* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download INTRODUCTION TO MECHANICS Introduction On the face of it
Bell test experiments wikipedia , lookup
Quantum decoherence wikipedia , lookup
Molecular Hamiltonian wikipedia , lookup
Quantum computing wikipedia , lookup
Dirac bracket wikipedia , lookup
Bra–ket notation wikipedia , lookup
Identical particles wikipedia , lookup
Quantum machine learning wikipedia , lookup
Hydrogen atom wikipedia , lookup
Coherent states wikipedia , lookup
Orchestrated objective reduction wikipedia , lookup
Bohr–Einstein debates wikipedia , lookup
Wave–particle duality wikipedia , lookup
Quantum electrodynamics wikipedia , lookup
Particle in a box wikipedia , lookup
Quantum field theory wikipedia , lookup
Renormalization wikipedia , lookup
Quantum group wikipedia , lookup
Matter wave wikipedia , lookup
Many-worlds interpretation wikipedia , lookup
Double-slit experiment wikipedia , lookup
Quantum key distribution wikipedia , lookup
Density matrix wikipedia , lookup
Theoretical and experimental justification for the Schrödinger equation wikipedia , lookup
Quantum entanglement wikipedia , lookup
Relativistic quantum mechanics wikipedia , lookup
Copenhagen interpretation wikipedia , lookup
Bell's theorem wikipedia , lookup
Probability amplitude wikipedia , lookup
Topological quantum field theory wikipedia , lookup
Quantum teleportation wikipedia , lookup
Renormalization group wikipedia , lookup
History of quantum field theory wikipedia , lookup
Scalar field theory wikipedia , lookup
Symmetry in quantum mechanics wikipedia , lookup
Measurement in quantum mechanics wikipedia , lookup
EPR paradox wikipedia , lookup
Interpretations of quantum mechanics wikipedia , lookup
Quantum state wikipedia , lookup
Hidden variable theory wikipedia , lookup
INTRODUCTION TO MECHANICS SEAN POHORENCE Introduction On the face of it, particle mechanics is the study of the simplest physical systems. However, this seemingly trivial task leads to some surprising consequences and some deep mathematics. At the quantum level, there are still large gaps in our mathematical understanding of these systems. In this talk, I hope to give a small taste of these areas and why one should be interested in studying them. For a comprehensive reference to the material covered, see Quantum Mechanics for Mathematicians by Leon Takhtajan. If you want to go from zero knowledge to solving problems quickly (and are okay with neglecting some of the mathematical details), I recommend Introduction to Quantum Mechanics by David Griffiths. 1. Classical Mechanics First, we give a brief introduction to the theory of classical mechanics. This will motivate our approach to quantum mechanics in the next section. 1.1. Principal of Least Action. We will study the motion of a point particle through space. This is described by a (smooth) map x : [0, 1] → M, [0, 1] 3 t 7→ x(t) ∈ M where M is a manifold which represents the space in which the particle moves. The image of this map is a path traced out in space. The graph of this map is a path in spacetime. In order to describe the dynamics of the system, i.e. the shape of this graph, we first specify a functional S : C ∞ ([0, 1], M ) → R which assigns to every path a real number. We require that R 1 this functional is “local”1 which we can think of as requiring S is of the form 0 L dt where L is a function depending only on the first k derivatives of x(t) at each time t. In this talk, we will only look at the case when k = 1. We think of this action as determining the “cost” of each path, so physical systems will seek to minimize this action. Thus, we may say that allowable classical paths x(t) must be critical points of the action. This formalism is conceptually nice because it is relatively easy to explain. However, it is not especially easy to actually compute the critical points of an arbitrary R1 action from this definition. As an example, let S = 0 21 ẋ2 dt. Here, we can see that the global minimum of the action is clearly achieved when ẋ = 0, i.e. when x(t) = p ∈ M is the contant path. It is not as obvious that any path with constant velocity will be a critical point of this action. It turns out that the local nature of 1An example of a non-local functional could be something that counted the total number of times the path x(t) crosses itself, or some other global behavior. 