* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download LCS 11: Introduction to Cognitive Science. Behaviorism
Survey
Document related concepts
Transcript
LCS 11: Introduction to Cognitive Science. Behaviorism Jesse Harris February 11, 2013 Background to behaviorism Much of philosophy has addressed what is sometimes known as ‘Plato’s problem’ – how do we come to know so much about the world, given our limited experience? Two important, though not necessarily mutually exclusive, strands of response are rationalism, with privileges reason over experience, and empiricism, which favors experience over reason.1 Rationalism How do we know so much about the world given our limited experience? The rationalists propose that knowledge is deductive, in that we may glean knowledge from principles independent of experience. Rationalism Knowledge is to be gained primarily through reason alone. With respect to questions of mind, rationalism is often associated with René Descartes, who modeled his method on geometric proofs from Euclid.2 Descartes wished to determine an incontrovertible foundation of knowledge which was free of the possibility of illusion from the senses and which supported the immortality of the soul. Descartes famously settled on a foundation of knowledge through the idea that, even if illusory, a thought must have a thinker: the very act of doubt verified some aspect of his existence! In other words, cognito ergo sum. There are three important methodological assumptions that Descartes made: 1. Knowledge can be determined independently of the senses; 2. Ideas are transparent to conscious introspection; 3. We should privilege that which could be established by pure thought, e.g., mathematical truths, over the sense data of experience Substance dualism The mind (soul) is a immaterial, immortal substance which exists independently of the body. 1 In the Meno, Plato adopts a rationalist approach, arguing that knowledge is innately given and that the soul relies on experience and reason to recollect that knowledge. His argument is illustrated by getting a slave to “recollect” how to determine the areas of embedded squares like those above. Euclid’s highly influential The Elements deduces Euclidean geometry from a limited set of axioms. Descartes and others seemed to consider the axiomatic method developed by Euclid to be the ideal form of scientific inquiry. 2 lcs 11: introduction to cognitive science. behaviorism Despite deeply ingrained problems with this view, substance dualism remains a popular view.3 An alternate, and just as venerable, view is known as empiricism, which treats the acquisition of knowledge as inductive. 2 Three prevalent considerations are as follows (see Cunningham, 2000, ch. 1) 3 1. Reliance on introspection 2. Causal separation Empiricism 3. Development of mind In contrast to rationalists, empiricists largely reject the assumption that ideas are innate. Instead, mental contents are derived from two factors. 1. Sensations – events with external causes. 2. Reflection – mental operations that associate external or internal states with other internal states. Together, these factors yield Ideas, mental contents likened to pictures or images, linked to what they are about. Empiricism Knowledge is to be gained primarily through sense experience. A prominent proponent of empiricism was John Locke, who devised a scheme for mental mechanics in which ideas come to be associated with one another. Through this kind of associationism, as it was called, simple ideas compose to form more complex ones. “Let us then suppose the mind to be, as we say, white paper, void of all character, without any ideas. How comes it to be furnished? . . . I answer, in one word, experience. In that, all our knowledge is founded, and from that it ultimately derives itself.” Essay Concerning Human Understanding John Locke (1689) Introspectionism Interestingly enough, the earliest experimental psychologists adopted elements, from both traditions. For example, Wilhelm Wundt and his student E. B. Titchener4 developed a method known as introspection, in which the contents of experience were reflected on during conscious investigation and reported back. In an attempt to make this process more scientific, participants were trained in introspection through many trials, reporting their subjective experience.5 In particular, participants were instructed to decompose the process into discrete stages: perception of stimulus, a search for a response, identification of response, production of response, and so on. Exercise: Try this for yourself. View this swatch of red and reflect on the experience, attempting to break down the experience into as many components as you can. 4 Wilhelm Wundt (1832–1920) E. B. Titchener (1867–1927) “The first order of the psychologist . . . is to ascertain the nature and number of mental elements. He takes up mental experience, bit by bit, dividing and subdividing, until the division can go no further. When that point is reached, he has found a conscious element.” 5 An Outline of Psychology (Titchener, 1896) lcs 11: introduction to cognitive science. behaviorism 3 Behaviorism Frustration and disillusionment with introspection as a method of gaining entry into mental processes quickly mounted.6 John Watson and, later, B. F. Skinner,7 led the charge against the subjectivity seemingly inherent to the introspective method.8 They proposed a purely behavioristic approach to studying the cognition, concerned in no small measure with the prediction and control of behavior. As discussed in Cunningham (2000), multiple kinds of behaviorism resulted, notably, Methodological and Metaphysical Behaviorism. Methodological behaviorism A scientific study of mind should eschew talk of the mind in favor of a description of behavior, since only behavior provides publicly observable, hence potentially verifiable, data. “Take the case of sensation. A sensation is defined in terms of its attributes. One psychologist will state with readiness that the attributes of a visual sensation are quality, extension, duration and intensity. Another will add clearness. Still another that of order. I doubt if any one psychologist can draw up a set of statements describing what he means by sensation which will be agreed to by three other psychologists of different training.