ (Rawls 1999b, p. 161) An account of non-ideal justice for a particular institution should then be developed with an eye to a complete institutional arrangement. Nonideal theory decides that some institutions or policies should be prioritized over others because doing so is most permissible morally, most feasible politically, or most effective in moving towards the ideal. Hence, a society might decide to pursue fair equality of opportunity primarily by means of education policy rather than by means of constraining family decisions about the transfer of wealth and exposure to cultural events. That would be a matter of nonideal theory settling on the best course to realize a general ideal of fair equality 8 of opportunity in a permissible and effective manner. But what counts as permissible can only be determined in light of the rest of the ideal theory of justice, and presumably in the present example in light of the principle of equal basic liberties. Rawls believes that the claims of ideal intergenerational justice (just savings) must be satisfied before proceeding to distribute within a generation (Rawls 1999b, p. 160). This is based on the plausible thought that before a generation can justly divide up its resources it must have an account of which resources are its own and which must be invested for subsequent generations. That view acknowledges a priority of intergenerational claims over the intra-generational ones in an ideal theory of justice, but it does not license developing an account of principles of justice relating to climate change over principles of justice relating to other matters of intergenerational ideal theory. A nonideal theory of climate change justice cannot be formulated and justified without ideal theories of global and intergenerational justice ‘on hand.’ In the context of urgency this is a considerable liability for nonideal theory, which is fundamentally practical. Recall Rawls’s claim that nonideal theory, ‘looks for policies and courses of action that are morally permissible and politically possible as well as likely to be effective’ in the transition to the ideal. Generally accounts of the appropriate action to take in pursuit of an ideal will be at least as controversial as the accounts of the ideal. Indeed, accounts of nonideal theory are likely be more controversial than the accounts of ideal theory because they will possess whatever controversy there is about the ideal as well as controversy about how best to realize the ideal. Moreover, Rawls maintains that only reasonably ideal circumstances of a shared democratic tradition establish ‘the conditions of the possibility of a reasonable public basis for of justification on fundamental political questions.’ (Rawls 1993, p. xix ). Assuming our world fails to satisfy principles of ideal justice generally, and not merely regarding climate change, we should expect political debate about nonideal theory to be doubly and deeply controversial. 9 The accumulation of CO2 in the atmosphere and the release of methane from arctic stores will not wait until we have achieved agreement about matters of ideal justice and political processes have then settled debates about the appropriate means for achieving the ideal. These considerations suggest the lack of practicality of the project of developing a nonideal account of justice for climate change. However, one recent account of the importance of ideal theory stresses its role in orienting our moral judgments in nonideal circumstances: ‘To dive into nonideal theory without an ideal theory in hand is simply to dive blind, to allow irrational free rein to the mere conviction of injustice and to eagerness for change of any sort.’ (Simmons 2010, p. 34) If it is impractical to proceed by employing the team of ideal and nonideal theory to justify climate change mitigation, are we left only with giving “irrational free rein to the mere conviction of injustice”? Over the next four sections, I shall argue that we are not. International Paretianism Eric A. Posner and David Weisbach defend their account of International Paretianism with urgency explicitly in mind. Indeed, the urgency of mitigation leads them to reject treaty proposals that include international redistribution. ‘The greater the risk of catastrophe, the more important it is to choose the most effective climate policy. By tying the two issues [international redistribution and effective mitigation] together we risk hurting both goals.’ (Posner and Weisbach 2010, p. 74). This seems broadly consistent with my argument against nonideal theory in the previous section. But Posner and Weisbach’s recommendation to guide climate change mitigation policy by a measure of efficiency, International Paretianism, to the exclusion of other considerations is misguided. International Paretianism is a conceptual descendent of the efficiency criterion of Pareto optimality, according to which a distribution is more efficient than another if at least one person in the former is better off than in the latter and no one is worse off. International 10 Paretianism is satisfied if and only if all states ‘believe themselves better off by their lights as a result of the climate treaty.’ (Posner and Weisbach 2010, p. 6) This is both more demanding than Pareto optimality and less so. More demanding insofar as the improvement must be for all states, not merely one, but less demanding because it is belief- rather than fact-sensitive. States need not in fact be better off as a result of the climate treaty, in order for the treaty to satisfy the International Paretianism; they must merely believe themselves to be. This beliefsensitive concept is odd in discussions of efficiency since the requirement that an agreement satisfy International Paretianism does not ensure that resources will in fact be used in a manner that is less wasteful. Why then do Posner and Weisbach employ a belief-sensitive concept of efficiency? If states were assumed to have perfect knowledge there would be no misfit between belief and reality. But that seems an heroic assumption when we are forecasting about the future. The belief-sensitive concept seems less odd if the primary advantage of International Paretianism is supposed to be its feasibility. Because a climate change treaty is urgent, perhaps considerations of feasibility trump. A treaty that each state believes makes it better off is especially attractive because as they put it, ‘[H]istory supplies very few cases where states act against their own perceived interests in order to satisfy the moral claims of other states.’ (Posner and Weisbach 2010, p. 6) A requirement that a treaty be believed to be in the interests of all states better serves the demands of feasibility than a requirement that a treaty in fact be in the interests of all states, because if states invariably act only on their perceived interests then their actual interests are important only insofar as they are also perceived to be their interests. Perhaps we can reasonably assume that many states—at least those wealthy enough to employ a sophisticated team of researchers and negotiators—will more or less correctly identify the treaty proposals that are in their actual interests. Nonetheless, the important matter for feasibility is that states believe the treaty to be in their interests, regardless of whether it really is. 11 Whether a treaty would be thought to benefit a state depends both upon the baseline against which the situation of the state under treaty is compared and upon the measure of benefit. Posner and Weisbach claim that mitigation is a feasible goal because ‘the benefits from reducing emissions exceed the costs.’ (Posner and Weisbach 2010, p. 179) This suggests the baseline is some business-as-usual scenario, in other words the absence of a comprehensive mitigation treaty. And insofar as Posner and Weisbach construe their project as a welfarist one along the lines of standard economic analyses, they usually seem to be measuring benefits in terms of GDP, although they are not entirely clear about this (Posner and Weisbach 2010, p. 6).4 The idea seems to be then to be the plausible one that beyond a certain threshold of warming the combined effects of climatic perturbations and political disruptions are likely to produce high costs to the GDP of all states; and a climate change mitigation treaty can reduce these costs in aggregate. Diplomatic art should then be directed to persuading each state that there is a version of the distribution of the costs according to which it would fare better than under a plausible business-as-usual scenario. Perhaps the effort of persuasion is made easier if it is true for each state that it would fare better, but once again that is, strictly speaking, beside the point. Posner and Weisbach are not morally indifferent to global poverty. They believe it to be a serious injustice (Posner and Weisbach 2010, p. 74). But they reject additional or alternative constraints on a mitigation treaty, including one that would recognize the right to sustainable development. Poverty eradication, it should be noted, is an energy intensive project. By putting a price on carbon a mitigation treaty could increase energy costs to developing and least developed states such that eradication of energy poverty, and therefore poverty generally, would be slowed or reversed. It is not inconceivable that a poor state might believe it would be better off under a treaty that slowed or reversed poverty eradication if due to its vulnerability to climate change the business-as-usual scenario were exceedingly grim. 12 The lack of concern about energy poverty and a fair global system of energy consumption, however, undermine the moral credibility of Posner and Weisbach’s account. We can appreciate this by imaging two different treaty choice situations. Situation One: There is a choice between on the one hand a treaty mitigating change by satisfying International Paretianism and raising energy prices for millions of poor people in poor states5 and on the other hand a treaty mitigating climate change by satisfying International Paretianism and not raising energy prices in poor states where energy poverty is severe. Posner and Weisbach’s account is indifferent between these two alternatives. But that seems unreasonable. Moreover if, as Posner and Weisbach accept, global poverty is unjust, then an account should not be indifferent between alternatives that are identical except that one secures continued progress in eradicating poverty and the other