Download Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts

Utilitarianism wikipedia , lookup

Compliance and ethics program wikipedia , lookup

Bernard Williams wikipedia , lookup

Virtue ethics wikipedia , lookup

Aristotelian ethics wikipedia , lookup

Individualism wikipedia , lookup

Sexual ethics wikipedia , lookup

Lawrence Kohlberg wikipedia , lookup

Internalism and externalism wikipedia , lookup

Morality and religion wikipedia , lookup

J. Baird Callicott wikipedia , lookup

Neohumanism wikipedia , lookup

Arthur Schafer wikipedia , lookup

Kantian ethics wikipedia , lookup

Cosmopolitanism wikipedia , lookup

Speciesism wikipedia , lookup

Morality throughout the Life Span wikipedia , lookup

Lawrence Kohlberg's stages of moral development wikipedia , lookup

Moral development wikipedia , lookup

Moral disengagement wikipedia , lookup

Business ethics wikipedia , lookup

Philosophy of history wikipedia , lookup

Jewish ethics wikipedia , lookup

Alasdair MacIntyre wikipedia , lookup

Moral responsibility wikipedia , lookup

Morality wikipedia , lookup

Ethics wikipedia , lookup

Moral relativism wikipedia , lookup

Jürgen Habermas wikipedia , lookup

Consequentialism wikipedia , lookup

Ethical intuitionism wikipedia , lookup

Secular morality wikipedia , lookup

Emotivism wikipedia , lookup

Ethics in religion wikipedia , lookup

Thomas Hill Green wikipedia , lookup

Universal pragmatics wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
Jürgen Habermas




The Theory of Communicative
Action (1981)
Moral Consciousness and
Communicative Action (1983/ tr
1995)
Postmetaphysical Thinking (1988)
Dialektik der Säkularisierung.
Über Vernunft und Religion (with
Joseph Ratzinger (2005) English:
The Dialectics of Secularization:
On Reason and Religion)
General characteristics



Continues and reconstructs Enlightenment ideals (of political emancipation
and democracy)
vs relativism
practical, pragmatic, procedural, formal [100] – find solutions to normative
problems in discourse / communication





An analysis of communicative structures
We need to identify and reconstruct the universal conditions of possible
understanding
communicative action, the process of giving and criticizing reasons for holding
or rejecting particular claims
language cannot be comprehended unless an understanding is achieved in it
- not settling the issue of ‘the good life’ (impossible with pluralism), but
justice [101]


there is an irreducible plurality of 'goods'; this conditions and limits moral
conversation
So a non-moral sense of ethics.
General characteristics



What do we have?
A development and reformulation of Kant’s insights “a deontological ethics”
[101]
a 'dialogical form of practical reason'




validity of a norm is justified only intersubjectively in processes of argumentation
between individuals; in a dialectic.
in search of a rational founding (Begrundung) of propositions
Needs a ‘life-world of a specific social group’ [100]
attempt to bridge the gap between "is" and "ought"
assumptions
 1. - rationality is a characteristic of all human beings
 2. - freedom is a characteristic of all human beings [leads to autonomy]




3, - equality
4. - therefore, all issues (incl. moral problems) are capable of being solved
in a rational and cognitive way
5. - the existence of some universal claims and therefore the importance of
universal norms;



this is the basis of reciprocity (why others count) and its emanicipatory character (as
being critical of established authority)
[leads to democracy, based on consent]
6. rationality capable, through discourse, of arriving at universal norms.
7. - (from 3) We need to take into consideration the viewpoints of all who
would be affected by the adoption of normative claims
the principle of discourse ethics (D) stipulates:
 “a [moral] norm may claim validity [to be justified] only if all who might be
affected by it reach (or would reach) [in their capacity] as participants in a
practical discourse, agreement that this norm is valid ” (J. Habermas,
"Discourse Ethics: Notes on a Program of Philosophical Justification,"
Cambridge, MIT Press 1990, p. 71).
the principle of universalization (U)
 A norm is valid only if "all concerned [affected] can accept the
consequences and the side affects its universal observance can be
anticipated to have for the satisfaction for everyone's interests (and that
these consequences are preferred to those of known alternative
possibilities for regulation)." (p. 71)
 "unless all affected can freely accept the consequences and the side
effects that the general observance of a controversial norm can be
expected to have for the satisfaction of the interests of each individual"
(see p. ___; Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action, p. 93).
Why universality?

