* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Nussbaum and Wolf Reading Study Guide Phil 240 Introduction to
Arthur Schafer wikipedia , lookup
Internalism and externalism wikipedia , lookup
Thomas Nagel wikipedia , lookup
J. Baird Callicott wikipedia , lookup
Utilitarianism wikipedia , lookup
Kantian ethics wikipedia , lookup
Aristotelian ethics wikipedia , lookup
Divine command theory wikipedia , lookup
Individualism wikipedia , lookup
Bernard Williams wikipedia , lookup
Morality and religion wikipedia , lookup
The Sovereignty of Good wikipedia , lookup
Lawrence Kohlberg wikipedia , lookup
Ethics of artificial intelligence wikipedia , lookup
Consequentialism wikipedia , lookup
Lawrence Kohlberg's stages of moral development wikipedia , lookup
Moral disengagement wikipedia , lookup
Ethics in religion wikipedia , lookup
Morality throughout the Life Span wikipedia , lookup
Critique of Practical Reason wikipedia , lookup
Moral development wikipedia , lookup
Virtue ethics wikipedia , lookup
Martha Nussbaum wikipedia , lookup
Ethical intuitionism wikipedia , lookup
Alasdair MacIntyre wikipedia , lookup
Moral responsibility wikipedia , lookup
Secular morality wikipedia , lookup
Nussbaum and Wolf Reading Study Guide Phil 240 Introduction to Ethical Theory Martha Nussbaum, “Non-Relative Virtues: An Aristotelian Approach” Recent philosophy has seen a large resurgence of interest in theorizing about the virtues, but many virtue-oriented ethical theories have involved some version of relativism—the view that ethics can only articulate local ideals rather than offering any universally valid norms of conduct. In contrast to this trend, Nussbaum sketches a program, heavily based on the works of Aristotle, for developing an objective account of human flourishing and the virtues. This program involves two stages. In the first stage, one isolates various nearly universal spheres of human experience, areas of our lives in which we all make choices about how to act. These spheres include fear of damages, bodily appetites and their pleasures, and the distribution of limited resources. Corresponding to each of these spheres is a virtue, which consists of being stably disposed to act appropriately within that sphere. The second stage of Nussbaum's Aristotelian program, which is largely left for another occasion, is to develop fuller specifications of each virtue by describing what sorts of attitudes or behaviors are appropriate within each sphere. Nussbaum discusses three objections to this sort of program. The first objection is that although we might agree that certain spheres of experience are more or less universal, it does not follow that there is a single objective virtue within each of these spheres, valid for all people at all times. The second objection goes even further, denying that there are genuinely universal spheres of shared human experience and arguing that even our perceptions of things like bodily appetites are highly culturally conditioned. The third objection is the most radical, and argues that many virtues, such as generosity, are simply responses to defective social conditions (e.g., the institution of private property). Nussbaum argues that each of these objections must be taken seriously, and that each forces modifications to her theory. Nonetheless, she insists that her Aristotelian framework provides a way forward in the project of articulating and justifying objective ethical ideals. Study Questions 1. What two-step process is involved in Aristotle’s account of each virtue? Do you agree that this two-step process can yield an account of virtue that is objective and universal? Why or why not? 2. How does Nussbaum think we can go about discovering what the virtues are? Do you think her account gives us a plausible way of discovering nonrelative virtues? Defend your answer. 3. Critically reflect on the objections to Aristotelian virtue ethics that Nussbaum presents. Do you think she succeeds in defusing the objection? Why or why not? 4. What does ethical progress consist in, for Aristotle (and Nussbaum)? Does virtue ethics provide a plausible method for making ethical progress? 5. In what sense does Nussbaum’s theory render the virtues objective? To what extent do the virtues depend on context? Does Nussbaum’s theory deliver a desirable kind of objectivity in ethics? 6. What objection does Nussbaum think is raised by the work of Foucault and others on the historically contingent nature of desire? How does she respond to this objection? Do you think her response is adequate? 7. Why does Nussbaum consider Marx’s view that virtues were responses to defective relations of production, and therefore needed to be overcome? How does she respond to this challenge? Susan Wolf, “Moral Saints” A moral saint, as Wolf defines it, is someone who is as morally good as possible. Although such an ideal might seem worth striving for, Wolf argues that moral sainthood is in fact not an attractive ideal. Wolf claims that any moral saint would necessarily live a life dominated by the commitment to improving the welfare of others, but she distinguishes between two different models of moral sainthood. The Loving Saint is someone whose happiness truly consists in the happiness of others. The Rational Saint does not share this trait, but simply pays little attention to her own happiness and attaches overriding importance to the concerns of morality. Although these different models will appeal to different thinkers—Wolf suggests that utilitarians might be more attracted to the Loving Saint, and Kantians to the Rational Saint—Wolf claims that neither of them presents us with a desirable ideal worth striving for. What's wrong with moral sainthood? Wolf argues that there are many nonmoral goods in which moral saints would not be willing or able to partake. Moral saints would spend the large majority of their time improving the lives of others, and thus would have little time to read interesting books, or to create or appreciate art, cuisine, or music. Furthermore, as moral saints would take great care not to cause offense, they would be unlikely to have a dry, sarcastic wit, and might very well be rather bland. By passing up on so much, either out of lack of interest or simply an iron will, moral saints seem to miss out on developing "an identifiable, personal self." Wolf concludes that although an acceptable moral theory should render the idea of a moral saint coherent, moral sainthood turns out to be an undesirable ideal. We are left with the surprising conclusion that to live a good life, one should not strive to do as much good as possible. Study Questions 1. What nonmoral ideals does Wolf endorse, and why does she think they are valuable? How important do you think these are to living a good life? 2. What would moral sainthood look like for a utilitarian? What objections does Wolf raise to this as an ideal? Do you find her objections compelling? 3. What would moral sainthood look like for a Kantian? What objections does Wolf raise to this as an ideal? Do you find her objections compelling? 4. What is “the point of view of individual perfection”? What role would morality play in a life that is perfect from this point of view, according to Wolf? Do you agree with her assessment? Why or why not? 5. What is a moral saint? Is moral saintliness a desirable ideal? Why or why not? 6. What two models of moral sainthood does Wolf distinguish? To whom does she think each would appeal, and why? Do you find one model more attractive than the other? Defend your answer. 7. What lessons for moral philosophy does Wolf draw from her conclusion that moral sainthood is an unattractive ideal? What ideal does she substitute in its place? Do you agree with her?