does not. Situation Two: There is a choice between on the one hand a treaty mitigating climate change by satisfying International Paretianism and raising the energy prices for millions of people in poor states and on the other hand a treaty mitigating climate change, which only one state believes won’t advance its GDP, but which would not raise energy prices for millions of people in poor states. Posner and Weisbach’s account would rank the treaty satisfying International Paretianism over the one providing access to energy for the poor because there is a single state that believed the latter would not sufficiently promote its GDP. Hence, ensuring that a single state believes its GDP would be promoted is more important than providing energy access to millions of poor people according to their account. That also is unreasonable. The only available defense of these rankings is to appeal to the unique feasibility of International Paretianism and the overriding importance of feasibility in conditions of urgency. But an appeal to the unique feasibility of International Paretianism is implausible. In Situation Two the rejection of the alternative that would not raise energy prices in poor states 13 in order to ensure that one additional state has the choice that it believes would promote its GDP is not recommended on grounds of feasibility. Many of those states whose poor populations would be consigned to energy poverty by the second treaty would reject that treaty, and would do so on morally commendable grounds, indeed on grounds that Posner and Weisbach would otherwise endorse. In light of such a rejection it is implausible that considerations of feasibility recommend that choice. It would seem at least as feasible either to pursue diplomatic efforts to compel the single state to sign the treaty or to proceed with a multi-lateral treaty without that state. It is not entirely clear whether Posner and Weisbach take the feasibility of a treaty to be determined solely by beliefs about benefit measured in terms of GDP growth, but as a general matter it seems doubtful that a state’s self-interest should be so narrowly perceived. A broader conception of interest seems warranted insofar as states have other self-regarding reasons to sign treaties, including reputational reasons. In Situation Two, the single state that believes that the mitigation treaty (that would not raise energy prices in poor states) would not improve its GDP might nonetheless have sufficient reputational reasons to support the treaty. Or that same state might take itself to benefit from supporting the treaty if rejecting it would lead to countermeasures in the negotiation of other treaties or under other international regimes.6 Reputational and indirect effects suggest that a conception of benefit broader than mere GDP improvement is warranted. Moreover, state leaders may find themselves under pressure to respond to a citizenry that is motivated by moral reasons to accept a treaty that cannot be justified merely by appeal to self-regarding reasons.7 In the next section I defend two such moral reasons, the promissory obligation that follows from ratifying the UNFCCC, and fairness in access to energy resources, which is protected by the right to sustainable development. The UNFCCC Norm of the Right to Sustainable Development 14 The UNFCCC entered into force in 1994. Currently there are 196 parties to the treaty. They have agreed to stabilize atmospheric concentrations of greenhouse gases ‘at a level that would prevent dangerous anthropogenic interference with the climate system.’ (Art. 2) The treaty is a piece of soft international law. It neither establishes a schedule for mitigation, nor provides a mechanism for holding states accountable. Instead, it establishes a number of background norms to guide further deliberation in pursuit of an agreement about how to ‘prevent dangerous anthropogenic interference with the climate system.’ Treaty ratification is a formal deliberative process that is not taken lightly in most states and should be taken as reflective endorsement of the terms of the treaty. In the present case, agreement to the treaty is agreement to pursue the objective of mitigation diplomatically within the constraints of the treaty’s norms. Additional agreements are necessary, and the treaty’s norms constrain the content of those agreements. In light of the present discussion, Article 3 is particularly important because it recognizes the importance of economic development and affirms that, ‘The Parties have a right to, and should, promote sustainable development.’ The Preamble understands that in order to promote sustainable development, ‘developing countries need access to resources required to achieve sustainable social and economic development and that, in order for developing countries to progress towards that goal, their energy consumption will need to grow.’ Respecting the right to sustainable development constrains acceptable additional agreements. A sustainable international energy regime requires a rapid transition away from fossil fuel consumption. But poverty-eradicating human development requires energy. Underdeveloped countries must increase their energy use substantially to achieve such development. Hence, there are two constraints on an international agreement consistent with the norms of the UNFCCC. It must prescribe rapid global reductions in CO2 emissions and it must not disrupt access to inexpensive sources of energy for underdeveloped states. Within the UNFCCC deliberative context there are two moral justifications for the 15 constraint that additional agreements must respect the right to sustainable development. The first is based upon the promissory obligation that states have assumed in virtue of the prior agreement to the treaty, which recognizes the right to sustainable development (Moellendorf 2014). States have agreed to constrain further deliberations by recognition of this right. In doing so, every state has a reasonable expectation that every other will so constrain their deliberations. Knowingly offering proposals that are inconsistent with that norm is disrespectful of others parties and expresses contempt for the process of finding agreement in the context governed by the treaty. The second moral justification for the right to sustainable development within the UNFCCC deliberative context is based on considerations of fairness. An effective international mitigation treaty is a cooperative practice in pursuit of a morally obligatory goal. Such a treaty would constrain energy consumption by reducing permissible consumption of fossil fuels. Given the necessity of energy consumption to the morally commendable project of eradicating poverty, it is important that the constraints on energy consumption be fair. Fair cooperation prohibits some people suffering morally grave burdens in order that others not suffer comparatively minor moral ones. An international treaty that would raise energy prices for poor states would burden its citizens with continued energy poverty and therefore lay a great moral burden on them. Alternatively, deep reductions in emissions can be carried out by wealthy states at comparatively minor transitional costs. The right to sustainable development directs the costs of mitigation in such a way that poor states are not hindered in the pursuit of poverty-eradicating development. It therefore ensures fairness in the distribution of the costs of the mitigation project. Neither of the two arguments on behalf of the right to sustainable development is an instance of Rawlsian nonideal theory. Neither makes reference to an ideal theory of justice, the realization of which would be facilitated by recognizing the right to sustainable development. Of course, any plausible ideal theory of international justice would require 16 states to honour treaties. But the moral force of a promissory obligation is what constrains the plausibility of the account of international justice; the obligation is not derived from an ideal theory of global or international justice. This is also the case with respect to the norm of fairness appealed to in the second argument. An ideal theory of global or international justice might incorporate an account of fairness to justify the principles that it defends. But the second argument has not been made in reference to principles of ideal justice. We have convictions about fairness, convictions about which we are reasonably confident prior to ideal theories of justice and which we employ to assess attempts at ideal theory. The second argument rests on one such principle. In the present context of urgency and deep disagreement about ideal theory, the independence of the two arguments from ideal theory is a virtue. This is not by any means to argue that ideal theory serves no important moral purpose. It is noteworthy, however, that both of these two arguments are plausibly moral justifications in the sense that Rawls understands justification. The idea of a moral justification is much broader than an ideal theory of justice. A justification is a manner of arguing about moral claims. Rawls distinguishes proofs from justifications by adding the requirement to the latter that the premises be acceptable to the audience to whom the argument is made (Rawls 1991, p. 508). The first of the two arguments appeals to a promissory obligation to respect a prior agreement about norms. The second appeals to a conviction about fairness, namely that in a cooperative framework some should not suffer grave moral burdens to prevent relative minor burdens to others. The first argument is a justification in the relevant sense since the moral weight is carried by appeal to promissory obligations, which are widely accepted. The second is plausibly a justification since the appeal to burden-sharing is based on a widely held conviction about fairness, and not on an appeal to controversial accounts of global and intergenerational justice. To the extent that one or the other of these arguments is a justification in the Rawlsian sense and to the extent that my argument against the application of a Rawlsian kind of nonideal theory is plausible, then 17 surprisingly in order to mount a Rawlsian type of justification for urgent climate change mitigation, one has to abandon the project of Rawlsian nonideal theory. A Criticism of the Right to Sustainable Development Posner and Weisbach explicitly reject the right to sustainable development as redistributivist. This charge of redistribritutivism