* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download General Semantics - Division of Social Sciences
Integrational theory of language wikipedia , lookup
Ancient Greek grammar wikipedia , lookup
Japanese grammar wikipedia , lookup
Esperanto grammar wikipedia , lookup
Zulu grammar wikipedia , lookup
Kannada grammar wikipedia , lookup
Indexicality wikipedia , lookup
Modern Hebrew grammar wikipedia , lookup
Construction grammar wikipedia , lookup
Sloppy identity wikipedia , lookup
Preposition and postposition wikipedia , lookup
Chinese grammar wikipedia , lookup
Interpretation (logic) wikipedia , lookup
Determiner phrase wikipedia , lookup
Vietnamese grammar wikipedia , lookup
Focus (linguistics) wikipedia , lookup
Antisymmetry wikipedia , lookup
Bound variable pronoun wikipedia , lookup
Latin syntax wikipedia , lookup
Spanish grammar wikipedia , lookup
Symbol grounding problem wikipedia , lookup
Junction Grammar wikipedia , lookup
Polish grammar wikipedia , lookup
Pipil grammar wikipedia , lookup
Lexical semantics wikipedia , lookup
Meaning (philosophy of language) wikipedia , lookup
Transformational grammar wikipedia , lookup
General Semantics Author(s): David Lewis Source: Synthese, Vol. 22, No. 1/2, Semantics of Natural Language, II (Dec., 1970), pp. 18-67 Published by: Springer Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20114749 . Accessed: 09/12/2014 13:21 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. . Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Synthese. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions DAVID GENERAL I. LEWIS SEMANTICS INTRODUCTION that all natural or artificial languages On the hypothesis can be given transformational of a certain grammars to it becomes sort, possible give very simple general of interest to us not-very-special answers to the questions: (1) What (2) What sort of thing is a meaning? is the form of the semantic are built up from compounds tuent parts? rules whereby meanings of the meanings of their consti It is not my plan to make any strong empirical claim about language. I want to propose a convenient the contrary: format for semantics a to for of work general enough great variety logically possible languages. This paper therefore belongs not to empirical linguistic theory but to the To thereof. philosophy to will not conform regarding the nature of meanings of those linguists who conceive of semantic interpreta to sentences and their constituents tion as the assignment of compounds of 'semantic markers' or the like. (Katz and Postal, 1964, for instance.) My proposals the expectations Semantic markers are symbols: call Semantic in the vocabulary of an artificial Markerese. Semantic by interpretation to a translation algorithm from the object items language we may means of them amounts merely language Markerese. language to the auxiliary But we can know the Markerese translation of an English sentence without knowing the first thing about the meaning of the English sentence :namely, the conditions under which it would be true. Semantics is not semantics. Translation conditions with no into Markerese treatment of truth is at best a substi tute for real semantics, relying either on our tacit competence (at some or on our ability to do real seman future date) as speakers of Markerese tics at least for the one language Markerese. Translation into Latin might Synthese 22 (1970) 18-67. All Rights Reserved Copyright ? 1970 by D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht-Holland This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions GENERAL serve as well, except insofar as into it useful features on symbolic logic - that might than for Latin. (See Markerese to build The Markerese SEMANTICS 19 the designers of Markerese may choose freedom from ambiguity, grammar based it easier to do real semantics for make Vermazen, 1967, for similar criticisms). in part just because it deals with is attractive finite combinations of entities of a familiar sort out method nothing but symbols: of a finite set of elements of finitely many by finitely many applications no risk of alarming the ontologically rules. There is But parsimonious. it is just this pleasing finitude that prevents Markerese semantics from dealing with the relations between symbols and the world of non-symbols - that we should be semantic relations. Accordingly, is, with genuinely a more to find in that adequate method, meanings may turn out prepared to be complicated, various infinite entities built up out of elements belonging to categories. ontological will also not conform proposals to the expectations of those who, My to the psychology turn immediately in analyzing meaning, and sociology of language users : to intentions, and mental ideas, or sense-experience, to social rules, conventions, I distinguish two topics: and regularities. as abstract of possible first, the description languages or grammars are associated with semantic systems whereby symbols aspects of the of the the and and world; second, description psychological sociological facts whereby a particular one of these abstract semantic systems is the one used by a person or population. comes of mixing Only confusion these two topics. This paper deals almost entirely with the first. (I discuss the second elsewhere: Lewis, 1968b and 1969, Chapter V.) are in the tradition of referential, or model-theoretic, My proposals semantics descended recent work of Kripke from Frege, Tarski, Carnap (in his later works), and and others on semantic foundations of intensional 1947 and 1963, ? 9; 1892; Tarski, 1936; Carnap, (See Frege, and 1971 ;Scott, 1970.) 