“ 6 Psychology as the Behaviorist Views It (Watson, 1913) 7 Metaphysical behaviorism Mental events are reducible in kind to behavior: there is no substance or thing corresponding to what we call ‘mind.’ Influenced by the Vienna Circle’s circumscribed view of science,9 behaviorism seeks to align, to various extents, the study of mind with the study of behavior. That is, instead of worrying about the connection between mind and body, we focus on what we can observe: responses to external stimuli. Among the vocabulary central to Skinner’s behaviorism was operant conditioning, in which modification of behavior is voluntary. Skinner developed the so-called “Skinner box” to control an animal’s environment, typically a pigeon or white rat, starve them to create a “drive,” and then wait for animal to discover a relation between the environment, e.g., a lever, and a reward, e.g., a food pellet. Soon enough, the behavior is associated with the reward. John B. Watson (1878–1958) B.F. Skinner (1904–1990) “Psychology as the behaviorist views it is a purely objective experimental branch of natural science. Its theoretical goal is the prediction and control of behavior. Introspection forms no essential part of its methods, nor is the scientific value of its data dependent upon the readiness of with which they lend themselves to interpretation in terms of consciousness. The behaviorist . . . recognizes no dividing line between man and brute.” Ibid. 8 The Vienna Circle refers to a group of philosophers and scientists in Vienna in the early 1920s who sought to eliminate what they deemed logical mistakes from philosophical questions. They thought that ambiguous language had radically misled scientific and philosophical inquiry, and proposed a unified science built on the foundation of symbolic logic and publicly observable sense experience. 9 In addition, Skinner placed animals on a schedule of reinforcement.10 If a pigeon is fed at regular intervals regardless of its behavior, it will adopt essentially arbitrary patterns of behavior which it has associated with the reward, such as spinning, pecking, etc. The efficacy of the association could be manipulated by varying the rate of reward: 10 Skinner, B. F. (1948). ‘Superstition’ in the pigeon. Journal of Experimental Psychology 38, 168–272 lcs 11: introduction to cognitive science. behaviorism fixed and random reinforcement. The strongest type was random reinforcement, in which the animal is rewarded at random intervals. Indeed, it sometimes happened that although feeding device was dismantled, the pigeon indefinitely continued to perform the behavior that was associated with the reward. Thus, the behaviorist was able to account for admitedly simple behavior without recourse to unsightly mentalistic terms like desire, belief, and so forth. That is, the psychologist needn’t speculate about what the bird was feeling; she only needed to report its behavior. Encouraged by the success with pigeons and rats, Skinner and colleagues proposed that the basic mechanism of association between a stimulus and response was the central, or even sole, mechanism driving all behavior, even in human beings. Skinner even claimed that language learning was simply an instance of operant reinforcement, albeit complex in nature. For example, a child might be rewarded by her parents to cry out Papa in the presence of her father, thereby associating the word with the figure. In a devasting review by Noam Chomsky,11 it soon became apparent that Skinner’s science of behavior was simply not rich enough to account for more complex forms of speech or human behavior. Indeed, even once committed behaviorists like Keller and Marian Breland12 observed that instinctive behaviors not driven by the external environment were a powerful determinant of an animal’s action. It is important to note that the success of behaviorism owes to a specific historical and cultural context, in that it opposed the deterministic, predjudice-driven psychological theories sweeping Europe at the time, most notably those associated with Nazism. At its core, behaviorism was an optimisitic approach to science, offering a vision of re-engineering society through simple mechanisms entirely under the individual’s control. May it rest in peace. References Breland, K. and M. Breland (1961). The misbehavior of organisms. American Psychologist 16, 681–684. Chomsky, N. (1959). Verbal Behavior. By B. F. Skinner. Language 35, 26–58. Cunningham, S. (2000). What is a Mind? An Integrative Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing. Skinner, B. F. (1948). ‘Superstition’ in the pigeon. Journal of Experimental Psychology 38, 168–272. Titchener, E. B. (1896). An Outline of Psychology. Macmillian. Watson, J. B. (1913). Psychology as the behaviorist views it. Psychological Review 20, 158–177. 4 Chomsky, N. (1959). Verbal Behavior. By B. F. Skinner. Language 35, 26–58 11 Noam Chomsky (b. 1928) Chomsky’s review is widely regarded as the death knoll for behaviorism, making commonsense, mentalistic talk once again respectable in American psychology. Breland, K. and M. Breland (1961). The misbehavior of organisms. American Psychologist 16, 681–684 12