1 2 SEAN POHORENCE the action allows us to describe the dynamics of a classical particle in a different manner in which the above example becomes very easy. 1.2. States, Observables, Measurement, and Dynamics. We begin with a question: given a path x(t) in Rn , how much information do we need to specify the motion of our particle starting from any point on the path, x(t0 )? Thinking of an example where the path crosses itself, it is clear that we must know both the position x(t0 ) and the velocity ẋ(t0 ) in order to uniquely specify the motion at x(t0 ). But is this enough? We could similarly dream up a situation in which the path passes tangent to itself at x(t0 ), so we would need to additionally specify the second time derivative at t0 to uniquely determine the motion. We could also continue this process, producing curves whose first kth order derivates all agreed at the point x(t0 ), meaning we would need to specify the first k + 1 time derivatives of x(t) at t0 . This situation seems quite grim, since for very badly behaved paths we would need to provide an infinite amount of initial data to know how our particle would move from an arbitrary point x(t0 ). Luckily, the locality of the action ensures that for physical paths (those which are critical points of the action), the situation R1 will never be so bad. In fact, if the action is of the form 0 L dt where L depends on the first k derivates of x(t), then it will be possible to uniquely specify the motion of the particle by supplying initial conditions consisting of the position x(t0 ) and the first k time derivatives of x(t) at t0 for any t0 ∈ [0, 1]. In particular, when k = 1, we may completely determine the behavior of the particle from any starting point x(t0 ) by supplying initial position and velocity conditions. In other words, for any physical path x(t) ∈ Rn , the path (x(t), ẋ(t)) ∈ R2n , will never cross itself.2 R1 As a summary of the above, given an action S = 0 L(x, ẋ)dt and the initial conditions (x(0), ẋ(0)) ∈ R2n , we may specify the motion of our particle for all t ∈ [0, 1] uniquely. Using calculus of variations, we can justify this statement by showing that the classical paths x(t) must satisfy n second order differential equations which are called the Euler-Lagrange equations of the system. The initial conditions (x(0), ẋ(0)) then uniquely specify a solution to the Euler-Lagrange equations. This is known as the Lagrangian description of classical mechanics. The result above contains all the key ideas you will need to know about classical mechanics for this talk. Here, we make some superficial changes which will allow us to present those ideas in a form which parallels the constructions in quantum mechanics which will follow. The details are not important for our purposes, so will be omitted for the most part. In the above, we considered the function L : R2n → R, R2n 3 (x, ẋ) 7→ L(x, ẋ) ∈ R. Applying the Legendre transform τL associated with L to R2n gives us a new function H(x, p) on the space R2n , now taken with coordinates (x, p).3 In particular, the Legendre transform acts by ∂L (x, ẋ) 7→ x, ∂ ẋ 2For an arbitrary manifold M , this will be a path in the tangent bundle T M . 3For a general M the Legendre transformation is a bundle morphism T M → T ∗ M . INTRODUCTION TO MECHANICS 3 and ∂L − L(x, ẋ). ∂ ẋ We call R2n with these coordinates phase-space and think of x as the position of the particle and p as its momentum. Similarly to in the Lagrangian description, the coordinates (x, p) uniquely determine classical paths in the sense that these paths do not cross themselves in phase space. For this reason, we call the pair (x, p), the state of the particle. We may think of smooth functions on phase-space as observables and define the concept of measurement as a map H ◦ τL = ẋ States × Observables = R2n × C ∞ (R2n ) → R which simply sends ((x, p), f ) 7→ f (x, p). Two easy examples are the function x̂ defined by (x, p) 7→ x and the function p̂ defined by (x, p) 7→ p. In this case, measurement of the observable x̂ just gives the position of the particle, and measurement of the observable p̂ gives the momentum of the particle. For this reason, we typically call x̂ the position and p̂ the momentum (and usually omit the hat). As in the Lagrangian description, dynamics are controlled by a set of differential equations. In particular, we require that d f (t) = {H, f (t)} dt ∂f ∂H ∂f for any observable f , where {H, f } := ∂H ∂x ∂p − ∂p ∂x is the Poisson bracket (it is clearly a skew symmetric map { , } : C ∞ (R2n ) × C ∞ (R2n ) → C ∞ (R2n ), and it turns out that the functions C ∞ (R2n ) equipped with the Poisson bracket form a Lie algebra). In the special cases when f is the position or momentum, we obtain ẋ = ∂H , ∂p ṗ = − ∂H ∂x which go by the name of Hamilton’s equations of motion. This formulation is called the Hamiltonian description of classical mechanics.4 It is worth noting that the above notation implies that the function H is an observable of the system. H is called the Hamiltonian of the system, and the observable quantity it measures is the energy of the system. 1.3. Examples. We start with the example given above, which, in the Hamiltonian 2 description, is given by H = p2 . The equations of motion are then ṗ = 0 and ẋ = p, so this describes a particle moving with constant velocity p. An essential example, which is equally important in the quantum case, is the harmonic oscillator in one dimension (so phase-space is just R2 ), which is given by Hamiltonian H = 21 (p2 + x2 ). It has equations of motion given by ẋ = p and ṗ = −x, i.e. the orbits in phase-space are circles. These equations describe any system with quadratic potential, for example a particle attached to a spring. 