Download What is and to which end does one study Bohmian Mechanics?

Document related concepts

Instanton wikipedia , lookup

Particle in a box wikipedia , lookup

Coherent states wikipedia , lookup

Density matrix wikipedia , lookup

Topological quantum field theory wikipedia , lookup

Orchestrated objective reduction wikipedia , lookup

Quantum field theory wikipedia , lookup

Hydrogen atom wikipedia , lookup

Propagator wikipedia , lookup

Max Born wikipedia , lookup

Renormalization wikipedia , lookup

Ensemble interpretation wikipedia , lookup

Bell test experiments wikipedia , lookup

Schrödinger equation wikipedia , lookup

Many-worlds interpretation wikipedia , lookup

De Broglie–Bohm theory wikipedia , lookup

Scalar field theory wikipedia , lookup

Quantum teleportation wikipedia , lookup

Erwin Schrödinger wikipedia , lookup

Quantum entanglement wikipedia , lookup

Renormalization group wikipedia , lookup

Measurement in quantum mechanics wikipedia , lookup

Dirac equation wikipedia , lookup

Elementary particle wikipedia , lookup

Quantum electrodynamics wikipedia , lookup

Bohr–Einstein debates wikipedia , lookup

Bell's theorem wikipedia , lookup

Atomic theory wikipedia , lookup

Quantum state wikipedia , lookup

History of quantum field theory wikipedia , lookup

Path integral formulation wikipedia , lookup

EPR paradox wikipedia , lookup

Interpretations of quantum mechanics wikipedia , lookup

T-symmetry wikipedia , lookup

Symmetry in quantum mechanics wikipedia , lookup

Double-slit experiment wikipedia , lookup

Identical particles wikipedia , lookup

Copenhagen interpretation wikipedia , lookup

Matter wave wikipedia , lookup

Relativistic quantum mechanics wikipedia , lookup

Probability amplitude wikipedia , lookup

Wave function wikipedia , lookup

Canonical quantization wikipedia , lookup

Wave–particle duality wikipedia , lookup

Hidden variable theory wikipedia , lookup

Theoretical and experimental justification for the Schrödinger equation wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
What is and to which end does one study
Bohmian Mechanics?
Detlef Dürr
Mathematisches Institut
LMU München
Feb. 2015
What is Bohmian Mechanics?
What is Bohmian Mechanics?
• Matter is described by point particles in physical space, i.e. an
N-particle universe is described by
Q1 , ..., QN , Qi ∈ R3 particle positions
What is Bohmian Mechanics?
• Matter is described by point particles in physical space, i.e. an
N-particle universe is described by
Q1 , ..., QN , Qi ∈ R3 particle positions
• particles move
The LAW of motion
The LAW of motion
• respects Galilean symmetry but is non-Newtonian. It is a
mathematically consistent simplification of the Hamilton Jacobi idea
of mechanics:
Q(t) = (Q1 (t), ..., QN (t)),
∇=
∂
∂q
configuration
obeys (time reversal invariance in ”first order” theory achieved by
complex conjugation)
dQ
Ψ∗ ∇Ψ
= v Ψ (Q(t), t) = αIm ∗ (Q(t), t) guiding equation
dt
Ψ Ψ
α is a dimensional parameter
the guiding field is
The LAW of motion
• respects Galilean symmetry but is non-Newtonian. It is a
mathematically consistent simplification of the Hamilton Jacobi idea
of mechanics:
Q(t) = (Q1 (t), ..., QN (t)),
∇=
∂
∂q
configuration
obeys (time reversal invariance in ”first order” theory achieved by
complex conjugation)
dQ
Ψ∗ ∇Ψ
= v Ψ (Q(t), t) = αIm ∗ (Q(t), t) guiding equation
dt
Ψ Ψ
α is a dimensional parameter
the guiding field is
• the ”universal” wave function
Ψ : R3N × R 7→ C(n)
(q = (q1 , . . . , qN ), t) 7→ Ψ(q, t)
Ψ
Ψ
• solves the Schrödinger equation
i
H=−
Pn
∂Ψ
(q, t) = HΨ(q, t) “Schrödinger“ equation
∂t
α
k=1 2 ∆k
+ W (Galilean invariant operator)
Bohmian motion encompasses Newtonian motion
Bohmian motion encompasses Newtonian motion
i
• write Ψ in polar form Ψ(q, t) = R(q, t)e ~ S(q,t) with R, S real
functions and ~ an (action-) dimensional constant
Bohmian motion encompasses Newtonian motion
i
• write Ψ in polar form Ψ(q, t) = R(q, t)e ~ S(q,t) with R, S real
functions and ~ an (action-) dimensional constant
• S satisfies a Hamilton Jacobi type of equation
Bohmian motion encompasses Newtonian motion
i
• write Ψ in polar form Ψ(q, t) = R(q, t)e ~ S(q,t) with R, S real
functions and ~ an (action-) dimensional constant
• S satisfies a Hamilton Jacobi type of equation
• v = m−1 ∇S for a Newtonian particle with mass m
Bohmian motion encompasses Newtonian motion
i
• write Ψ in polar form Ψ(q, t) = R(q, t)e ~ S(q,t) with R, S real
functions and ~ an (action-) dimensional constant
• S satisfies a Hamilton Jacobi type of equation