1963 ; 1964; Montague, 1960,1968, Kaplan, Kripke, The project of transplanting referential semantics from artificial to natural logic. in various ways, by several phi has recently been undertaken, and 1967; Parsons, 1968; Montague, losophers linguists (Davidson, no I and have 1970b; Keenan, 1969, 1970a, 1969.) quarrel with these languages indeed, I have here adapted features from several of them. I hope, that the system set forth in this paper offers a simpler way to however, do essentially the same thing. But simplicity is a matter of taste, and efforts; This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions DAVID 20 LEWIS simplicity at one place trades off against simplicity these trade-offs that my approach differs most from II. A CATEGOR?ALLY grammar 1964, Part categorial Bar-Hillel, the following BASED It is in elsewhere. the others. GRAMMARS in the sense of Ajdukiewicz II) is a context-free phrase 1935; (Ajdukiewicz, structure grammar of sort. First, we have a small number of basic categories. One of these is the category sentence (S). Others might be, for instance, the categories name (N) and common noun (C). Perhaps we can get by with these three and no more; went so far as to do without the category indeed, Ajdukiewicz common noun. Or perhaps we might do better to use different basic categories ;we will consider dispensing with the category name in favor noun verb phrase of an alternative basic category (VP), or perhaps phrase (NP). c, cx, ..., Second, we have infinitely many derived categories. Whenever or we a are have derived either basic any categories, derived, cn(n^\) category which we will write (c/c1... cn). (However, we will usually omit the outermost parentheses.) Third, we have context-free c-+(c/c1...cn) corresponding c,cl9...9cn, + phrase-structure c1+?+cH to each derived the result of rules of the form category. concatenating That any is to say: for any categories expression of category of category cl9 then..., and finally any then any expression (c/c^.Xj), an we expression of category c. Accordingly, expression of category cn is ... and a cn and makes a c. The takes a ct and will say that a (c/ci...cn) rules are implicit in the system of derived categories. phrase-structure a lexicon wherein finitely many expressions - words we have Finally, - are or word-like morphemes assigned to categories. The categories of these lexical expressions may be either basic or derived; unless some lexical expressions belong to derived categories, no non-lexical compound can be generated. Notice that although there are infinitely expressions and infinitely many derived rules, many phrase-structure categories nevertheless with any given lexicon all but finitely many categories This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions and GENERAL rules will be unemployed. This SEMANTICS is true even 21 though many l?xica will generate infinitely many compound expressions. To specify a categorial grammar, we need only specify its lexicon. The rest is common to all categorial grammars. Consider this lexicon: <a (S/(S/N))/C><pig (believes (every (grunts (is (loves (Petunia (S/N)/S> (S/(S/N))/C> S/N> (S/N)/N> (S/N)/N> N> C> (piggishly (Porky (something (the (which (yellow (S/N)/(S/N)> N> S/(S/N)> (S/(S/N))/C> (C/C)/(S/N)> C/C> It gives us a categorial grammar which is simply a notational this rather commonplace context-free grammar: NP+VP VP+Npr Adv+VP VP NP Nco Adj Vt+Npr Vs + S Art+Nco Adj + Nco Rel + VP Npr NP' J of Porky [Petunia something Nco pig VP vt variant grunts J loves [is Vs Art believes a every the Adj yellow Adv piggishly Rel which There are three peculiarities about the grammar. First, proper nouns are noun from distinguished phrases. Proper nouns or noun phrases may be word order) but only proper nouns may with different subjects (though be objects. Second, there is nothing to prevent inappropriate iteration of Third, the word order is sometimes odd. We will see later how these peculiarities may be overcome. The employed rules in this example are the eight phrase-structure rules to the eight employed derived categories. corresponding modifiers. This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions DAVID 22 LEWIS In this example, I have used only derived categories of the form (c/c^ that take a single argument. I shall adopt this restriction for the most part in practice, but not in principle. It is apparent that categorial grammars of this sort are not reasonable grammars for natural language. For that matter, they are not reasonable - the grammars for most artificial languages either exception being sym bolic logic in Polish notation. Hence, their despite elegance, categorial have largely been ignored since the early 1950's. Since then, we have become interested in the plan of using a simple phrase however, structure grammar as a base for a transformational grammar. The time grammars therefore mars, seems ripe to explore categorially based transformational gram by taking an Ajdukiewicz categorial grammar as base and a transformational far as I know, this proposal So component. obtained adding has been made only once before (Lyons, 1966), but it seems an obvious one. to the that by adding a transformational component our we of could the word order and categorial grammar example, rectify out we filter iterations of modifiers. Less obviously, could inappropriate com provide for noun phrase objects by means of a transformational lexical items - items that need never ponent together with a few additional It is obvious appear in the final generated If reasonable categorially sentences. can be transformational grammars to can all of if this interest and be under the done us, given for languages are to be determined entirely by base structure, constraint that meanings so that the transformational is irrelevant to semantics, then component : it becomes extremely easy to give general answer to the questions What based is a