“Every person who accepts the universal and necessary communicative
presuppositions of argumentative speech and who knows what I means to
justify a norm of action implicitly presupposes as valid the principle of
universalisation,…”
- Habermas, Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action, MIT Press,
1995, p. 86.
Specific ‘normative’ assumptions / “rules of the game”
Habermas (1990) / Robert Alexy :

Level 1: logical-semantic rules of argumentation (no ethical content) :
[p. 84]

Understandability
Non-contradiction (1.1) No speaker may contradict himself.
Consistency (1.2) Every speaker who applies predicate F to object A must
be prepared to apply F to all other objects resembling A in all relevant
aspects.
No Equivocation (1.3) Different speakers may not use the same expression
with different meanings (p. 87).



Specific ‘normative’ assumptions / “rules of the game”
Habermas (1990) / Alexy :

Level 2: the rules of jurisdiction and relevance (have ethical import
and content) [p. 85]

Sincerity / Seriousness / Authenticity [Ernsthaftigkeit],
(2.1) Every speaker may assert only what he really believes.
Legitimacy
(2.2) A person who disputes a proposition or norm not under discussion
must provide a reason for wanting to do so (p.88).



Specific ‘normative’ assumptions / “rules of the game”
Habermas (1990) / Alexy :

Level 3: Ideal Speech Situation [p. 86]

Openness / Freedom from Constraint and Coercion
(3.1) Every subject with the competence to speak and act is allowed to take
part in a discourse.
(3.2)
a. Everyone is allowed to question any assertion whatever.
b. Everyone is allowed to introduce any assertion whatever into the
discourse.
c. Everyone is allowed to express his attitudes, desires and needs.
(3.3) No speaker may be prevented, by internal or external coercion, from
exercising his rights as laid down in (3.1) and (3.2) (p. 88).





Consensus = “all affected can freely accept the consequences and the side
effects that the general observance of a controversial norm can be
expected to have for the satisfaction of the interests of each individual.”
Discourse Ethics and Solidarity


these procedural rules must be complemented by a sense of solidarity
among participants (i.e., concern for the well-being of both one's fellow
human beings and of the community at large)
"Justice conceived in postconventional terms [a Kohlbergian reference]
can converge with solidarity, as its other side, only when solidarity has
been transformed in the light of the idea of a general, discursive formation
of will."
Discourse Ethics and Democracy


the general conditions of the ideal speech situation and the rules of reason,
coupled with this sense of solidarity, describe the necessary conditions of
democratic polity.
these conditions and rules establish the legitimacy of pluralism.
There can be rightness and wrongness

“I hold the view that normative rightness must be regarded as a claim to
validity that is analogous to a truth claim. This notion is captured by the
term “ cognitivist ethics .” A cognitivist ethics must answer the question of
how to justify normative statements….. Only those norms may claim to be
valid that could meet with the consent of all affected in their role as
participants in a practical discourse….. For a norm to be valid, the
consequences and side effects of its general observance for the
satisfaction of each person's particular interests must be acceptable to all.”
(“Morality and Ethical Life”, in MCCA, p. 197)
Advantages:
Useful; provides a (communicative) framework in which political and (some)
moral conflicts can be resolved
Presence of rationality, freedom, equality
Non-relativistic (right & wrong)
Universalizable
Consistent with solidarity and democracy

Limited in extent


Limited in scope


Does not give norms for every moral conflict that might arise
Individualistic



self-understanding and self-determination not included in moral theory
individual participants
tries to avoid this through ‘generalization’ – Is this possible?
Naively idealistic

assumes that human beings have capacities that they don’t have;
people are incapable of being objective and rational in dialogue


Inconsistent
Too vague


Too narrow



has Habermas adequately defended universalization as
necessary/required for argumentation?
do we need universalization?
Does it apply to all discourses?


applies in some situations with a practical resolution (e.g., conflict
resolution)
Too much or too little Kantianism


rightness defined in terms of “worthiness”
No; not comprehensive doctrines / religious ones;
Question-begging or too narrow?

assumes that some “reasons” (public reasons) are superior to others