• v = m−1 ∇S for a Newtonian particle with mass m
• vΨ =
α
~ ∇S
potential”
=⇒ identify α =
~
m
and
W
~
=: V as the ”Newtonian
• Newtonian Bohmian motion for ”Quantum Potential”
~2 ∆R
2m R
≈0
Bohmian mechanics with Newtonian identification of
parameters1
dQ
Ψ∗ ∇Ψ
= v Ψ (Q(t), t) = ~m−1 Im ∗ (Q(t), t)
dt
Ψ Ψ
where m is a diagonal matrix with mass entries mk
!
n
X
~2
∂Ψ
i~
(q, t) = −
∆k + V (q) Ψ(q, t)
∂t
2mk
k=1
1 Analogy:
Boltzmann’s constant kB relates thermodynamics to Newtonian
mechanics, ~ relates Newtonian mechanics to Bohmian Mechanics
simplest way to Bohmian mechanics
simplest way to Bohmian mechanics
• R 2 = |Ψ|2 satifies ∂t |Ψ|2 = −∇ · (v Ψ |Ψ|2 ) =: −∇ · j Ψ the quantum
flux equation
simplest way to Bohmian mechanics
• R 2 = |Ψ|2 satifies ∂t |Ψ|2 = −∇ · (v Ψ |Ψ|2 ) =: −∇ · j Ψ the quantum
flux equation
• vΨ =
jΨ
|Ψ|2
(Pauli 1927, J.S. Bell 1964)
”Bohmian Mechanics agrees with Quantum Predictions”
”Bohmian Mechanics agrees with Quantum Predictions”
• quantum flux equation means ρ(t) = |Ψ(t)|2 is equivariant: Assume
Q is distributed according to ρ = |Ψ|2 then Q(t) at any other time
is distributed according to ρ(t) = |Ψ(t)|2
Historical Criticisms
Historical Criticisms
• |ψ|2 is a probability, probability is subjective, hence the Bohmian
motion is guided by ignorance of the observer
Historical Criticisms
• |ψ|2 is a probability, probability is subjective, hence the Bohmian
motion is guided by ignorance of the observer
• In BM the position plays a distinguished role: The unitary symmetry
of Hilbert-space is violated
Historical Criticisms
• |ψ|2 is a probability, probability is subjective, hence the Bohmian
motion is guided by ignorance of the observer
• In BM the position plays a distinguished role: The unitary symmetry
of Hilbert-space is violated
• In BM particles have definite positions: The indistinguishability of
quantum particles is violated
Historical Criticisms
• |ψ|2 is a probability, probability is subjective, hence the Bohmian
motion is guided by ignorance of the observer
• In BM the position plays a distinguished role: The unitary symmetry
of Hilbert-space is violated
• In BM particles have definite positions: The indistinguishability of
quantum particles is violated
• solution: configuration space of identical particles is (like in classical
mechanics) the manifold R3N /SN −→ Fermion-Boson-Alternative
Historical Criticisms
• |ψ|2 is a probability, probability is subjective, hence the Bohmian
motion is guided by ignorance of the observer
• In BM the position plays a distinguished role: The unitary symmetry
of Hilbert-space is violated
• In BM particles have definite positions: The indistinguishability of
quantum particles is violated
• solution: configuration space of identical particles is (like in classical
mechanics) the manifold R3N /SN −→ Fermion-Boson-Alternative
• spin cannot be described in BM
Historical Criticisms
• |ψ|2 is a probability, probability is subjective, hence the Bohmian
motion is guided by ignorance of the observer
• In BM the position plays a distinguished role: The unitary symmetry
of Hilbert-space is violated
• In BM particles have definite positions: The indistinguishability of
quantum particles is violated
• solution: configuration space of identical particles is (like in classical
mechanics) the manifold R3N /SN −→ Fermion-Boson-Alternative
• spin cannot be described in BM
• solution: read
Ψ∗ ∇Ψ
Ψ∗ Ψ
as inner product in spinor space
Historical Criticisms
• |ψ|2 is a probability, probability is subjective, hence the Bohmian
motion is guided by ignorance of the observer
• In BM the position plays a distinguished role: The unitary symmetry
of Hilbert-space is violated
• In BM particles have definite positions: The indistinguishability of
quantum particles is violated
• solution: configuration space of identical particles is (like in classical
mechanics) the manifold R3N /SN −→ Fermion-Boson-Alternative
• spin cannot be described in BM
• solution: read
Ψ∗ ∇Ψ
Ψ∗ Ψ
as inner product in spinor space
• particle creation and annihilation contradicts the existence of
particles
Historical Criticisms
• |ψ|2 is a probability, probability is subjective, hence the Bohmian
motion is guided by ignorance of the observer
• In BM the position plays a distinguished role: The unitary symmetry
of Hilbert-space is violated
• In BM particles have definite positions: The indistinguishability of
quantum particles is violated
• solution: configuration space of identical particles is (like in classical
mechanics) the manifold R3N /SN −→ Fermion-Boson-Alternative
• spin cannot be described in BM