seems directed to the feasibility of a treaty proposal that contains a commitment to the right to sustainable development, namely if such a treaty requires redistributing resources from one state to another, the former state will reject it on grounds that there is an alternative non-redistributive possibility that is better for its GDP. In response to the criticism of the right to sustainable development I maintain that it is not necessarily redistributivist, and that the greater feasibility of International Paretianism is highly doubtful. To appreciate why satisfying the right to sustainable development need not be redistributivist, recall Situation One discussed in a previous section. In that case there is a choice between two treaties both satisfying International Paretianism and one of the two also satisfying the right to sustainable development. Let’s specify the situation in greater detail. Situation One Further Specified: There are only two states. A business as usual scenario would leave Rich State with a GDP of 10, Poor State has a GDP of 3. Treaty One would leave Rich State with a GDP of 15 and Poor Sate with a GDP of 4. Treaty Two, which satisfies the right to sustainable development, would leave Rich State with a GDP of 12 and Poor State with a GDP of 7. Under Treaty Two are the gains for Poor State the product of redistribution from Rich State? Posner and Weisbach list several sufficient conditions of redistribution; and two of them may be applicable to this case. First, redistribution from a rich to a poor state occurs if the rich state is held to stricter mitigation requirements than the poor one. Second, redistribution from a rich state to a poor one occurs if the treaty better serves the interests of the poor state than the rich one (Posner and Weisbach 2010, p. 80). 18 Posner and Weisbach’s two conditions, however, seem insufficient to identify cases of redistribution. Some forms of progressive taxation redistribute from the wealthy to the poor by, for example, supplying income support for the latter. Other forms of progressive taxation simply fund public goods without redistributing to the poor. If a wealthy person pays income tax at higher rate than a poor one, with the proceeds going to finance something for the benefit of both, for example public roads, that is not a case of redistribution from the rich person to the poor person. The concept of redistribution requires some transfer in holdings from one party to another. This is, as it were, the “re-” in redistribution. In Situation One Further Specified the two states each seem to have different growth trajectories in the two treaty scenarios. In one instance the rich state does better, in the other the poor state does better. If the gains of Poor State in Treaty Two are the product of redistribution from Rich State, then the gains of Rich State in Treaty One must be the result of redistribution from Poor State. But neither case is necessarily redistributivist. Differing growth trajectories of the two treaties could be the result of different energy policies leading to differences in wealth creation. The wealth in that case is not transferred from one state to another by the mitigation treaty because it did not exist prior to the growth. If the wealth gained was not ex ante in either state, then it was not taken from one to add to the GDP of the other. In that case, neither Treaty One nor Treaty Two is redistributive. Perhaps I am wrong about what the concept of redistribution requires. Maybe it does not require transferring pre-existing holdings from one party to give to another. Posner and Weisbach claim that a climate change treaty in which the poor benefit more than is required by International Paretianism is redistributivist (Posner and Weisbach 2010, p. 83). To state the idea in neutral terms perhaps a policy is redistributive between parties if, although it benefits both, it results in greater benefits to one party than an alternative would. In that case both Treaty One and Treaty Two are redistributive in comparison to the other. Treaty One redistributes for the benefit of Rich State and Treaty Two for the benefit of Poor State. In that 19 case there is no policy that is uniquely redistributive and the charge of a policy being redistributive loses its bite. It is also not the case that a treaty that satisfies the right to sustainable development is necessarily less feasible than one that satisfies International Paretianism. If the treaty satisfying the right to sustainable development also satisfies International Paretianism, as in Situation One, then it is not less feasible even by Posner and Weisbach’s lights. But even if the treaty does not satisfy International Paretianism, it may be no less feasible because, as the discussion above of Situation Two indicates, there might be other self-regarding reasons that lead a state to accept the treaty that does not satisfy International Paretianism. Moreover, the discussion of Situation Two also suggests that in circumstances in which satisfying International Paretianism requires raising energy prices in poor states and thereby threatening the right to sustainable development, there is no reason to think that International Paretianism will be endorsed by poor states. In