4One may note that the proper setting for the Hamiltonian formalism is in symplectic geometry. In this case, we take space to be a smooth manifold M and phase space to be T ∗ M equipped with the canonical symplectic form ω = −dη. Then, to each observable f ∈ C ∞ (T ∗ M ), we may associate a Hamiltonian vector field Xf which satisfies df = ιXf ω (note that the non-degeneracy of ω ensures this is well defined). Then, we may define the Poisson bracket by {f, g} := ω(Xf , Xg ). f, defining M f to be the In fact, we may apply this construction to any symplectic manifold M phase-space of the classical system. 4 SEAN POHORENCE 2. Quantum Mechanics 2.1. Motivation. Now, let’s try to turn the ideas above into a quantum theory. We will need this theory to agree with experimental results, in particular, the way we describe measurements must agree with experimental observations. This gives us two goals for the theory: (1) The order of measurements matters. (2) In the “classical limit” the theory agrees with the classical theory. Many “paradoxes” in experimental results can be boiled down to this first property. For instance, in the double slit experiment, we see that making a preliminary measurement by checking which slit particles pass through changes the subsequent measurement of the distribution of particles on the detector.5 We may say that a potentially viable quantum theory will consist of a map between the classical observables introduced above to some new quantum observables, along with a (possibly new) concept of states. Moreover, we should include a method for making measurements. Crucially, we should require that these measurements depend on a parameter that controls the “quantum-ness” of the system and reproduces the above results as this parameter tends to zero. 2.2. States, Observables, Measurement, and Dynamics. Before giving an actual construction of quantum mechanics, we provide an axiomatic definition of how such a theory behaves. The first step is to define the building blocks of the theory. States. While classical states were simply points in an even dimensional Euclidean space (or, more generally, a symplectic manifold), we define states in the quantum theory to be elements of a complex Hilbert space H with norm 1 (i.e. elements of the projectivization PH). Observables. Classically, observables were functions on the state space. Here, we define the quantum observables to be self-adjoint linear operators on H. That is, elements O ∈ End(H) satisfying hOϕ, ψi = hϕ, Oψi where h , i is the inner product on H. We denote the (real) vector space of self-adjoint linear operators on H by BH . Note that these operators will not, in general, be compact or even bounded. Measurement. The first attempt to define measurement proceeds as follows. Pretend that any observable in H. Then, we see that for any state, P∞O is diagonalizable P∞ ϕ, we have Oϕ = O ( i=1 ci ei ) = i=1 λi ci ei where ci = hϕ, ei i and the λi are the eigenvalues of O in the {ei } basis, where we take this basis to be orthonormal. Then, for the special case where ϕ = ei for some i, we may say that the measurement of the observable O of ϕ, denoted (O, ϕ), will be λi (since O is self-adjoint, this is a real number). For general ϕ, we define measurement in a non-deterministic way. Generalizing the special case above, we say that the measurement (O, ϕ) will 2 result P∞ in 2a value of λi with probability |ci | (note that since ||ϕ|| =P1,∞ we have 2 i=1 λi |ci | . i=1 |ci | = 1). The expected value of the measurement is given by This says that, a priori, the state of the system does not completely determine the results of measurements as it did in the classical case. However, once a measurement is made, it must result in a given value, so we say that making a measurement resulting in value λi also changes the state of the system to the corresponding ei . 5See http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Double-slit_experiment. INTRODUCTION TO MECHANICS 5 This is where the possibility for the ordering of measurements to matter is built in, since the act of making a measurement may alter the state of the system. However, the assumption that O is diagonalizable in H will not always be correct. Two of the most important operators in the model of quantum mechanics we will introduce below do not have any eigenstates in the corresponding Hilbert space. Thus, we need to modify our definition of measurement to accomodate for these types of operators. The key to this will be to relax how precise the result of a measurement is. For any measurement (O, ϕ) instead of assigning probabilities to any one given value, we will assign probabilities to all ranges of values [a, b] that the measurement may take (we see the above is a specific case of this where we only worry about intervals [a, a]). In other words, to any measurement, we R associate a measure µ on R. The expected value of the measurement is given by R x dµ(x). In the description above, we said that the state of a