meaning? What is the form of a semantic how this can be done. III. INTENSIONS projection rule? Let us see FOR BASIC CATEGORIES In order to say what a meaning is, we may first ask what a meaning and then find something that does that. A meaning under which for a sentence the sentence of the sentence various places, in various for various is something that determines is true or false. It determines possible speakers, does, the conditions the truth-value states of affairs, at various times, at and so on. (Imean this to apply even This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions GENERAL SEMANTICS 23 to non-declarative Similarly, a meaning but postpone of them.) consideration sentences, for a name is something that determines what thing, states of affairs, at various the name names in various possible if any, times, and so on. Among 'things' we include things that do not actually exist, but might exist in states of affairs different from the actual state of affairs. Similarly, determines which noun a meaning (possible to in various applies for a common noun is something that common if that any, actual) things, states of affairs, at various times, possible or so on. and We call the truth-value of a sentence the extension of that sentence; we call the thing named by a name the extension of that name; we call the set of things to which a common noun applies the extension of that common noun. The extension in one of these three cate of something and, in general, on other things as well: on its meaning the world, on the time of utterance, on the place of utter ance, on the speaker, on the surrounding discourse, etc. It is the meaning of which determines how the extension depends upon the combination gories depends on facts about sort of things determine how something factors. What on something else? Functions, of course; functions in the most in which set-theoretic domain of the sense, arguments and the general sort of of of values consist entities may any range whatever, and in which it is not required that the function be specifiable by any simple rule. We have now found something to do at least part of what a meaning for a other relevant depends sentence, name, or common noun does :a function an appropriate extension when given as input a factors on which the extension may depend. We package of relevant factors an index; and we will indices to appropriate an extensions for a sentence, yields as output package of the various will call such an input which call any function from name, or common noun intension. Thus an appropriate intension for a sentence is any function from indices an appropriate intension for a name is any function from to truth-values; to intension for a common noun is any indices things ; an appropriate function from indices to sets. The plan to construe intensions as extension originated with Carnap. (Carnap, 1947, ? 40, and us call such functions Carnapian let intensions. But 1963.) Accordingly, as whereas Carnap's extension-determining functions take their arguments models or state-descriptions representing possible worlds, I will adopt the determining functions This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 24 DAVID LEWIS be 1968; Scott, 1970) of letting the arguments (Montague, suggestion of miscellaneous factors relevant to determining extensions. packages We may take indices as ?-tuples (finite sequences) of the various items that may enter into determining other than meaning extensions. We call these various of the index, and we shall assume some arbitrary fixed order. items coordinates that the are given we must sentences coordinate. Contingent have a possible-world First, on so are true for their truth value facts about the and world, depend coordinates at some possible worlds and false at others. A possible world corresponds to a possible totality of facts, determinate in all respects. Common nouns at different possible worlds; and so do also have different extensions some names, at least if we adopt the position in Lewis, 1968a) (defended that things strong are related to their counterparts rather than identity. in other worlds by ties of similarity to Second, we must have several contextual coordinates corresponding familiar sorts of dependence on features of context. (The world coordinate itself might be regarded as a feature of context, since different possible utterances of a sentence are located in different possible worlds.) We must have a time coordinate, in view of tensed sentences and such sen tences as 'Today is Tuesday'; aplace coordinate, in view of such sentences as 'Here there are tigers' ; a speaker coordinate in view of such sentences as T am Porky' ; an audience coordinate in view of such sentences as 'You are Porky' ; an indicated-objects coordinate in view of such sen tences as 'That pig is Porky' or 'Those men are Communists'; and a previous discourse coordinate in view of such sentences as 'The afore mentioned pig is Porky'. to have an assignment it coordinate: an infinite is convenient Third, as of sequence giving the values of any variables that things, regarded occur free in such expressions as 'x is tall' or 'son of y9. Each variable employed in the language will accordingly be a name having as its inten sion, for some number n, the nth variable intension: that function whose value, at any index /, is that thing which is the nth. term of the assignment may coordinate thing is the extension, or value, of the variable at /. there is more than one possible thing, the variable are distinct: nothing is both the ?xth and the n2th variable of /. That that because (Note intensions intension nt and n2.) The extensions of 'x is tall' on the assignment and world coordinates of indices for two different numbers of 'son of y9 depend