Download Bare nominals, true and fake vocatives Romance

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts

Sanskrit grammar wikipedia , lookup

Polish grammar wikipedia , lookup

Ojibwe grammar wikipedia , lookup

Spanish grammar wikipedia , lookup

Agglutination wikipedia , lookup

Malay grammar wikipedia , lookup

Serbo-Croatian grammar wikipedia , lookup

Dependency grammar wikipedia , lookup

Grammatical case wikipedia , lookup

Distributed morphology wikipedia , lookup

Parsing wikipedia , lookup

Integrational theory of language wikipedia , lookup

Antisymmetry wikipedia , lookup

Equative wikipedia , lookup

Proto-Indo-European nominals wikipedia , lookup

Lexical semantics wikipedia , lookup

Musical syntax wikipedia , lookup

Transformational grammar wikipedia , lookup

Junction Grammar wikipedia , lookup

Scottish Gaelic grammar wikipedia , lookup

Vocative case wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
Bare nominals, true and fake vocatives
Romance languages, in spite of being languages with determiners, allow bare nominals
in predicate position, in object position of prepositions and of a restricted class of verbs
(Espinal & McNally 2007, in press), and in vocatives. One of the questions that must be
answered is whether these bare nominals are to be attributed the same syntactic
structure, in particular, the canonical structure for nominal expressions postulated for
languages with number morphology and determiners (see (1); Chierchia 1998,
Longobardi 2001, Zamparelli 1995).
Following Dobrovie-Sorin & Laca (2003), Dobrovie-Sorin et al. (2006), and Espinal &
McNally (in press) I will assume that bare nominals in object position are NPs or
NumPs depending on whether they are unmarked for Number (number neutral bare
nominals) or not (bare singulars and bare plurals). Similarly, bare predicates can either
be NPs or NumPs, but do not require a DP. What these bare nominals have in common
from a semantic perspective is that they denote properties, either properties of kinds of
individuals or properties of individual objects (when Number is present).
By contrast, bare nominals in true vocatives, either in singular or in plural (see (2a,b)),
have the additional restriction that they denote properties that allow the identification of
a singular entity or of a sum of individuals that correspond to the hearer(s) or
addressee(s). They have often been said to be referential and have a deictic
interpretation, like proper names (see (2c)).
In this paper I will focus on the following two questions: Q1. What is the internal
structure of a phrase interpreted as Vocative? (see Moro 2003, D’hulst et al. 2007, Hill
2007, Stavrou 2009). Q2. Is it possible to find a syntactic correlation between Vocatives
and other syntactic structures?
I will address these questions within a generative formal syntactic theory, the main
ingredients of which are the following: (i) VocP is a functional projection (Moro 2003,
Stavrou 2009) whose head Vocº is defined by [+II,-I] person formal features; (ii) Vocº
can be specified by a vocative particle, and Vocº selects a DP (see the structure in (3));
(iii) second person strong pronouns, which are standardly assumed to be generated in Dº
(Déchaine & Wiltschko 2002), are postulated to move from this position to Vocº in
order to be valued appropriately; and (iv) Nº movement to Dº in the syntax (Longobardi
1994), which is assumed to apply not only to proper names but also to common nouns
(Coene et al. 1999, Cabredo Hofherr 2009), is to be extended to Vocº. These ingredients
will provide an explanation for the syntactic and semantic properties of vocative
nominal expressions: both proper names and bare count nominals are incompatible with
Ds in a language like Catalan that usually requires Ds, a full DP or NP cannot move to
Vocº, full indefinite and quantificational expressions cannot be used in true vocative
constructions, predicative bare nominals and bare adjectives move neither to Dº (they
are not argumental) nor to Vocº (they are not deictic).
Finally, I will focus on the set of vocatives in (4). I will come to some significant
structural similarities that hold crosslinguistically between vocatives and copular
sentences. Following Higgins’ (1979) claim that copular sentences are not uniform, I
will discuss, based on Catalan data, that vocatives are not a peripheral phenomenon in
the syntax of natural languages, and that three of the four types of copular sentences
postulated by Higgins apply to vocative structures as well, namely the identificational,
the identity and the predicational types. What these three structures have in common is
that the subject (i.e., the true vocative head) is always referential, while the predicate
(i.e., the subsequent NP or DP) is either identificational, referential or predicational,
respectively (compare the three examples in (4)); in this sense the NP/DP predicate is a
fake vocative. I will argue that vocatives are not arguments of verbal predicates
(Longobardi 1994, Moro 2003, D’hulst et al. 2007), but they can be arguments of
nominal (and adjectival) predicational structures (4c), as it is the case in predicational
copular sentences (Higgins 1979). They only differ from the latter in that they never
show an overt copular verb.
The relevant parallelism I will introduce between vocative structures and copular
structures will allow me to extend the proposed analysis to the English data in (5).
(1)
[DP D [NumP Num [NP N ]]]
(2) a. Ei,
company, com va?
guy
how goes
‘Hey! Guy! How are things?
b. Eh,
nois, espero que estigueu bé.
PART boys hope that be.SUB fine
‘Hey! Boys! I hope that you are fine.’
c. Ei,
Joan, quin goig que fas!
PART Joan how
nice that do
‘Hey! Joan, how nice you look!’
PART
(3)
[VocP Part [Voc’ Vocº [DP [D’ Dº [NP [N’ Nº ]]]]]]
(4) a. Tu! el noi de la camisa blava!
you the boy of the shirt blue
‘You! The boy with the blue shirt!’
b. Tu! Joan!
you Joan
‘You! Joan!’
c. Tu! noi!
you boy
‘You! boy!’
identificational
(5) a. You, the linguists.
b. You, linguists.
identificational
predicational
identity
predicational
Selected references
Cabredo-Hofherr, P. 2009. Definiteness markers in vocatives. Ms. CNRS/Paris8, Paris.
Coene, M., D’Hulst, Y., Tasmowski, L.1999. Romance vocatives and the DP hypothesis. Paper presented
at CSSP, Paris.
Cowper E., Currie Hall, D. 2009. Argumenthood, pronouns, and nominal feature geometry. In
J.Ghomeshi, I. Paul & M. Wiltschko (eds.), Determiners. Amsterdam: John Benjamins, 97-120.
Déchaine, R.M., Wilstchko, M. 2002, Decomposing pronouns’. Linguistic Inquiry, vol. 33. 3, 409 – 442.
Higgins, F.R. 1979. A pseudo-cleft construction in English. New York: Garland.
Hill, V. 2007. Vocatives and the pragmatics-syntax interface. Lingua 117, 2077-2105.
Longobardi, G. 1994. Reference and proper names: a theory of N-movement in syntax and logical form.
Linguistic Inquiry 25.4, 609-665.
Moro, A. 2003. Notes on vocative case. A case study in clause structure. In J. Quer & J. schroten (eds.),
Romance languages and linguistic theory 2001, Amsterdam, John Benjamins, 247-261.
Stavrou, M. 2009. Vocative!. Ms. Aristotle University of Thessaloniki.