Download ON THE QUANTUM-CLASSICAL ANALOGIES 1. INTRODUCTION It

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts

Bohr–Einstein debates wikipedia , lookup

Basil Hiley wikipedia , lookup

Instanton wikipedia , lookup

Delayed choice quantum eraser wikipedia , lookup

Renormalization wikipedia , lookup

Renormalization group wikipedia , lookup

Topological quantum field theory wikipedia , lookup

Measurement in quantum mechanics wikipedia , lookup

Quantum decoherence wikipedia , lookup

Particle in a box wikipedia , lookup

Quantum electrodynamics wikipedia , lookup

Probability amplitude wikipedia , lookup

Quantum dot wikipedia , lookup

Aharonov–Bohm effect wikipedia , lookup

Bell's theorem wikipedia , lookup

Wave–particle duality wikipedia , lookup

Quantum fiction wikipedia , lookup

Density matrix wikipedia , lookup

Quantum field theory wikipedia , lookup

Scalar field theory wikipedia , lookup

Orchestrated objective reduction wikipedia , lookup

Hydrogen atom wikipedia , lookup

Copenhagen interpretation wikipedia , lookup

Quantum entanglement wikipedia , lookup

Max Born wikipedia , lookup

Many-worlds interpretation wikipedia , lookup

Double-slit experiment wikipedia , lookup

Relativistic quantum mechanics wikipedia , lookup

Quantum computing wikipedia , lookup

Quantum group wikipedia , lookup

Theoretical and experimental justification for the Schrödinger equation wikipedia , lookup