system “collapses” after making a measurement in such a way that subsequent measurements will result in the same value with probability one.6 In the case where measurements are no longer exact, we say that if the result of a measurement (O, ϕ) is an interval [a, b] that the state will collapse in such a way that subsequent measurements will lie within that range with probability one. Exactly how this manifests itself in terms of a general model of quantum mechanics is more technical than our previous construction, so we instead postpone these details until we have a concrete model to work with. Quantization and Dynamics. With these building blocks, we may now define what a model of quantum mechanics actually is. Here, we will only discuss models which come up as the quantization of a classical model.7 Given such a classical model consisting of a Lie algebra of observables (A, { , }), we define a quantization to consist of a choice of Hilbert space H and an bijective map of sets Q~ : A → BH which depends on a parmeter ~. Note that on BH the operation i[ , ], where [O1 , O2 ] = O1 O2 − O2 O1 is the commutator of operators, is well defined (i.e. i times the commutator of two self-adjoint operators is self-adjoint).8 We require that this map satisfies the following lim [Q~ (f ), Q~ (g)] = 0, ~→0 and i [Q~ (f ), Q~ (g)]. ~ The first condition means that as ~ → 0, the quantum observables commute. The second condition means that as ~ → 0 the map Q~ takes Poisson brackets to ~i times the commutator (i.e. Q~ becomes an isomorphism of Lie algebras). Thus, in this limit, we obtain a commutative algebra of observables isomorphic to the original one, so it reproduces the classical theory. For this reason, this is called the classical limit of the quantum theory. We define the dynamics of the quantum system in an analogy with the classical case. Namely, given a classical Hamiltonian Hcl , we define the quantum Hamiltonian H := Q~ (Hcl ) and specify that the time evolution of a quantum observable O lim Q~ ({f, g}) = lim ~→0 ~→0 6When we say that subsequent measurements will result in the same value with probability one, we imagine these measurements occurring immediately after the first. If the system is allowed to evolve for some time after the first measurement, this will no longer be true. 7Not all quantum theories arise in this way. 8In fact, this turns the vector space of self-adjoint operators into a Lie algebra. 6 SEAN POHORENCE is given by9 d i O(t) = [H, O(t)]. dt ~ 2.3. A Model of Quantum Mechanics. The model we will describe is a quantization of a one dimensional classical system. In particular, we consider a system with phase space R2 with coordinates (x, p) and Hamiltonian Hcl = 21 p2 + V (x) where V (x) is a polynomial function in the position. To quantize this system, we set our Hilbert space H to be L2 (R), the space of square integrable complex-valued functions on the real line, with inner product given by Z ϕψ dx. hϕ, ψi := R Here, we only provide part of the data of a full quantization, but this is actually sufficient to obtain many important results about systems of this type. We define Q~ (x) = mx where mx is the operator defined by multiplication by x and Q~ (p) = d i~ dx . For convenience, we will denote the quantum position operator by X and the quantum momentum operator by P . Here, you might protest that neither of these map all of H into itself. There are a few reasons why this does not create problems. One is that measurements (which will be defined later) will still be well defined on all of H, and these are the only physical parts of the theory. Another is that many of the “important” states in H will be well behaved enough (possibly they will decay exponentially) so that X and P are well defined on them (in fact, X and P are well defined on a dense subspace D ⊂ H). To check that these quantum observables do indeed define a quantization of x and p we may write (for ϕ ∈ D) d ]ϕ = −i~ϕ dx so we see that as ~ → 0, we have [X, P ] → 0 and ~i [X, P ] = 1 = {x, p}. The reason why the quantizations of position and momentum capture so much of this theory is they allow us to write the quantization of the Hamiltonian. That is, we set 1 Q~ (Hcl ) = P 2 + V (X). 2 With this quantum Hamiltonian, we can write down how the dynamics of position and momentum behave, or any other observable once we have defined the full quantization. We should note here that the only reason we could write down H in terms of X and P is that the classical Hamiltonian had no cross terms between x and p. For a general classical observable which is a function of x and p, in order to quantize it we would need to know how to turn a function of commuting variables into a functions on non-commuting variables. [X, P ]ϕ = [x, i~ 9This formulation of quantum mechanics, in which observables vary with time and states are fixed is called the Heisenberg picture. Since the only physical elements of the theory are the results of measurements, which come from a pairing of states and observables, it