This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions GENERAL SEMANTICS 25 just as the extensions of T am tall' of'son of mine' depend on the speaker cannot naturally coordinate and world coordinates. Yet the assignment among features of context. One might claim that variables do not appear in sentences of natural languages; but even if this is so, it may be useful to employ variables in a categorial base. In any case, I be included seek sufficient generality to accommodate languages that do employ variables. But Perhaps other coordinates would be useful. (See the Appendix.) let us stop here, even though the penalty for introducing a superfluous is mere clutter, while the penalty for omitting a needed one coordinate is inadequacy. Thus an index is tentatively any octuple of which the first the second coordinate coordinate is a possible world, of is a moment a a is the fourth the third coordinate coordinate is person time, place, is a (or other creature capable of being a speaker), the fifth coordinate set of persons (or other creatures capable of being an audience), the sixth coordinate is a set (possibly empty) of concrete things capable of being is a segment of discourse, and the at, the seventh coordinate an is infinite of coordinate sequence eight things. our functions from indices to extensions, are designed to Intensions, pointed do part of what meanings do. Yet they are not meanings; for there are in meaning in differences differences It intension. unaccompanied by would be absurd to say that all tautologies have the same meaning, but they have the same intension ; the constant function having at every index are part of the way to meanings, however, and they are of interest in their own right. We shall consider later what must be added to an intension to obtain something that can do all of what a the value truth. Intensions does. meaning We may permit Carnapian from intensions to be partial functions some name indices. A indices, undefined at may not denote anything at a given possible world. 'Pegasus', for instance, denotes nothing at our so be taken as undefined at any index having its intension may world, our world as its world coordinate. A sentence that suffers from failure of presupposition is often to lack a truth-value (for instance in Strawson, 1950; Keenan, 1969; McCawley, 1969). If we adopt this treat ment of presupposition, sentences to lack of truth-value susceptible should have intensions that are undefined at some indices. They might even have intensions that are undefined at all indices; a sentence with thought This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions DAVID 26 LEWIS inconsistent function, Hitherto tensions should presuppositions defined at no index. have as its intension the empty of 'things'. Things are name ex spoken uncritically name sets of things are common-noun of and values intensions; I have and values of common-noun sequences of things set of the Change underlying sets of and the extensions, indices, change Carnapian intensions. What, then, are things? Of course I want to say, once and for all: everything is a thing. But I must not say that. Not all sets of things extensions are assignment things and we coordinates of intensions; indices. can be things; else the set of things would be larger than itself. No at certain intension can be a thing (unless it is undefined Carnapian ... a member a of of must We it would be member itself. else indices); of extensions, the above definitions indices, and Carnapian of compositional definitions intensions, (and the coming a as to set of relativized chosen and l?xica) things. Can tacitly meanings, we choose the set of things once and for all? Not quite; no matter what set we choose as the set of things, the system of intensions defined over intensions for certain terms - 'intension', for that set will not provide to that choice. instance of the semantic metalanguage corresponding understand intensions Consider extension language must move the language of this paper (minus this paragraph) with the semantic meta of 'thing' somehow fixed; it is an adequate for some languages but not for itself. To do semantics for it, we language in which 'thing' is taken more inclusive ly; to do semantics for that language we must move to a third language in which 'thing' is taken more inclusively still; and so on. Any language can be treated in a metalanguage in which 'thing' is taken inclusively to a second limited by the enough; but the generality of semantics is fundamentally fact that no language can be its own semantic metalanguage (Cf. Tarski, no can But universal semantic be hence there and metalanguage. 1936) we can approach generality as closely as we like by taking 'thing' in enough. For the remainder of this paper, let us proceed on the that the set of things has been chosen, almost once and for assumption all, as some very inclusive set: at least as the universe of some intended clusively model possible, set theory with all the non-sets we want, actual or as individuals. Let us ignore the sequence of semantic that still escape treatment. of standard included metalanguages In that case there is overlap between things, sets of things, and truth This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions SEMANTICS GENERAL 27 (Not all sets of things can be things, but some should be.) More if we adopt the sets and truth-values over, there is overlap between common conventions of identifying the truth-values truth and falsity with values. 