• solution: read
Ψ∗ ∇Ψ
Ψ∗ Ψ
as inner product in spinor space
• particle creation and annihilation contradicts the existence of
particles
• solution: standard birth and death process
Einstein’s criticism: Ψ on configuration space2 cannot be
physical
2 1080
dimensional
Einstein’s criticism: Ψ on configuration space2 cannot be
physical
• Ψ as function of configuration is called ”entanglement” of the wave
function
2 1080
dimensional
Einstein’s criticism: Ψ on configuration space2 cannot be
physical
• Ψ as function of configuration is called ”entanglement” of the wave
function
• k−th particle’s trajectory Qk (t)
dQk (t)
~
Ψ∗ ∇ k Ψ
=
Im
(Q1 , (t) . . . , QN (t), t),
dt
mk
Ψ∗ Ψ
2 1080
dimensional
Einstein’s criticism: Ψ on configuration space2 cannot be
physical
• Ψ as function of configuration is called ”entanglement” of the wave
function
• k−th particle’s trajectory Qk (t)
dQk (t)
~
Ψ∗ ∇ k Ψ
=
Im
(Q1 , (t) . . . , QN (t), t),
dt
mk
Ψ∗ Ψ
for entangled wave function influenced by all particles at t =⇒
manifestly not local, against the spirit of relativity
2 1080
dimensional
Einstein’s criticism answered by John S. Bell
Einstein’s criticism answered by John S. Bell
• the derivation of Bell’s inequalities and the experimental results
establish that nature is nonlocal (Jean Bricmont’s talk)
Einstein’s criticism answered by John S. Bell
• the derivation of Bell’s inequalities and the experimental results
establish that nature is nonlocal (Jean Bricmont’s talk)
• Ψ is that nonlocal agent, which produces nonlocal correlations
Einstein’s criticism answered by John S. Bell
• the derivation of Bell’s inequalities and the experimental results
establish that nature is nonlocal (Jean Bricmont’s talk)
• Ψ is that nonlocal agent, which produces nonlocal correlations
• BM is just what the doctor ordered.
universal Ψ and subsystem’s ϕ
S. Goldstein, N. Zanghì and I started this analysis 25 years ago
here at IHES
universal Ψ and subsystem’s ϕ
S. Goldstein, N. Zanghì and I started this analysis 25 years ago
here at IHES
• BM is a complete quantum theory, notions like measurement or
observer are not fundamental notions for defining the theory
universal Ψ and subsystem’s ϕ
S. Goldstein, N. Zanghì and I started this analysis 25 years ago
here at IHES
• BM is a complete quantum theory, notions like measurement or
observer are not fundamental notions for defining the theory
• the empirical import of BM comes solely from mathematical analysis
universal Ψ and subsystem’s ϕ
S. Goldstein, N. Zanghì and I started this analysis 25 years ago
here at IHES
• BM is a complete quantum theory, notions like measurement or
observer are not fundamental notions for defining the theory
• the empirical import of BM comes solely from mathematical analysis
• Boltzmann’s statistical analysis of BM (ρ = |ϕ|2 ) based on typicality
measure dPΨ = |Ψ|2 dq 3N which is equivariant (cf. quantum flux
equation)
Bohmian flow TtΨ : Q 7→ Q(t) commutes with Schrödinger evolution
Ψ 7→ Ψt :
dPΨ ◦ (TtΨ )−1 = dPΨt
universal Ψ and subsystem’s ϕ
S. Goldstein, N. Zanghì and I started this analysis 25 years ago
here at IHES
• BM is a complete quantum theory, notions like measurement or
observer are not fundamental notions for defining the theory
• the empirical import of BM comes solely from mathematical analysis
• Boltzmann’s statistical analysis of BM (ρ = |ϕ|2 ) based on typicality
measure dPΨ = |Ψ|2 dq 3N which is equivariant (cf. quantum flux
equation)
Bohmian flow TtΨ : Q 7→ Q(t) commutes with Schrödinger evolution
Ψ 7→ Ψt :
dPΨ ◦ (TtΨ )−1 = dPΨt
universal Ψ and subsystem’s ϕ
S. Goldstein, N. Zanghì and I started this analysis 25 years ago
here at IHES
• BM is a complete quantum theory, notions like measurement or
observer are not fundamental notions for defining the theory
• the empirical import of BM comes solely from mathematical analysis
• Boltzmann’s statistical analysis of BM (ρ = |ϕ|2 ) based on typicality
measure dPΨ = |Ψ|2 dq 3N which is equivariant (cf. quantum flux
equation)
Bohmian flow TtΨ : Q 7→ Q(t) commutes with Schrödinger evolution
Ψ 7→ Ψt :
dPΨ ◦ (TtΨ )−1 = dPΨt
• Anology: Stationarity of microcanonical measure (Liouville equation)
on phase space in Hamiltonian Mechanics
universal Ψ and subsystem’s ϕ
S. Goldstein, N. Zanghì and I started this analysis 25 years ago
here at IHES
• BM is a complete quantum theory, notions like measurement or
observer are not fundamental notions for defining the theory
• the empirical import of BM comes solely from mathematical analysis
• Boltzmann’s statistical analysis of BM (ρ = |ϕ|2 ) based on typicality