is also possible to construct a version of the theory where states vary in time while operators are fixed which produces the same physical predictions. This view is called the Schrödinger picture. In the d Schrödinger picture, the time evolution of a state ψ is given by i~ dt ψ = Hψ, which is known as the Schrödinger equation for the state ψ. In particular, if ψ is an eigenvector of H with eigenvalue i d λ, we have i~ dt ψ = λψ so the solution of the Schrödinger equation is ψ(t) = e− ~ λt ψ(0). When it is possible to diagonalize H in H, this resulting solution is often easier to work with than the equations for the time evolution of operators in the Heisenberg picture. INTRODUCTION TO MECHANICS 7 In the special case where V (x) = x2 , this system can actually be solved exactly. In this case, there is an algebraic trick which allows us to diagonalize H in H and obtain the energy eigenstates. From there, we may use the Schrödinger picture formalism to solve for the time evolution of any state (once we have written it in the basis of energy eigenstates). This is a very special property of Hamiltonians of this form (i.e. with kinetic term p2 and quadratic potential V (x)). For most physical Hamiltonians, it turns out that we can approximate the behavior of the corresponding systems using a Hamiltonian with quadratic potential. This is sometimes called the semiclassical approximaiton. We finish our discussion of this model by briefly describing how measurement is defined. For the position operator, we define the probability of the measurement Rb (X, ϕ) belonging to the interval [a, b] is given by the integral a |ϕ|2 dx. That is, we specify that theRmeasure µ on R corresponding to the measurement (X, ϕ) is defined by µ(E) = E |ϕ|2 dx. In order to define measurement for the momentum operator, we first observe that P ϕ = FXϕ where F is the Fourier transform on L2 (R) (possibly up to a constant term).10 In this spirit, we define the probability of Rb a momentum measurement belonging to the interval [a, b] by the integral a |ϕ̂|2 dx where ϕ̂ is the Fourier transform of ϕ. We may also define the collapse of the state resulting from the act of measuring it. For (X, ϕ), we say that after measuring the position in an interval [a, b], the state will take the form Cχ[a,b] ϕ where C is the necessary normalization constant. The definition for (P, ϕ) is similar. 2.4. The Path Integral. We now change gears and discuss one of the more mysterious elements of quantum theory. When we introduced classical mechanics, we started out by defining the principle of least action, which, in turn, led us to the development of Hamiltonian mechanics. When we sought to quantize a classical system, we modeled our approach on the Hamiltonian formulation of classical mechanics. One could ask whether the action principle has a counterpart in the quantum theory. The answer is, in some sense, not quite known. In the formulation of quantum mechanics above, we focused on the Heisenberg picture, in which all the dynamics are encoded in observables and the states are constant in time. As hinted at previously, we may also take the viewpoint that observables should be constant in time while states must evolve according to some differential equation (the Schrödinger equation). In this case, one may ask the following question: give an initial state ψt0 at time t0 , what is the probability of this state evolving to a new state ψt1 and time t1 ? Let U (t) be the time evolution operator so that U (t1 − t0 )ψ0 is the state of the system at time t1 . In particular, U (T ) is of the form e−iHt/~ . Then, given two elements of norm one in a Hilbert space, a natural way to check how similar they are is to take their inner product. Thus, we define the propagator K(ψt0 , t0 ; ψt1 , t1 ) := hψt1 , U (t1 − t0 )ψt0 i. This provides us with a formula, but we still need to do some calculations in order to get a meaningful answer. In special cases, it is possible to write the propagator 10This is not just a coincidence. The relationship between the position and momentum operators is an interesting topic both classically and in the quantum case. In both models, these observables are “complimentary” in the sense that any observable whose braket with both p and x vanishes must be a multiple of the identity. In the quantum regime, this relationship also has consequences in terms of how accurately one can measure position and momentum simultaneously. 