Coherent states wikipedia , lookup

Path integral formulation wikipedia , lookup

Symmetry in quantum mechanics wikipedia , lookup

EPR paradox wikipedia , lookup

Quantum machine learning wikipedia , lookup

Quantum key distribution wikipedia , lookup

Quantum teleportation wikipedia , lookup

Interpretations of quantum mechanics wikipedia , lookup

Quantum cognition wikipedia , lookup

History of quantum field theory wikipedia , lookup

Quantum state wikipedia , lookup

Hidden variable theory wikipedia , lookup

T-symmetry wikipedia , lookup

Canonical quantization wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
Dedicated to Professor Apolodor Aristotel Răduţă’s 70th Anniversary
ON THE QUANTUM-CLASSICAL ANALOGIES
D. DRAGOMAN
University of Bucharest, Physics Dept., P.O. Box MG-11, 077125 Bucharest-Magurele,
E-mail: [email protected]
Received June 2, 2013
The issue of analogies between classical optics and quantum mechanics is
analyzed in details. The appropriateness and limitations of these analogies are discussed
for both Schrödinger and Dirac type quantum states.
Key words: classical physics, quantum physics, analogies.
1. INTRODUCTION
It is with great pleasure that I contribute to the special issue of Romanian
Journal of Physics, dedicated to the 70th anniversary of Prof. Apolodor Raduta. I
have known Prof. Raduta with the occasion of a research project submission.
Although the project was unsuccessful, it was a great opportunity to meet some
extraordinary people, among them Prof. Raduta.
In this issue I would like to address briefly one of the research issues that is
constantly present throughout my activity: the analogies between the classical and
the quantum worlds. I became interested in this subject when I started to use the
Wigner distribution function (WDF) [1] as a mathematical tool suitable for
describing optical sources and systems. At that moment, I was particularly
intrigued by the affirmation that [2] negative values of the WDF are a signature of
the quantum nature of the system under investigation. I knew that this statement
was wrong because negative values of WDF have been experimentally generated in
classical optics [3-4]. On the other hand, it was quite difficult to convince quantum
physicists of this reality. The reason is at the same time simple and subtle. It is
usually assumed that quantum mechanics is a totally different theory (conceptually
as well as formally) than classical mechanics. Indeed, a quantum particle cannot be
represented by a point in phase space, for example, but by an area that cannot be
less than h due to the uncertainty principle. However, there are classical theories in
Rom. Journ. Phys., Vol. 58, Nos. 9–10, P. 1319–1326, Bucharest, 2013
1320
D. Dragoman
2
physics that share this nonlocal character with quantum mechanics: wave theories,
in particular, optics. An optical beam cannot either be represented by a point in
phase space [5]; only light rays can be represented as such, but light rays are
approximations of electromagnetic waves, in a similar way in which classical
mechanics is an approximation of quantum mechanics.
In this paper I would like to comment on the analogies between quantum
mechanics and classical optics, starting from the definitions of analogy found in the
Oxford dictionary: “a comparison between one thing and another, typically for the
purpose of explanation or clarification”, [6] and in Wikipedia: “Analogy […] is a
cognitive process of transferring information or meaning from a particular subject
(the analogue or source) to another particular subject (the target)” [7].
2. APPROPRIATENESS AND LIMITATIONS
OF CLASSICAL-QUANTUM ANALOGIES
In view of the latter definitions, classical optics, or at least some
appropriately chosen concepts, can aid us in understanding specific quantum
concepts or theories. But how in-depth can we use such analogies? Are there
quantum concepts/systems with no classical analogs? Are, actually, these analogies
appropriate/useful? In fact, it is not at all obvious that analogies could exist
between classical optics and quantum mechanics. I would like to recall that
quantum mechanical Hamiltonians of are commonly introduced by replacing with
operators the dynamical variables in the classical mechanical Hamiltonian
H ( r , p ) = p 2 / 2m( r ) − V ( r )
(1)
where m and V are the (effective) mass and potential energy. On the contrary, in
classical optics the Hamiltonian H ( r , p ) = −[ n 2 ( r ) − p 2 ]1 / 2 is defined starting
from the Fermat principle and [8], in the paraxial approximation only, it acquires a
form similar to (1):
H ( r , p ) = p 2 / 2 n ( r ) − n( r )
(2)
where n is the refractive index. The structure of the optical and classical
mechanical Hamiltonians are different mathematically: a restriction similar to
| p |≤ n in optics does not exist in classical mechanical and, moreover, the formal
equivalent parameters to the uncorrelated (effective) mass and potential energy in
classical mechanics become identical in optics. Yet, it is possible to find analogies
between the propagation of classical optical beams (constituted, from a quantum
mechanical point of view, from massless photons) and the evolution of massive
quantum particles.
3
On the quantum-classical analogies
1321
In fact, the analogies between classical optics governed by the Maxwell
equations and massive particles described by the Schrödinger equation are known
for quite a long time [9] and have inspired the development of research areas such
as particle optics [10] or photonic crystals [11]. Such analogies can only exist for