measure dPΨ = |Ψ|2 dq 3N which is equivariant (cf. quantum flux
equation)
Bohmian flow TtΨ : Q 7→ Q(t) commutes with Schrödinger evolution
Ψ 7→ Ψt :
dPΨ ◦ (TtΨ )−1 = dPΨt
• Anology: Stationarity of microcanonical measure (Liouville equation)
on phase space in Hamiltonian Mechanics
• ρ is the empirical density in an ensemble of subsystems
universal Ψ and subsystem’s ϕ
S. Goldstein, N. Zanghì and I started this analysis 25 years ago
here at IHES
• BM is a complete quantum theory, notions like measurement or
observer are not fundamental notions for defining the theory
• the empirical import of BM comes solely from mathematical analysis
• Boltzmann’s statistical analysis of BM (ρ = |ϕ|2 ) based on typicality
measure dPΨ = |Ψ|2 dq 3N which is equivariant (cf. quantum flux
equation)
Bohmian flow TtΨ : Q 7→ Q(t) commutes with Schrödinger evolution
Ψ 7→ Ψt :
dPΨ ◦ (TtΨ )−1 = dPΨt
• Anology: Stationarity of microcanonical measure (Liouville equation)
on phase space in Hamiltonian Mechanics
• ρ is the empirical density in an ensemble of subsystems
• ϕ is wave function of subsystem
conditional wave function ϕ of subsystem
X = (X1 , . . . , Xn ) system’s particles
Q = (X , Y ) splitting in system and rest of universe
Y
⇓
ϕ (x) := Ψ(x, Y )/kΨ(Y )k
normalized conditional wave function of subsystem guides X
conditional wave function ϕ of subsystem
X = (X1 , . . . , Xn ) system’s particles
Q = (X , Y ) splitting in system and rest of universe
Y
⇓
ϕ (x) := Ψ(x, Y )/kΨ(Y )k
normalized conditional wave function of subsystem guides X
crucial ”conditional measure” formula
PΨ (X ∈ dx|ϕY = ϕ) = |ϕ(x)|2 dx
Autonomous subsystem: effective wave function
If wave function of universe Ψ(x, y ) = ϕ(x)Φ(y ) + Ψ(x, y )⊥
where
suppΦ ∩ suppΨ⊥ = ∅ macroscopically disjoint
and if
Y ∈ suppΦ e.g. preparation of ϕ
⇓
Autonomous subsystem: effective wave function
If wave function of universe Ψ(x, y ) = ϕ(x)Φ(y ) + Ψ(x, y )⊥
where
suppΦ ∩ suppΨ⊥ = ∅ macroscopically disjoint
and if
Y ∈ suppΦ e.g. preparation of ϕ
⇓
ϕY = ϕ
is effective wave function for system
Autonomous subsystem: effective wave function
If wave function of universe Ψ(x, y ) = ϕ(x)Φ(y ) + Ψ(x, y )⊥
where
suppΦ ∩ suppΨ⊥ = ∅ macroscopically disjoint
and if
Y ∈ suppΦ e.g. preparation of ϕ
⇓
ϕY = ϕ
is effective wave function for system
decoherence sustains disjointness of supports
⇓
Schrödinger equation for ϕ for some time
n
i~
X ~2
∂ϕ
(x, t) = −
∆k ϕ(x, t) + V (x)ϕ(x, t)
∂t
2mk
k=1
macroscopically disjoint Y - supports
X
N = 10
N =10
Y
24
Bohmian Subsystem
(X , ϕ) physical variables
dX
ϕ∗ ∇ϕ
= v ϕ (X (t), t) = ~m−1 Im ∗ (X (t), t) guiding equation
dt
ϕ ϕ
n
i~
X ~2
∂ϕ
(x, t) = −
∆k ϕ(x, t)+V (x)ϕ(x, t) Schrödinger equation
∂t
2mk
k=1
Born’s law ρ = |ϕ|2
Born’s law ρ = |ϕ|2
• Consider an ensemble of subsystems each having effective wave
function ϕ
Born’s law ρ = |ϕ|2
• Consider an ensemble of subsystems each having effective wave
function ϕ
• Theorem: PΨ -typically the empirical distribution ρ of X -values is
≈ |ϕ|2
Born’s law ρ = |ϕ|2
• Consider an ensemble of subsystems each having effective wave
function ϕ
• Theorem: PΨ -typically the empirical distribution ρ of X -values is
≈ |ϕ|2
• In short: Quantum Equilibrium holds!
Hydrogene ground state: ρ = |ψ0 |2 ,
0
v ψ0 = 0
two slit experiment, computed trajectories
computer simulation of Bohmian trajectories by Chris Dewdney
1
kx/k
0.5
−0.5
−1
m
−3
x 10
1
two slit experiment: weak measurement of phase, trajectories
reconstructed
kx/k
0.5
0
momentum of the photons reaching any particular position in the image plane, and, by repeating this procedure in a series of planes, we can
reconstruct trajectories over that range. In this
sense, weak measurement finally allows us to
speak about what happens to an ensemble of
particles inside an interferometer.
Our quantum particles are single photons
emitted by a liquid helium-cooled InGaAs quantum dot (23, 24) embedded in a GaAs/AlAs micropillar cavity. The dot is optically pumped by a
CW laser at 810 nm and emits single photons at
−0.5
−1
5
ate [mm]
photon counts) of
omponents of |y〉,
d and blue curves),
m values calculated
imaging planes at
z = 5.6 m, and (D)
ata points are the
background subentum values were
fect of Poissonian
he magenta curve
ned from enforcing
between adjacent
e-grained averags, the probabilityre not as sensitive
um values to highern with steep mo-
Fig. 3. The reconstructed
average trajectories of an
4
ensemble of single photons
in the double-slit apparatus. The trajectories are re2
constructed over the range
2.75 T 0.05 to 8.2 T 0.1 m