that case, International Paretianism has no feasibility advantage. Making the Norms Stickier An earlier section presented two moral arguments for adhering to the UNFCCC’s norm of respecting a state’s right to sustainable development, one based on promissory obligations, the other based on fairness. In this section I present a third argument appealing to the significant good of the continued existence of the treaty as a robust source of norms. I also offer a final prudential consideration that weighs against pushing proposals that contravene UNFCCC norms. Background norms have tremendous pragmatic importance for subsequent deliberation. By constraining acceptable agreements to those consistent with the norms, they also constrain acceptable proposals by ruling out proposals inconsistent with accepted background norms. By narrowing the range of acceptable proposals, background norms serve 20 the pragmatic goal of facilitating agreement in a timely fashion. Proposals that are patently inconsistent with background norms can be rejected without thoroughgoing debates of their merits. That saves both time and the acrimony of having to address certain proposal on their merits. For proposals that do not patently contradict background norms, discussion that subsequently reveals such a contradiction provides the basis for rejecting the proposal without extensive normative wrangling and negotiation. Background rules then serve to focus debates and thereby also to conserve the sometimes scarce resource of diplomatic good will. Attempting to negotiate outside of a framework of existing background rules would involve huge time costs. And reconstructing a new normative framework to structure discussions is no easy task. As Robert O. Keohane observes, ‘International regimes are easier to maintain than to construct.’ (Keohane 1984, p. 102) The UNFCCC can be seen then as a kind of institutional sunk cost in the negotiation process (Keohane 1984, p. 102). It is difficult to envisage the circumstance in which it would be rational—assuming the aim of a comprehensive mitigation project—to start all over again, all the more so given the urgency of reaching an agreement. Unless negotiations were between parties with closely shared understandings of the normative dimensions of the problem of climate change, to start negotiations disavowing UNFCCC norms is to invite either re-negotiating background norms or discussing the merits of a much broader array of proposals—including for example, International Paretianism—than would be acceptable within the UNFCCC context. Neither of these is desirable given the urgency of reaching an agreement. The UNFCCC does not provide for legal sanction to a party that violates its norms by, say, insisting on a mitigation treaty that is inconsistent with them. Absent legal sanctions, any sanction for a state contravening the norms of the UNFCCC would be informal, such as condemnation or diplomatic consequences for other matters important to the state.8 The status of the principles in the treaty as norms is then heavily contingent on their continued voluntary observance and informal enforcement. Their normative force consists in their stickiness. 21 Given the relative youth of the treaty and the lack of success thus far of negotiating a comprehensive and effective mitigation agreement under its auspices, the status of UNFCCC principles as norms is relatively precarious. In light of the general good served by having the system of background norms in place, states have reason not to proffer proposals that would exacerbate the precariousness of the norms. Many states may also have a self-regarding reason not to offer a proposal that would contravene UNFCCC norms. Any treaty proposal that contravenes the norms of the UNFCCC threatens to weaken the overall normative structure of the treaty. In this regard there are additional costs to proposals that a state motivated only by self-regarding interests should consider. If it is the case that the existence of a structure of background norms reduces the costs of negotiation for all parties by narrowing the range of acceptable proposals and by providing the basis for procedural reasons for rejecting those proposals that contravene the norms, then any state that would erode the structure of background norms has to reckon with whether the sum of the reputational costs to it and the costs incurred by loss of the background structure are outweighed by the benefits of succeeding in pushing through a proposal. There is no reason to suppose that there is an a priori answer to what the weighing would recommend. But unless a state has good reason to be especially confident about pushing its proposal over the short term, and unless it is powerful enough to mitigate the long term reputational damage and to pursue its interests over the long term in an international arena characterized by less cooperation and greater suspicion, the result of the weighing would seem favour not eroding the norm. For very powerful states it might be rational to erode the normative framework of a background agreement, but then only if its interests can be served without a treaty arising within that agreement. Since unmitigated climate change is likely eventually to affect all states