time-independent systems and they do not rely on the Hamiltonians (1) and (2) but
on the formal similarity between the Helmholtz equation obeyed by any component
A of the monochromatic electromagnetic field with frequency ω,
∇ 2 A + (ωn / c ) 2 A = 0 ,
(3)
where c is the speed of light, and the time-independent Schrödinger equation for
the wavefunction Ψ:
∇ 2 Ψ + [ 2m( E − V ) / = 2 ]Ψ = 0 .
(4)
Indeed, (3) and (4) resemble each other, although A is a vector and Ψ a scalar
function.
What happened with the differences in (1) and (2) between classical optics
and classical/quantum mechanics? One of the origins of the differences between
classical optics and classical mechanics is that the Hamiltonian formulation in
optics is associated with the phase/the eikonal function/the wavefront of light
waves. As such, it is related to a non-local description of electromagnetic waves.
By replacing p and r in the classical Hamiltonian (1) with their corresponding
operators, quantum mechanics becomes itself a non-local theory. In addition, using
(3) instead of (2) to describe the evolution of optical beams, not only the phase but
also the amplitude of electromagnetic fields is taken into account, as in (4). At this
point, a simple equivalence between Ψ and a component of A and a corresponding
replacement of the optical propagation constant/wavenumber k = ωn / c with the
quantum one γ = 2m( E − V ) / = almost lead to a quantitative equivalence
between the propagation of ballistic quantum wavefunctions and of optical fields.
“Almost” because boundary conditions need also to be similar. Because the
boundary conditions at interfaces are different for transverse electric and transverse
magnetic polarized radiation, a set of analogous optical/quantum parameters can be
found separately for the two cases [12]. Now, one can easily design optical
structures with the same transmittance and reflectance as the transmission and
reflection probabilities of quantum wavefunctions propagating through a
succession of layers with different effective electron masses and/or potential
energies. We have a quantitative optical-quantum analogy.
Of course, the fact that optical fields and quantum wavefunction evolve in
similar ways does not mean that their meaning is the same. The advantage is that
optical amplitude and phase measurements could give us a hint on the quantum
wavefunction, which are much more difficult to measure. In addition, although the
analogies between (3) and (4) are strictly valid only for ballistic (without
1322
D. Dragoman
4
collisions) quantum propagation, they can be extended to multiple scattering
regimes as long as the phase coherence is not completely lost [13]. Random lasers
[14], for example, are a result of pursuing such analogies with strongly localized
electrons in random nanostructures.
Are we to declare then that classical optics is not so much different from
quantum mechanics? Of course, the answer is no. But why? We have to look now
to an essentially quantum property: entanglement. It is usually considered that
entanglement has no classical analog. Is it true? Not exactly. Entanglement exists
also in classical optics (or any classical wave theory) in a restrictive sense, i.e. as
non-factorizability of a state vector. More precisely, we can have local
entanglement between different degrees of freedom (momentum/direction and
polarization, for example) of a single light beam [15-16]. In particular, there are
optical analogs of quantum bits (qubits) in the form of optical cebits [16], defined
as superpositions of classical beams, and there are even implementations of
quantum algorithms by classical optical systems [17-18]. However, nonlocal
correlations/multiparticle entanglement between spatially separated states cannot
be mimicked in classical optics. This is the reason why the scaling behavior of
qubits (the exponential decrease of computation time with a linear increase in the
input states) differs from that of cebits. A number of n optical components/beams
do not lead to 2 n optical paths [15].
Is this the end of the story? Is quantum mechanics only different from
classical optics through nonlocal entanglement? Not quite. I have mentioned in the
beginning of this short paper that the starting point of interest in the classicalquantum analogies was the phase space formalism of classical optics. This
formalism is particularly suited for comparing quantum and classical optics
theories because it uses the same mathematical language in both cases (the opposite
approach, that of expressing classical optical beams and systems via quantum
mechanical operators can also be successfully applied [19-20]).
In a, let’s say, two-dimensional phase space ( x, p ) , time-independent
quantum mechanical systems must be represented not by localized points, due to
the uncertainty principle but by quasiprobability distributions F ( x, p ) that lead to
correct forms of the observable quantities and similar expectation values of
arbitrary operators Aˆ ( xˆ , pˆ ) as in classical phase spaces [21], i.e.
〈 Aˆ ( xˆ , pˆ )〉 = ∫ A( x, p ) F ( x, p )dxdp ,
(5)
where A( x, p ) is the function obtained from Aˆ ( xˆ , pˆ ) by replacing the position and
momentum operators xˆ , pˆ with scalar variables x and p, respectively. If the Weyl
or symmetric rule of association is obeyed at these replacements the
quasiprobability function is the WDF. It is defined for pure states as
5
On the quantum-classical analogies
W ( x, p, t ) =
1
q  
q 
*
∫ exp(−ipq / =)Ψ  x − , t Ψ  x + , t dq ,
2π=
2
2 