by using the momentum data
0
(black points in Fig. 2) from
41 imaging planes. Here,
−2
80 trajectories are shown.
To reconstruct a set of trajectories, we determined the
−4
weak momentum values for
the transverse x positions at
the initial plane. On the basis
−6
of this initial position and
momentum information, the
3000
4000
5000
6000
7000
8000
x position on the subsequent
Propagation distance[mm]
imaging plane that each
trajectory lands is calculated, and the measured weak momentum value kx at this point found. This
process is repeated until the final imaging plane is reached and the trajectories are traced out. If a
trajectory lands on a point that is not the center of a pixel, then a cubic spline interpolation between
neighboring momentum values is used.
Transverse coordinate[mm]
0
to the initial uncertainty in pointer position, so
that significant information is acquired in a single
shot. However, this implies that the pointer momentum must be very uncertain, and it is this
uncertainty that creates the uncontrollable, irreversible disturbance associated with measurement.
In a “weak” measurement, the pointer shift is
small and little information can be gained on a
single shot; but, on the other hand, there may be
arbitrarily little disturbance imparted to the system. It is possible to subsequently postselect the
system on a desired final state. Postselecting on
Downloaded from www.science
−3
x 10
S.Kocsis et al: Observing the Average Trajectories of Single Photons in a
Two-Slit Interferometer. Science 2011
www.sciencemag.org
SCIENCE
VOL 332
3 JUNE 2011
1171
operational analysis of BM: PVM’s
system (X , ϕ) and apparatus (Y , Φ) with pointer positions Yα pointing
towards value α. Suppose
then for ϕ =
=⇒
P
α cα ϕα ,
ϕΦ
ϕα Φ
P
Schrödinger evolution
α
−→
|cα |2 = 1
Schrödinger evolution
−→
Ψ=
ϕα Φα
X
α
cα ϕα Φα
operational analysis of BM: PVM’s
system (X , ϕ) and apparatus (Y , Φ) with pointer positions Yα pointing
towards value α. Suppose
then for ϕ =
P
α cα ϕα ,
ϕΦ
ϕα Φ
P
Schrödinger evolution
α
−→
|cα |2 = 1
Schrödinger evolution
−→
Ψ=
ϕα Φα
X
cα ϕα Φα
α
=⇒
• If Y ∈ suppΦβ then ϕβ is new effective wave function for system
(effective wave function collapse)
operational analysis of BM: PVM’s
system (X , ϕ) and apparatus (Y , Φ) with pointer positions Yα pointing
towards value α. Suppose
then for ϕ =
P
α cα ϕα ,
ϕΦ
ϕα Φ
P
Schrödinger evolution
α
−→
|cα |2 = 1
Schrödinger evolution
−→
Ψ=
ϕα Φα
X
cα ϕα Φα
α
=⇒
• If Y ∈ suppΦβ then ϕβ is new effective wave function for system
(effective wave function collapse)
• the ϕα ’s form an orthogonal family (⇒ PVM)
operational analysis of BM: PVM’s
system (X , ϕ) and apparatus (Y , Φ) with pointer positions Yα pointing
towards value α. Suppose
then for ϕ =
P
α cα ϕα ,
ϕΦ
ϕα Φ
P
Schrödinger evolution
α
−→
|cα |2 = 1
Schrödinger evolution
−→
Ψ=
ϕα Φα
X
cα ϕα Φα
α
=⇒
• If Y ∈ suppΦβ then ϕβ is new effective wave function for system
(effective wave function collapse)
• the ϕα ’s form an orthogonal family (⇒ PVM)
• Probϕ (β) = Probϕ (Y ∈ suppΦβ ) = |cβ |2 = |hϕ|ϕβ i|2
operational analysis of BM: PVM’s
system (X , ϕ) and apparatus (Y , Φ) with pointer positions Yα pointing
towards value α. Suppose
then for ϕ =
P
α cα ϕα ,
ϕΦ
ϕα Φ
P
Schrödinger evolution
α
−→
|cα |2 = 1
Schrödinger evolution
−→
Ψ=
ϕα Φα
X
cα ϕα Φα
α
=⇒
• If Y ∈ suppΦβ then ϕβ is new effective wave function for system
(effective wave function collapse)
• the ϕα ’s form an orthogonal family (⇒ PVM)
• Probϕ (β) = Probϕ (Y ∈ suppΦβ ) = |cβ |2 = |hϕ|ϕβ i|2
• PVM ⇒ self adjoint  =
the experiment
P
α|ϕα ihϕα | encodes all relevant data for
operational analysis: POVMs
Suppose not ϕα Φ
Schrödinger evolution
−→
ϕα Φα
but apparatus (Y , ψ) with values
F (Y ) = λ ∈ Λ
then probability for pointer position if system’s wave function is ϕ
Probϕ (A) := PΦT (F −1 (A)) , A ⊂ Λ
can be written as
= hϕ|
Z
A
d λ|φλ ihφλ ||ϕi
where in general hφλ |φν i =
6 δλ,ν (overcomplete set)
Z
d λ|φλ ihφλ |, A ⊂ Λ
A
is called POVM or generalised observable
Heisenberg’s uncertainty relation follows from BM
Equivariance of ρ = |ϕ|2
∂|ϕ(x, t)|2
= −divv ϕ (x, t)|ϕ(x, t)|2 =⇒
∂t
Eϕ (f (X (t)) = Eϕ(t) (f (X ))
Heisenberg’s uncertainty relation follows from BM
Equivariance of ρ = |ϕ|2
∂|ϕ(x, t)|2
= −divv ϕ (x, t)|ϕ(x, t)|2 =⇒
∂t
Eϕ (f (X (t)) = Eϕ(t) (f (X ))
Heisenberg’s uncertainty relation follows from BM
Equivariance of ρ = |ϕ|2
∂|ϕ(x, t)|2
= −divv ϕ (x, t)|ϕ(x, t)|2 =⇒
∂t
Eϕ (f (X (t)) = Eϕ(t) (f (X ))
⇓ by analysis
m
m X (t)
L
V∞ := lim
t→∞ ~
~
t
is distributed according to |ϕ̂|2
Heisenberg’s uncertainty relation follows from BM