1 and 0 respectively, and of identifying each natural number extensions and in Thus the appropriate the set of its predecessors. the numbers with for function that is the intension of the name sentences, names, of all contradictions we want however, is harmless. Whenever a of intensions by ordered pairs category for that category. FOR INTENSIONS The overlap. is also same the intension noun 'zero' and of the common IV. nouns common and tensions 'round square'. Such overlap, to get rid of it, we can replace and an intension DERIVED appropriate CATEGORIES it is best to foresake extensions and Carna Turning to derived categories, for instance, a in the interest of generality. Sometimes, pian intensions - that - has an extension like that of a common noun : an is, C/C adjective a set of things to which (at a given index) it applies. Probably 'married' is such an extensional adjective. But most adjectives do not have exten sions. What is the set of things to which 'alleged' applies? An alleged is not something which is, on the one hand, an alleged thing Communist and, on the other hand, a Communist. In general, an takes adjective common and the noun a common to make a new, the new common common noun in a manner of intension com noun noun; deter depends on the intension of the original of the adjective. A meaning for an adjective, mined by the meaning intension therefore, is something that determines how one common-noun pound depends on another. Looking for an entity that does what a meaning does, we are led to say that an appropriate intension for an adjective is any intensions. In function from common-noun intensions to common-noun more from detail indices : it is a function whose to sets. Thus domain the intension and range consist of functions 'alleged' is a function that, of 'windshield', or, given as argument the intension of 'Communist', 'chipmunk' yields as value the intension of the compound common noun or 'alleged chipmunk' respec 'alleged Communist', 'alleged windshield', when tively. Note common-noun that it would extensions not work to use (sets) to common-noun instead a function extensions from ;for at certain This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 28 DAVID LEWIS and 'Maoist' have the same extension but 'alleged and 'alleged Maoist' do not - or, at other indices, vice versa. generally, let us say that an appropriate intension for a (c/c1...cn), 'Communist' indices Communist' More where function from cn are and ..., c, cu any basic categories, ..., and ^-intensions, or is any derived, ?-place to c-intensions. ?-?-intensions That is, it is any function (again in the most general set-theoretic sense) having as as its range of values a set of ?-intensions, its domain of first having as set of the and its domain of nth ..., arguments having q-intensions, set arguments the and makes a c by concatenation; takes of a q-intension and as function ?-intension A ??-intensions. ... and (c/c1...cn) correspondingly, a ??-intension value. We will a ct takes as call these ... and and a cn a (?/q.-.O-intension and arguments intensions a makes for derived some of my intensions. (Intensions resembling compositional in Kaplan, intensions are discussed 1964; in Scott, 1970; compositional - in and - as appropriate intensions for adjectives and other modifiers 1970a. The latter discussion is due in part 1968 and Montague, Parsons, to J. A. W. Kamp.) The general form of the semantic projection rules for categories an interpreted categorial grammar is implicit in the nature of composi tional intensions, just as the general form of the phrase-structure rules is implicit in the nomenclature for derived categories. The result of a concatenating with (c/ci...cn) intension a <j>09 ct with intension (?>u ..., and a cn with intension <j>nis a c with intension 0o(^i---0?) We have considered already the derived category adjective C/C. another example, take the derived category verb phrase, S/N. For to make a sentence. (We rely on the trans to component change the word order if necessary.) An ap - an - is therefore a for verb intension phrase propriate S/N-intension a function from name intensions to sentence intensions. That is, it is a A verb phrase takes a name formational function from functions to truth values. The from to things to functions from indices 'grunts', for instance, is that function any function (?)lfrom indices to things, indices intension of (j)whose value, given as argument is that function <?>2 from indices to truth values truth if , ... _ *2W" world such that, for any index i, grunts </>!(/) is something which and time given by the appropriate dinatesofi falsity otherwise. This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions at the coor GENERAL SEMANTICS 29 rule, we find that the sentence 'Porky grunts' is i such that the thing named by 'Porky' at i grunts that is the world coordinate of i at the time which the projection Applying true at just those indices at the possible world is the time coordinate it comes is spurious; intension of a word of /. (The appearance of circularity of the fact that I am using English of English.) in this account to specify the example, take the derived category adverb (of one sort), An adverb of this sort takes a verb phrase to make a verb (S/N) (S/N). so an intension for such an adverb - an (S/N)/(S/N) appropriate phrase; intension - is a function from verb-phrase in intensions to verb-phrase For another from functions tensions; or, in more detail, a function from functions to func from indices to things to functions from indices to truth-values tions from functions from indices to things to functions from indices to truth-values. I deliver functions I promised from functions from func simplicity; to functions from functions to functions. And worse tions to functions is in store ifwe consider the sort of adverb that modifies ordinary adverbs : the category ((S/N)/(S/N))/((S/N)/(S/N)). Yet I think no apology is called are complicated but the principles of their constructs, are extremely simple. The situation is common : look at any