 
1323
(6)
and obeys a series of useful properties (it has real values, satisfies the marginal
properties and the Moyal formula, transforms in a simple way at spatial and
angular translations, etc. [1, 21]). A phase space treatment of quantum mechanics is
equivalent to the Schrödinger, Heisenberg or interaction representations and can be
expressed also by a series of axioms [22].
I would like to emphasize here only that a classical optical WDF can be
similarly defined in terms of any component of the electromagnetic field except
that the normalized Planck constant is replaced by the normalized wavelength of
light (see the reviews in [5, 23]).
The interest in the phase space treatment of classical optics and quantum
mechanics is motivated by the fact that all previously discussed analogies are
retrieved also in phase space since the WDF is defined in terms of
wavefunctions/electromagnetic field components. In particular, the modes of
graded index optical waveguides are the analogs of Fock states [24-25], while the
quantum squeezing operator is implemented in classical optics by systems
consisting of lenses and free spaces [25]. However, since the WDF is bilinear in the
wavefunction/electromagnetic field component, it displays interference terms
whenever a superposition of quantum or classical states appear, irrespective of the
classical or quantum nature of states’ interference; we can have phase space
interference terms even if the states do not actually interfere in the configuration
space. In particular, although quantum interference between spatially separated
states cannot be mimicked by classical means, the WDF of a superposition of two
coherent classical fields with different spatial or angular positions has the same
form as that of a quantum Schrödinger cat state [26]; the measured interference
term has positive and negative values, as in the quantum case [4]. In this sense the
quantum-classical analogies in phase space seem to reach a deeper level than in
configuration space. There is actually no difference at all in the phase space
treatment of quantum and classical worlds, the phase space approach, and in
particular the WDF, being an ideal mathematical tool in a unified formalism [22,
27-28]; using this mathematical language a quantum system need no longer be
separated from the classical environment. As such, the question of appropriateness
and limits of quantum-classical analogies must be answered very carefully.
3. CLASSICAL ANALOGIES OF QUANTUM MASSLESS PARTICLES
In the previous section we have discussed the classical optical analogies of
quantum massive particles described by the Schrödinger equation. However, the
recent surge in interest related to graphene [29] has put forward the issue of
1324
D. Dragoman
6
classical optical analogies of quantum states described by a massless Dirac-like
equation. At first it seemed that such analogies could be found easier since the
photons are also massless particles. But such considerations proved themselves to
be naïve. In fact it is much harder to find classical optical analogs to quantum states
in graphene and the corresponding optical systems are not common. Because the
wavefunction in graphene is spinorial, Ψ = (ψ 1 ,ψ 2 )T , classical optical analogies
have been searched for in the form of polarized states of light propagating in
gyrotropic and electro-optic materials [30-31] or in the form of electromagnetic
fields evolving through common [32] or complex conjugate media [33]. In all cases
quantitative analogies could be found, in the sense that the optical transmittance
and reflectance through specific structures was identical to the transmission and
reflection probabilities in graphene-based structures. However, it is harder to
follow these analogies than in the case of the corresponding similarities between
classical optics and Schrödinger particles. In particular, it was not possible to
define a set of analogous classical-quantum parameters because the form of the
optical and quantum reflection and transmission coefficients was different in all
cases; only the square modulus of these coefficients could be equated. The reason
of the difficulty of finding simple classical optical analogs for graphene lies in the
chiral nature of quantum states of graphene. Chirality has no classical analog; it can
only be mimicked by electromagnetic waves in very special materials. With one
notable exception: photonic structures with Dirac points [34-35]. In this case the
two spinorial components of the wavefunction in graphene are replaced by two
degenerate optical Bloch states that satisfy, for certain frequencies of the incident
radiation, the same massless Dirac-like equation. The quantum-classical analogies