Equivariance of ρ = |ϕ|2
∂|ϕ(x, t)|2
= −divv ϕ (x, t)|ϕ(x, t)|2 =⇒
∂t
Eϕ (f (X (t)) = Eϕ(t) (f (X ))
⇓ by analysis
m
m X (t)
L
V∞ := lim
t→∞ ~
~
t
P̂ =
Z
is distributed according to |ϕ̂|2
⇓
dkk|kihk|
momentum observable
empirical import: (X (t), ϕ) for interesting ϕ
empirical import: (X (t), ϕ) for interesting ϕ
• classical limit
empirical import: (X (t), ϕ) for interesting ϕ
• classical limit
Bohmian trajectories approximately Newtonian
empirical import: (X (t), ϕ) for interesting ϕ
• classical limit
Bohmian trajectories approximately Newtonian
• measurement of ϕ
empirical import: (X (t), ϕ) for interesting ϕ
• classical limit
Bohmian trajectories approximately Newtonian
• measurement of ϕ
measurement
|ϕ|2 through measuring X , phase by weak
empirical import: (X (t), ϕ) for interesting ϕ
• classical limit
Bohmian trajectories approximately Newtonian
• measurement of ϕ
measurement
|ϕ|2 through measuring X , phase by weak
• statistics of (arrival) time
empirical import: (X (t), ϕ) for interesting ϕ
• classical limit
Bohmian trajectories approximately Newtonian
• measurement of ϕ
measurement
|ϕ|2 through measuring X , phase by weak
• statistics of (arrival) time
empirical import: (X (t), ϕ) for interesting ϕ
• classical limit
Bohmian trajectories approximately Newtonian
• measurement of ϕ
measurement
|ϕ|2 through measuring X , phase by weak
• statistics of (arrival) time
empirical import: (X (t), ϕ) for interesting ϕ
• classical limit
Bohmian trajectories approximately Newtonian
• measurement of ϕ
measurement
|ϕ|2 through measuring X , phase by weak
• statistics of (arrival) time
for good wave functions good statistics
arrival time statistics
G
supp ! 0
arrival time statistics
G
supp ! 0
when and where does a counter click?
time statistics for Bohmian flow
Pψ (X (τ ) ∈ dS, τ ∈ dt) = v ψ |ψ|2 · dSdt = j ψ · dSdt
scattering formalism and scattering cross section
Born’s scattering formula for single particle
16.7 The Scattering Cross-Section
373
#R
BEAM
!
R
x1
#
A
"#
x3
V
k1
k0
k3
x2
supp !
k2
Fig. 16.6 Schematic representation of a scattering experiment. Also shown at the bottom is the
support of the Fourier transform of the wave function y , which is a member of a beam of identical
wave functions impinging on the target. See the text for further explanation
it to compute the probability of scattering into the cone CS (see Remark 16.2). But
since we already have the the crucial formula (16.56) for the crossing probability,
which directly connects with the clicks in the detector, we shall now go on with that
scattering formalism and scattering cross section
Born’s scattering formula for single particle
16.7 The Scattering Cross-Section
373
#R
BEAM
!
R
x1
#
A
"#
x3
V
k1
k0
k3
x2
supp !
k2
Fig. 16.6 Schematic representation of a scattering experiment. Also shown at the bottom is the
R large
support of the Fourier transform of the wave function
y , which is a member of a beam of identical
ψ
2
wave functions impinging
R on the target. See the text for further explanation
in
P (X (τ ) ∈ Σ , τ ∈ [0, ∞))
≈
R
CΣ
dkhk|Sψ i
it to compute the probability of scattering into the cone CS (see Remark 16.2). But
since we already have the the crucial formula (16.56) for the crossing probability,
which directly connects with the clicks in the detector, we shall now go on with that
which in the limit R → ∞ should become (1).
In Bohmian mechanics the joint probability (2) is readily defined, where P is the measure Pψ on the
particles’ initial positions with density |ψ|2 . By virtue of the continuity of Bohmian trajectories, first
B
crossing times through boundaries of regions in space are well defined. Let texl,R be the first exit time of
Bl,R
3
the lth particle from the ball xl < R then X ψ
(x
,
t
)
∈
R
is
the
position
of the lth particle at this
0 ex
l
time (see Figure 1). We shall show that
#
# $
$2
!
"
Bl,R
$%
$
(3)
lim Pψ X ψ
...
$ψout (k)$ d3 k1 · · · d3 kN .
l (x0 , tex ) ∈ RΣl ∀ l ∈ {1, . . . , N } =
many particle scattering
R→∞
C Σ1
C ΣN
RΣ
1
B
1,R
Xψ
1 (x0 , tex )
Σ1
supp ψ
x0,2
x0,1
S2
Target
RS 2
Σ2
RΣ
2
B
2,R
Xψ
2 (x0 , tex )
Figure 1. Sketch of the scattering situation for N = 2.
The idea for proving (3) is rather simple: Far away from the scattering center, the particles’ trajectories
become more or less straight lines directed along the asymptotic velocity
vψ
∞ (x0 ) := lim
t→∞
%
2
1
X ψ (x0 , t)
,
t
which in the limit R → ∞ should become (1).
In Bohmian mechanics the joint probability (2) is readily defined, where P is the measure Pψ on the
