* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Bare nominals, true and fake vocatives Romance
Sanskrit grammar wikipedia , lookup
Polish grammar wikipedia , lookup
Ojibwe grammar wikipedia , lookup
Spanish grammar wikipedia , lookup
Agglutination wikipedia , lookup
Malay grammar wikipedia , lookup
Serbo-Croatian grammar wikipedia , lookup
Dependency grammar wikipedia , lookup
Grammatical case wikipedia , lookup
Distributed morphology wikipedia , lookup
Integrational theory of language wikipedia , lookup
Antisymmetry wikipedia , lookup
Proto-Indo-European nominals wikipedia , lookup
Lexical semantics wikipedia , lookup
Musical syntax wikipedia , lookup
Transformational grammar wikipedia , lookup
Junction Grammar wikipedia , lookup
Bare nominals, true and fake vocatives Romance languages, in spite of being languages with determiners, allow bare nominals in predicate position, in object position of prepositions and of a restricted class of verbs (Espinal & McNally 2007, in press), and in vocatives. One of the questions that must be answered is whether these bare nominals are to be attributed the same syntactic structure, in particular, the canonical structure for nominal expressions postulated for languages with number morphology and determiners (see (1); Chierchia 1998, Longobardi 2001, Zamparelli 1995). Following Dobrovie-Sorin & Laca (2003), Dobrovie-Sorin et al. (2006), and Espinal & McNally (in press) I will assume that bare nominals in object position are NPs or NumPs depending on whether they are unmarked for Number (number neutral bare nominals) or not (bare singulars and bare plurals). Similarly, bare predicates can either be NPs or NumPs, but do not require a DP. What these bare nominals have in common from a semantic perspective is that they denote properties, either properties of kinds of individuals or properties of individual objects (when Number is present). By contrast, bare nominals in true vocatives, either in singular or in plural (see (2a,b)), have the additional restriction that they denote properties that allow the identification of a singular entity or of a sum of individuals that correspond to the hearer(s) or addressee(s). They have often been said to be referential and have a deictic interpretation, like proper names (see (2c)). In this paper I will focus on the following two questions: Q1. What is the internal structure of a phrase interpreted as Vocative? (see Moro 2003, D’hulst et al. 2007, Hill 2007, Stavrou 2009). Q2. Is it possible to find a syntactic correlation between Vocatives and other syntactic structures? I will address these questions within a generative formal syntactic theory, the main ingredients of which are the following: (i) VocP is a functional projection (Moro 2003, Stavrou 2009) whose head Vocº is defined by [+II,-I] person formal features; (ii) Vocº can be specified by a vocative particle, and Vocº selects a DP (see the structure in (3)); (iii) second person strong pronouns, which are standardly assumed to be generated in Dº (Déchaine & Wiltschko 2002), are postulated to move from this position to Vocº in order to be valued appropriately; and (iv) Nº movement to Dº in the syntax (Longobardi 1994), which is assumed to apply not only to proper names but also to common nouns (Coene et al. 1999, Cabredo Hofherr 2009), is to be extended to Vocº. These ingredients will provide an explanation for the syntactic and semantic properties of vocative nominal expressions: both proper names and bare count nominals are incompatible with Ds in a language like Catalan that usually requires Ds, a full DP or NP cannot move to Vocº, full indefinite and quantificational expressions cannot be used in true vocative constructions, predicative bare nominals and bare adjectives move neither to Dº (they are not argumental) nor to Vocº (they are not deictic). Finally, I will focus on the set of vocatives in (4). I will come to some significant structural similarities that hold crosslinguistically between vocatives and copular sentences. Following Higgins’ (1979) claim that copular sentences are not uniform, I will discuss, based on Catalan data, that vocatives are not a peripheral phenomenon in the syntax of natural languages, and that three of the four types of copular sentences postulated by Higgins apply to vocative structures as well, namely the identificational, the identity and the predicational types. What these three structures have in common is that the subject (i.e., the true vocative head) is always referential, while the predicate (i.e., the subsequent NP or DP) is either identificational, referential or predicational, respectively (compare the three examples in (4)); in this sense the NP/DP predicate is a fake vocative. I will argue that vocatives are not arguments of verbal predicates (Longobardi 1994, Moro 2003, D’hulst et al. 2007), but they can be arguments of nominal (and adjectival) predicational structures (4c), as it is the case in predicational copular sentences (Higgins 1979). They only differ from the latter in that they never show an overt copular verb. The relevant parallelism I will introduce between vocative structures and copular structures will allow me to extend the proposed analysis to the English data in (5). (1) [DP D [NumP Num [NP N ]]] (2) a. Ei, company, com va? guy how goes ‘Hey! Guy! How are things? b. Eh, nois, espero que estigueu bé. PART boys hope that be.SUB fine ‘Hey! Boys! I hope that you are fine.’ c. Ei, Joan, quin goig que fas! PART Joan how nice that do ‘Hey! Joan, how nice you look!’ PART (3) [VocP Part [Voc’ Vocº [DP [D’ Dº [NP [N’ Nº ]]]]]] (4) a. Tu! el noi de la camisa blava! you the boy of the shirt blue ‘You! The boy with the blue shirt!’ b. Tu! Joan! you Joan ‘You! Joan!’ c. Tu! noi! you boy ‘You! boy!’ identificational (5) a. You, the linguists. b. You, linguists. identificational predicational identity predicational Selected references Cabredo-Hofherr, P. 2009. Definiteness markers in vocatives. Ms. CNRS/Paris8, Paris. Coene, M., D’Hulst, Y., Tasmowski, L.1999. Romance vocatives and the DP hypothesis. Paper presented at CSSP, Paris. Cowper E., Currie Hall, D. 2009. Argumenthood, pronouns, and nominal feature geometry. In J.Ghomeshi, I. Paul & M. Wiltschko (eds.), Determiners. Amsterdam: John Benjamins, 97-120. Déchaine, R.M., Wilstchko, M. 2002, Decomposing pronouns’. Linguistic Inquiry, vol. 33. 3, 409 – 442. Higgins, F.R. 1979. A pseudo-cleft construction in English. New York: Garland. Hill, V. 2007. Vocatives and the pragmatics-syntax interface. Lingua 117, 2077-2105. Longobardi, G. 1994. Reference and proper names: a theory of N-movement in syntax and logical form. Linguistic Inquiry 25.4, 609-665. Moro, A. 2003. Notes on vocative case. A case study in clause structure. In J. Quer & J. schroten (eds.), Romance languages and linguistic theory 2001, Amsterdam, John Benjamins, 247-261. Stavrou, M. 2009. Vocative!. Ms. Aristotle University of Thessaloniki.