become again exact since chirality is strongly related to the honeycomb lattice, but
the classical and quantum fields retain their conceptual differences. Only the
mathematical formalism is identical, as are, for example, the reflection and
transmission coefficients through certain lengths of graphene-like honeycomb lattices.
4. CONCLUSIONS
After this brief discussion on the quantum-classical optical analogies, I
believe that the main conclusion is that this problem has different levels of
understanding and answers. There are quantum systems that have classical analogs
in phase space only, there are quantum states described by the Schrödinger
equation that propagate through specific structures in exactly the same way as
electromagnetic fields through appropriately designed optical structures, and
finally there are quantum states described by a Dirac-like equation that are
analogous to optical fields propagating through special materials or through
specifically designed honeycomb lattices. Is the quantum-classical analogy useful?
There is no doubt about its usefulness taking into account the feedback it produced
7
On the quantum-classical analogies
1325
between different areas of physics. In addition, the quantum-classical analogies
help us understand better the fundamental differences between classical and
quantum theories. Is the analogy appropriate? It is our task to find appropriate
quantum and classical systems that are analogous; they probably exist. What are
the limits of the analogy? Again, it depends on our skills to establish or surpass the
limits of classical analogies to quantum systems. All such analogies, if they exist,
are based on the non-local character of quantum and optical states. These analogies
must be used with care, in the sense that the conceptual differences between the
quantum and classical worlds do not disappear if an analogy is established. The art
of analogies in physics is to compare different systems for the purpose of
clarification (as in the definition in [6]) rather than to transfer meaning from a
particular research field to another (as in the definition in [7]). Of course, a transfer
of information from one research field to another (as implied by the definition in
[7]) is always welcome.
REFERENCES
1. E.P. Wigner, Phys. Rev. 40, 749–759 (1932).
2. V. Bužek, P.L. Knight, Prog. Opt. 34, 1–158 (1995).
3. K.H. Brenner, A.W. Lohmann, Opt. Commun. 42, 310–314 (1982).
4. D. Dragoman, M. Dragoman, Opt. Quantum Electron. 33, 239–252 (2001).
5. D. Dragoman, Prog. Opt. 37, 1–56 (1997).
6. http://oxforddictionaries.com/definition/english/analogy
7. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Analogy
8. R.K. Luneburg, Mathematical Theory of Optics, University of California Press, Berkeley, 1964.
9. G.N. Henderson, T.K. Gaylord, and E.N. Glytsis, Proc. IEEE 79, 1643–1659 (1991).
10. O. Klemperer, M.E. Barnett, Electron Optics, 3rd ed., Cambridge Univ. Press, Cambridge, 2004.
11. K. Sakoda, Optical Properties of Photonic Crystals, 2nd ed., Springer, Berlin, 2004.
12. D. Dragoman, M. Dragoman, Prog. Quantum Electron. 23, 131–188 (1999).
13. D.S. Wiersma, P. Bartolini, A. Lagendijk, and R. Righini, Nature 390, 671–673 (1997).
14. H. Cao, J. Phys. A 38, 10497–10535 (2005).
15. R.J.C. Spreeuw, Phys. Rev. A 63, 062302 (2001).
16. R.J.C. Spreeuw, Found. Phys. 28, 361–374 (1998).
17. N. Bhattacharya, H.B. van Linden van den Heuvell, and R.J.C. Spreeuw Phys. Rev. Lett. 88,
137901 (2002).
18. J.F. Clauser, J.P. Dowling, Phys. Rev. A 53, 4587–4590 (1996).
19. D. Gloge, D. Marcuse, J. Opt. Soc. Am. 59, 1629–1631 (1969).
20. S.G. Krivoshlykov, Quantum-Theoretical Formalism for Inhomogeneous Graded-Index
Waveguides, Akademie Verlag, Berlin, 1994.
21. H.-W. Lee, Phys. Rep. 259, 147–211 (1995).
22. D. Dragoman, Physica Scripta 72, 290–295 (2005).
23. D. Dragoman, Prog. Opt. 42, 433–496 (2002).
24. D. Dragoman, Optik 111, 393–396 (2000).
25. K. Wódkiewicz, G.H. Herling, Phys. Rev. A 57, 815–821 (1998).
26. K.B. Wolf, A.L. Rivera, Opt. Commun. 144, 36–42 (1997).
27. D. Dragoman, J. Opt. Soc. Am. B 22, 633–642 (2005).
28. D. Dragoman, Annales Fond. Louis Broglie 34, 25–34 (2009).
1326
D. Dragoman
8
29. A.H. Castro Neto, F. Guinea, N.M.R. Peres, K.S. Novoselov, and A.K. Geim, Rev. Mod. Phys.
81, 109–162 (2009).
30. D. Dragoman, J. Opt. Soc. Am. B 27, 1325–1331 (2010).
31. D. Dragoman, A. Radu, S. Iftimie, J. Opt. 15, 035710 (2013).
32. I. Mihalache, D. Dragoman, J. Opt. Soc. Am. B 28, 1746–1751 (2011)
33. D. Dragoman, Opt. Commun. 284, 2095–2098 (2011).
34. T. Ochiai, M. Onoda, Phys. Rev. B 80, 155103 (2009)
35. S. Bittner, B. Dietz, M. Miski-Oglu, P. Oria Iriarte, A. Richter, and F. Schäfer, Phys. Rev. B 82,
014301 (2010).