account of the set-theoretic construction of real numbers, yet recall that the real numbers rather well. children often understand to find simpler intensions, but at In some cases, it would be possible for. Intensions construction an exorbitant cost: we would have to give up the uniform function-and form for semantic projection rules. We have noted already arguments that some adjectives are extensional, though most are not. The exten sional adjectives could be given sets as extensions and functions from indices to sets as Carnapian intensions. Similarly for verb phrases: we iff there is a function (/>from indices may call a verb phrase extensional to sets such that if (f)l is the (compositional) intension of the verb phrase, name is / is any index, then is and intension, 03 (?)2 any (?)i(4>2)9 , ._ is a member {truth if 02(0 otherwise. {falsity of </>(/) If there is any such function 4>, there is exactly one; we can call it the intension of the verb phrase and we can call its value at any Carnapian index / the extension of the verb phrase at /. 'Grunts', for instance, is an This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions DAVID 30 LEWIS verb phrase; its extension at an index i is the set of things that and the grunt at the world and the time given by the world coordinate time coordinate of the index /. Verb phrases, unlike adjectives, are ordi but Barbara Partee has pointed out that the verb narily extensional; seems to in 'The of milk is be non-extensional. price phrase rising' extensional There is no harm in noting that extensional adjectives and verb phrases intensions as well as compositional have Carnapian intensions. However, it is the compositional intension that should be used to determine the of intension an or extensional-adjective-plus-common-noun extensional If we used the Carnapian combination. intensions, verb-phrase-plus-name we would have a miscellany of semantic projection rules rather than the uniform function-and-arguments rules using Carnapian projection for reconstructing compositional with the rule. (Indeed, the best way to formulate intensions might be to combine a rule intensions rule function-and-arguments we would sacrifice generality: Moreover, verb phrases would have or not at all. This ones, of adjectives; but not to be treated from Carnapian intensions for compositional intensions.) non-extensional adjectives and from the extensional separately loss of generality would be serious in the case in the case of verb phrases since there are few, verb phrases. if any, non-extensional For the sake of generality, we might wish to take account of selection restrictions intension to be undefined for by allowing a compositional some arguments of appropriate type. If we thought that 'green idea' should lack an intension, for instance, we might conclude that the intension intensions 'green' ought to be a partial function from common-noun of to common-noun intensions, undefined for such arguments as the intension of 'idea'. It proves more convenient, however, never to let the intension be undefined but rather to let it take on a value called the null intension (for the appropriate category). The null intension for the basic categories will be the empty function; the null intension for any derived category that will be whose value for any combina (c/cl...cn) (?/?^..??)-intension tion of appropriate arguments is the null intension for ?. Thus the inten sion of 'green', given as argument the intension of 'idea', yields as value the null intension for the category C. The intension of the adverb 'furious ly', given as argument the intension of 'sleeps', yields as value the null intension for the category (S/N, and that in turn, given as value any name intension, yields as value the null intension for the category S. (I dislike This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions GENERAL this treatment of selection SEMANTICS restrictions, 31 the option but provide for those who want it.) It is worth mentioning that my of and the categories, corresponding pendent of my account of and N-intensions S-intensions or ideas in someone's mind of intensions for derived form for projection rules, is inde for basic categories. Whatever intensions - even of Markerese may be expressions - it still is possible from N-intensions functions account to S-intensions of 'Porky grunts' by applying the intension intension of 'Porky' as argument. V. to take S/N-intensions as and to obtain the intension of 'grunts' as function to the MEANINGS have already observed that intensions for sentences cannot be iden in meaning - for instance, between tified with meanings since differences in intension. The may not carry with them any difference tautologies same goes for other categories, basic or derived. Differences in intension, We in meaning. For fine differences in say, give us coarse differences we to must look the analysis of a compound into constituents meaning For instance 'Snow is and to the intensions of the several constituents. we may or it isn't' differs finely in meaning from of the difference in intension between white because 'Grass is green or it isn't' sentences the embedded and 'Grass is green'. For still finer differences in meaning look in turn to the intensions of constituents of constituents, and 'Snow is white' we must on. so Only when we take sameness Carnap, 'analytic we come of intension 1947, ? 