severely, it is likely to prove irrational to erode the norms of the UNFCCC. Adhering to its norms serves both the general good and very likely also each state’s long term good. 22 Recapping A nonideal theory as Rawls understands it is highly unlikely to be the object of widespread agreement among state parties within the time-frame necessary for negotiating an effective climate change agreement. It does not follow from this that moral considerations should be abandoned altogether in favour of International Paretianism. The indifference of that view to the grave problems of energy poverty and underdevelopment generally renders it implausible. Moreover, International Paretianism is not necessarily more feasible than an account that seeks to reduce energy poverty. In contrast, the norms of the UNFCCC, including the right to sustainable development, are appealing. Several considerations count in favour of adhering to them. Parties to the treaty have a promissory obligation to honour them. Fairness seems to require accepting the right to sustainable development within the context of distributing access to energy and extant energy poverty. The normative framework of the treaty serves the general good of facilitating agreement. And finally for any given state the costs of contravening the norms might be very high over the long run. If these arguments are plausible, there are very good reasons to take the norms of the UNFCCC seriously. 23 Bibliography Abbot, Kenneth W. and Duncan Snidal. 2000. “Hard and Soft Legalization,” International Organization 54. Caney, Simon. 2012. “Just Emissions,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 40. IPPC 2014. Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change, Climate Change 2014, Fifth Assessment Report (AR5), The Physical Basis of the Science, Summary for Policy Makers http://www.climatechange2013.org/images/report/WG1AR5_SPM_FINAL.pdf. Kennedy, Martin, et al. 2008. “Snowball Earth Termination by Destabilization of Equatorial Permafrost Methane Clathrate,” Nature 453: 642–645. Keohane, Robert O. 1984. After Hegenomy: Cooperation and Discord in the World Political Economy. Princeton, Princeton University Press. Knight, Frank H. 1921. Risk, Uncertainty, and Profit New York, Hart, Schaffner and Marx; Houghton Mifflin Co. Moellendorf, Darrel. 2014. The Moral Challenge of Dangerous Climate Change: Poverty, Policy, and Values. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Posner, Eric A. and David Weisbach. 2010. Climate Change Justice, Princeton: Princeton University Press. Rawls, John. 1993. Political Liberalism. New York, Columbia University Press. Rawls, John. 1999a. A Theory of Justice rev. ed. Cambridge, M., Harvard University Press. Rawls, John. 1999b. The Law of Peoples. Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, Science Daily, 2008. “Large Methane Release Could Cause Abrupt Climate Change As Happened 635 Million Years Ago,” May 29. Simmons, A. John. 2010. “Ideal and Nonideal Theory,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 38. Roberts, J. Timmons and Bradley C. Parks. 2007. A Climate of Injustice: Global Inequality, North-South Politics, and Climate Policy. Cambridge, MA, The MIT Press. Trillionth Tonne. http://trillionthtonne.org/. 24 1 An earlier version of this paper was presented at Sciences Po, Paris. I would like to thank the audience for their helpful comments. I would also like to thank Daniel Callies, Clare Heyward, Merten Reglitz, and Dominic Roser for their helpful feedback. 2 See also Simmons 2010, p. 22: ‘A good policy in nonideal theory is good only as transitionally just—that is, only as a morally permissible part of a feasible overall program to achieve perfect justice, as a policy that puts us in an improved position to reach that ultimate goal. And good policies are good not relative to the elimination of any particular, targeted injustices, but only relative to the integrated goal of eliminating all injustice.’ 3 Simon Caney rejects what he calls methods of isolation on similar grounds. See Caney 2012, p. 271. 4 But see also p. 179 where they state claim it can be in the interests of states satisfy the altruism of their citizens. This, however, confounds their account since the argument against redistribution is then only successful to the extent that citizens do not stand by the claim that satisfying citizens’ altruism can be in the interests of states. . 5 Because GDP is an aggregate measure, an improvement in GDP is consistent with a class of poor people faring worse. 6 Compare to Abbot and Snidal, 2000, p. 30: ‘[P]articipation in other international legal regimes should enhance credibility: it exposes states to greater reputational costs and makes them more vulnerable to countermeasures.’ I claim that refusal to participate may also have reputational costs and make states vulnerable to countermeasures. 7 Posner and Weisbach are also aware of this possibility. See Climate Change Justice, p. 185. 8 See Roberts and Parks 2007, p. 223: ‘It is also worth pointing out that abrogation of a widely accepted principle in one regime can be exceedingly, even prohibitively costly if that action 25 makes a country look like an outlaw in other regimes that use that same principle as an international focal point.’