particles’ initial positions with density |ψ|2 . By virtue of the continuity of Bohmian trajectories, first
B
crossing times through boundaries of regions in space are well defined. Let texl,R be the first exit time of
Bl,R
3
the lth particle from the ball xl < R then X ψ
(x
,
t
)
∈
R
is
the
position
of the lth particle at this
0 ex
l
time (see Figure 1). We shall show that
#
# $
$2
!
"
Bl,R
$%
$
(3)
lim Pψ X ψ
...
$ψout (k)$ d3 k1 · · · d3 kN .
l (x0 , tex ) ∈ RΣl ∀ l ∈ {1, . . . , N } =
many particle scattering
R→∞
C Σ1
C ΣN
RΣ
1
B
1,R
Xψ
1 (x0 , tex )
Σ1
supp ψ
x0,2
x0,1
S2
Target
RS 2
Σ2
RΣ
2
B
2,R
Xψ
2 (x0 , tex )
Figure 1. Sketch of the scattering situation for N = 2.
”genuine” Bohmian analysis
The idea for proving (3) is rather simple: Far away from the scattering center, the particles’ trajectories
become more or less straight lines directed along the asymptotic velocity
vψ
∞ (x0 ) := lim
t→∞
%
2
1
X ψ (x0 , t)
,
t
Gretchen Frage: Wie hältst du es mit der Relativität?
Relativistic Bohmian Theory
Weinberg’s challenge
Gretchen Frage: Wie hältst du es mit der Relativität?
Relativistic Bohmian Theory
Weinberg’s challenge
It does not seem possible to extend Bohm’s version of quantum
mechanics to theories in which particles can be created and destroyed,
which includes all known relativistic quantum theories. (Steven Weinberg
to Shelly Goldstein, 1996)
Why should it be problematic to have particles created or
destroyed?
Why should it be problematic to have particles created or
destroyed?
• philosophically not possible?
Why should it be problematic to have particles created or
destroyed?
• philosophically not possible?
• technically, i.e. mathematically not possible?
Why should it be problematic to have particles created or
destroyed?
• philosophically not possible?
• technically, i.e. mathematically not possible?
• not possible in a deterministic theory of particles in motion?
Creation and Annihilation, the configuration space
S∞
Q: configuration space Q = n=0 Q(n) (disjoint union)
a) Q(0) no particle b) Q(1) one particle
c) Q(2) two particles d) Q(3) three particles
(a)
(b)
Q(t2−)
Q(t1−)
Q(t2+)
(c)
Q(t1+)
(d)
The LAW: equivariant Markov Process
The LAW: equivariant Markov Process
• guiding field Ψ ∈ F, a Fock space
The LAW: equivariant Markov Process
• guiding field Ψ ∈ F, a Fock space
• P(dq): positive-operator-valued measure (POVM) on Q acting on
F so that the probability that the systems particles in the state Ψ
are in dq at time t is
Pt (dq) = hΨt |P(dq)|Ψt i
The LAW: equivariant Markov Process
• guiding field Ψ ∈ F, a Fock space
• P(dq): positive-operator-valued measure (POVM) on Q acting on
F so that the probability that the systems particles in the state Ψ
are in dq at time t is
Pt (dq) = hΨt |P(dq)|Ψt i
• For a Hamiltonian H (e.g. quantum field Hamiltonian)
∂Ψt
= HΨt −→
∂t
d Pt (dq)
2
= Im hΨt |P(dq)H|Ψt i .
dt
~
i~
The LAW: equivariant Markov Process
• guiding field Ψ ∈ F, a Fock space
• P(dq): positive-operator-valued measure (POVM) on Q acting on
F so that the probability that the systems particles in the state Ψ
are in dq at time t is
Pt (dq) = hΨt |P(dq)|Ψt i
• For a Hamiltonian H (e.g. quantum field Hamiltonian)
∂Ψt
= HΨt −→
∂t
d Pt (dq)
2
= Im hΨt |P(dq)H|Ψt i .
dt
~
• Find ”minimal” generator so that (rewrite left hand side, so that)
i~
d Pt (dq)
= Lt Pt (dq) .
dt
(Minimal) Markovian Process: Flow, (No) Diffusion, (Only as much
as necessary) Jumps
Quantum field Hamiltonians provide rates for configuration
jumps
Generator for pure Jump-Process
Z (Lρ)(dq) =
σ(dq|q 0 )ρ(dq 0 ) − σ(dq 0 |q)ρ(dq)
q 0 ∈Q
H = H0 + HI
L = L0 + LI
HI is often an Integral-Operator −→ Jump-Generator given by rates
σ(dq|q 0 ) =
[(2/~) Im hΨ|P(dq)HI P(dq 0 )|Ψi]+
.
hΨ|P(dq 0 )|Ψi
The tension with relativity challenge: Einstein’s criticism of
QM
The tension with relativity challenge: Einstein’s criticism of
QM
Nature is nonlocal, the wave function is the nonlocal agent, Bohmian
Mechanics takes the wave function seriously: it needs for its formulation
a simultaneity structure, e.g. a foliation F which seems to be against
the spirit of relativity
The tension with relativity challenge: Einstein’s criticism of
QM
Nature is nonlocal, the wave function is the nonlocal agent, Bohmian
Mechanics takes the wave function seriously: it needs for its formulation
a simultaneity structure, e.g. a foliation F which seems to be against
the spirit of relativity
Possible relief: The foliation F Ψ is given by the wave function, e.g.
defined by a time like vector field induced by the wave function.
Covariance is expressed by the commutative diagram
Ψ −−−−→ F Ψ