14, on to lexical non-compound, constituents can as a sufficient condition 'intensional isomorphism'; of synonymy. (See C. I. Lewis, 1944, on meaning'.) It is natural, with semantically inter therefore, to identify meanings their terminal nodes: finite ordered trees preted phrase markers minus intension. If we asso having at each note a category and an appropriate ciate a meaning of this sort with an expression, we are given the category of the expression; and if the expression is compound, we are given also the categories and intensions of its constituent parts, their constituent parts, and so on down. and intension Perhaps we would thereby cut meanings will be unable to agree with someone who too finely. For instance, we says that a double negation This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions DAVID 32 LEWIS has the same meaning as the corresponding affirmative. But this difficulty does not worry me :we will have both intensions and what I call meanings, and sometimes one and as an be preferable some about meanings. Perhaps can also be found, but I doubt that there the other will sometimes of our explication ordinary entities of intermediate fineness discourse is any uniquely natural way to do so. It may be disturbing that in our explication of meanings we have made - for in an index. instance, of the order of coordinates arbitrary choices - how can we choose to construct them in one are Meanings meanings to set is a general objection way rather than another? The objection so not I will theoretic constructions Benacerraf, (see 1965), reply to it are here. But if it troubles you, you may prefer to say that real meanings I call 'meanings' do duty for sui generis entities and that the constructs a because there is real meanings natural one-to-one be correspondence tween them and the real meanings. also be disturbing that I have spoken of categories without a matter of arbitrary choice; are. what This is they saying again we might, for instance, take them as sets of expressions in some language, or as sets of intensions, or even as arbitrarily chosen code-numbers. It It might hitherto turns out to be most convenient, to identify cate if slightly unnatural, own names: in with their the proper way expressions gories composed out of the letters 'S', 'N', 'C (and whatever others we may introduce later in considering revisions of the system) together with parentheses and our slashes. This does not prevent from being category-names diagonal names of categories: involving they name themselves. All definitions categories are to be understood categories and in accordance with the identification of category-names. Some might even wish to know what a tree is. Very well : it is a function that assigns to each member of the set of nodes of the tree an object said to occupy or be at that node. The nodes themselves are finite sequences of positive numbers. A set of such sequences is the set of nodes of some tree iff, first, it is a finite set, and second, whenever it contains a sequence <[b1.. .bk} then it also contains every sequence that is an initial segment of <?>i..A> and every sequence <ei..A-i?>fc> with 0k<0k- We regard zero as of the the sequence topmost node; (b{) as the Z^th < >, length, node from the left immediately beneath < >; (bt b2} as the b2th node from the left immediately beneath <[b{); and so on. We can easily define This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions GENERAL SEMANTICS 33 notions of tree theory in terms of this construction. identified meanings with semantically interpreted phrase it becomes natural to reconstrue the phrase-structure rules of all the requisite Once we have markers, grammar, together with the corresponding projection rules, as of well-formedness for meanings. 1968.) Ac (Cf. McCawley, cordingly, we now define a meaning as a tree such that, first, each node is occupied by an ordered pair <? 0> of a category and an appropriate intension for that category; and second, immediately beneath any non categorial conditions terminal node occupied by such a pair <? <?>are two or more nodes, and these are occupied by pairs <?0 0O>, <?x^X ..., <?? 0?> (in that order) such that ?o is (c/c1...cn) and (?>is ^oO^i---^?) A meaning may be a tree with a single node; call such meanings simple and other meanings are, as it were, compound. Compound meanings in built up from simple meanings which several meanings by steps (simple or compound) are combined as sub-trees under a new node, analogously are built up by concatenating in which expressions shorter a a a m' constituent call We may meaning of meaning m iff expressions. m' is a subtree of m. We may say that a meaning m is generated by a set of m belongs to that set. iff every simple constituent of simple meanings to the way generally, m is generated by a set of meanings (simple or compound) iff every simple constituent of m is a constituent of some constituent of m, possibly itself, which belongs to that set. as though they were We shall in many ways speak of meanings sym More expressions generated by an interpreted categorial grammar, even is the though they are nothing of the sort. The category of a meaning as of its intension found the first node. The topmost category component bolic of its top is the intension found as the second component of a meaning name most node. The extension at an index i of a sentence meaning, or common-noun is the value of the intension of the meaning meaning, i. A sentence meaning is true or false at i for the argument or a as names name at i truth its is extension falsity, according meaning at i that thing, if any, which is its extension at /; and a common-noun meaning meaning we have derived things belong to its extension at /. As applies at i to whatever in seen, extensions might also be provided for certain meanings a non as or cannot such but be done in this S/N, categories C/C artificial, general way. Given as fundamental the definition of truth of a sentence meaning This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions at DAVID 34 LEWIS an index, we can define many derivative truth relations. Coordinates of the index may be made explicit, or may