8 SEAN POHORENCE down explicitly. Namely, suppose that ψt0 = ψx and ψt1 = ψx0 where ψx is a state completely localized at the position x, i.e. an eigenstate of the position operator with eigenvalue x (of course, these states do not exist, but let’s suspend any skepticism for now). In the case where H = P 2 , the propagator can be solved exactly and written in terms of a Gaussian integral. In the case where H = P 2 + 2 V (X), one may hope that we can write eiHt/~ = eiP t/~ eiV (X)t/~ where the second exponential reduces to just a complex number since ψx is an eigenstate of the position operator, so also of V (X), and the behaviour of the first exponential is the same as above (where V (X) = 0). However, since P and X do not commute, we may not write U (t) in this form. Luckily for us, there is another approach we can try. Instead of trying to compute the entire propagator at once, we can split the time interval [t0 , t1 ] into many smaller intervals partitioned by the times t0 = s0 < s1 < · · · < sn = t1 . Then, we may try to compute each of the intermediate propagators. In the limit where n → ∞ and the separation ∆tj := sj+1 − sj → 0, 2 the above formula holds: eiH∆ti /~ = eiP ∆ti /~ eiV (X)∆ti /~ (this result is called the Lie-Kato-Trotter Product Formula). Of course, when we split the larger propagator into a number of intermediate ones, we have some degrees of freedom added to the problem coming from the choice of the intermediate states ψxi assigned at times si . If we integrate over each of these degrees of freedom, then after some manipulation, the total propagator takes the form ! ! n−1 2 Z n−1 Y xi+1 − xi i X − V (xi ) ∆ti K(ψx , t0 ; ψx0 , t1 ) = lim exp dxi . n→∞ ~ i=0 ∆ti i=1 Now, for each n, we may choose a smooth path x(t) such that x(si ) = xi . Then, where n → ∞, we see that the sum in the exponential becomes Rint1 the limit 2 ( ẋ(t)) − V (x(t)) dt. Writing this integral more compactly as S, and also denott0 Qn−1 ing limn→∞ i=0 dxi by Dx, we may write the propagator as Z i e ~ S(x(t)) Dx {x(t) | x(t0 )=x, x(t1 )=x0 } where the integral is over all paths x(t) such that start at x and end at x0 . Now, this looks very familiar. The term S looks like the classical action of a system with L(x, ẋ) = ẋ2 − V (x). Then, it is tempting to think of this form of the propagator as an “integral over paths” where each path is weighted by an exponential factor depending on how large the classical action of that path is. However, we must emphasize that this is just a rewritten version of the initial formula above, and that it should not be interpreted as any sort of integral over path space.11 This definition of the path integral is just a reinterpretation of the theory developed in the previous section. Why Path Integrals? This conclusion, combined with the difficulty of using this formula to actually compute anything, might lead you to think that the path integral interpretation of quantum mechanics is rather useless. This is why it is very surprising that forgetting the mathematical subtleties and simply assuming the path integral exists as an integral can actually produce sensical results and is 11This can actually be made rigorous by considering the so-called Wiener measure. There has been a lot of energy devoted to providing mathematical definitions of the path integral, especially in quantum field theory where the problem becomes even more difficult. INTRODUCTION TO MECHANICS 9 more useful than our original approach to quantization in certain situations. For example, when the system we are describing has a special kind of symmetry called supersymmetry 12 the ill-defined path integral may become localized and turn into a finite-dimensional integral that can be done in the normal manner. For physicists, this phenomenon is part of the reason why supersymmetric theories behave so nicely and why people would hope that they can make predictions about our universe. For mathematicians, research in supersymmetric quantum mechanics and supersymmetric quantum field theories has actually uncovered links between these physical theories and many areas of mathematics (in particular, geometry and topology). A very different example which emphasizes the importance of this approach, in which the notion of path integral is even harder to define than in the quantum mechanical case, is quantum field theory. Roughly speaking, quantum field theory is a theory that unifies the predictions of quantum mechanics and special relativity. In such a theory, one would like to develop a mathematical framework that is inherently covariant, which means invariant under the symmetries of special relativity. If one simply tries to extend the Hilbert space definition of quantum mechanics to quantum field theory, it is not possible (or at least not easy) to manifestly preserve covariance. It turns out that many results that can be computed will be covariant, but it may seem like a small miracle that this is the case at first glance. The path integral formulation, on the other hand, is inherently covariant. This provides motivation for mathematicians and physicists to find a rigorous definition of the path integral in quantum field theory. Such a definition may shed light on a vast number of questions in theoretical physics. As it currently stands, what such a definition would be, or even if one exists, is an open problem. 12Supersymmetry is a symmetry between even (commuting, bosonic) and odd (anticommuting, fermionic) particles in the theory. In particular, supersymmetry imposes that the theory must be invariant under certain transformations between the even and odd particles.