Λ
Ug y
y g
(1)
0
Ψ0 −−−−→ F Ψ .
Here the natural action Λg on the foliation is the action of Lorentzian g
on any leaf Σ of the foliation F Ψ .
to which end...
to which end...
• non commutativity of observables is a simple consequence of BM
to which end...
• non commutativity of observables is a simple consequence of BM
• nonlocality of nature is manifest in BM
to which end...
• non commutativity of observables is a simple consequence of BM
• nonlocality of nature is manifest in BM
• BM is in Bell’s sense a theory like Maxwell-theory of
electromagnetism: theorems instead of a cornucopia of axioms
to which end...
• non commutativity of observables is a simple consequence of BM
• nonlocality of nature is manifest in BM
• BM is in Bell’s sense a theory like Maxwell-theory of
electromagnetism: theorems instead of a cornucopia of axioms
• the challenge BM offers: Dirac divided the difficulties of quantum
theory in two classes
to which end...
• non commutativity of observables is a simple consequence of BM
• nonlocality of nature is manifest in BM
• BM is in Bell’s sense a theory like Maxwell-theory of
electromagnetism: theorems instead of a cornucopia of axioms
• the challenge BM offers: Dirac divided the difficulties of quantum
theory in two classes
• First class difficulties are those which have to do with the
measurement problem–how do facts arise?
to which end...
• non commutativity of observables is a simple consequence of BM
• nonlocality of nature is manifest in BM
• BM is in Bell’s sense a theory like Maxwell-theory of
electromagnetism: theorems instead of a cornucopia of axioms
• the challenge BM offers: Dirac divided the difficulties of quantum
theory in two classes
• First class difficulties are those which have to do with the
measurement problem–how do facts arise?
• Second class difficulties are those which have to do with singularities
in field theories (self energy, Dirac vacuum, ...)
to which end...
• non commutativity of observables is a simple consequence of BM
• nonlocality of nature is manifest in BM
• BM is in Bell’s sense a theory like Maxwell-theory of
electromagnetism: theorems instead of a cornucopia of axioms
• the challenge BM offers: Dirac divided the difficulties of quantum
theory in two classes
• First class difficulties are those which have to do with the
measurement problem–how do facts arise?
• Second class difficulties are those which have to do with singularities
in field theories (self energy, Dirac vacuum, ...)
• BM solves first class difficulties – it encourages the search for
relativistic interacting theories which are mathematically coherent
from the start
to which end...
• non commutativity of observables is a simple consequence of BM
• nonlocality of nature is manifest in BM
• BM is in Bell’s sense a theory like Maxwell-theory of
electromagnetism: theorems instead of a cornucopia of axioms
• the challenge BM offers: Dirac divided the difficulties of quantum
theory in two classes
• First class difficulties are those which have to do with the
measurement problem–how do facts arise?
• Second class difficulties are those which have to do with singularities
in field theories (self energy, Dirac vacuum, ...)
• BM solves first class difficulties – it encourages the search for
relativistic interacting theories which are mathematically coherent
from the start
• a guiding example is
Gauss-Weber-Tetrode-Fokker-Schwarzschild-Wheeler-Feynman direct
interaction theory. Fully relativistic and without fields (my friends
Shelly and Nino are not enthusiastic about that theory, my young
friends are and future is theirs)
the end: perhaps more on the solutions of second class
difficulties in 25 years