be determined by a context of over all coordinates, utterance, or may be generalized over. Generalizing we can say that a sentence meaning is analytic (in one sense) iff it is true over the world and assignment at every index. Generalizing coordinates be determined by context, we can and letting the remaining coordinates is analytic (in another sense) on a given say that a sentence meaning occasion iff it is true at every index / having as its time, place, and previous-discourse coordinates indicated-objects speaker, audience, ively the time, the place, the speaker, to, and the previous discourse pointed over the time and assignment cluding world) be determined respect the audience, the set of objects on that occasion. Generalizing coordinates and letting the others (in we define eternal truth of a by context, over the assignment on an occasion; co sentence meaning generalizing ordinate and letting all the rest be determined by context, we define and so on. simply truth on an occasion; We also can define truth relations even stronger than truth at every index. Let us call a meaning m' a semantic variant of a meaning m iff m and m' have exactly the same nodes, with the same category but not a common the same intension at each node, and, whenever necessarily in m, a common intension also us an m' call appears s-fixed semantic iffm and m' are semantic variant ofm, where s is a set of simple meanings, of s which is a constituent of m is also a variants and every member intension constituent, appears at those at the at two terminal nodes two nodes in m'. same ofm'. place, Let Then we can call a sentence meaning s-true iff every ?'-fixed semantic variant of it (including itself) is true at s we would of If the set whose is bearers index. every simple meanings we as s-true call sentence then may logical vocabulary, classify meanings logically true; if s is the set of simple meanings whose bearers we would classify as mathematical (including logical) vocabulary, we may call s-true we can define a true. Analogously, sentence meanings mathematically and relation of s-fixed semantic variance between sequences of meanings; we can say that a sentence meaning m0 is an s-consequence (for instance, a logical consequence or mathematical ml9 ... iff, for every ?-fixed semantic (m0 mx ...> and every true at i. (The premises consequence) of sentence meanings of the sequence variant <jnQm\...y index / such that all of m'l9 ... are true at i9m0 is mi9 ... may be infinite in number. Their order is This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions GENERAL SEMANTICS 35 in terms of insignificant.) These definitions are adapted from definitions truth in all logically or mathematically standard interpretations of a given language. However, we have been able to avoid introducing of alternative of a language, since so far we interpretations with entirely meanings. the notion are dealing VI. GRAMMARS RECONSTRUCTED of meanings may serve, in effect, as a universal base for transformational based grammars. There is no need to repeat categorially as a base com rules of categorial well-formedness the phrase-structure Our system as given, ponent in each such grammar. Instead, we take the meanings a relation and regard a grammar as specifying a way to encode meanings: and certain expressions between certain meanings (sequences of sound we or which will call the of types representing relation deter mark-types) by the grammar. We might just identify grammars with representing but I prefer to take grammars as systems which determine representing relations in a certain way. mined relations; If we were concerned with nothing but transformation-free categorial we could take a grammar to consist of nothing but a lexicon: grammars, ? is a a finite set of triples of the form <e ? 0> where e is an expression, and category, say that an <?>is an intension expression e represents appropriate or has for that category. We a meaning m relative may to a lexicon <[ex ct 0X>, ..., <?? ?? </>?>such that, first, e is the result of concatenating el9 ..., en (in that order), and second, the of m are occupied terminal nodes ..., <?? </>?>(in that by <?x $!>, L iff L contains items order). We could in two steps. Let us define a (cate instead have proceeded as a tree marker nodes having categories at its non-terminal gorial) phrase a and expressions at its terminal nodes. Then phrase marker p represents to a lexicon L iff p is obtained from m as of the meaning m occupied by a pair terminal node given any node it another below occupied by an expression e such that <? </>>,place c in the lexicon; then remove the intensions, the item (e <?> is contained node by its unaccompanied replacing the <? (j)} pair at each non-terminal or has a meaning m relative follows: thus representable that the set of meanings relative to category ?. Note a lexicon L comprises all and only those meanings that are generated by This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions DAVID 36 LEWIS the set of simple meanings of the lexical items themselves; let us call it the set of meanings the L. lexicon generated by Next, we define the terminal string of a phrase marker p as the expres sion obtained by concatenating, in order, the expressions at the terminal e represents a meaning m of;?. Thus we see that an expression to a lexicon L, according to the definition iff e is the above, terminal string of some phrase marker that represents m relative to L. nodes relative In the case of a categorially based transformational grammar, we have not two steps but three. Such a grammar consists of a lexicon L together with a transformational component T. The latter imposes finitely many on finite sequences of phrase markers. A sequence <[pl.. ./??> of phrase markers that satisfies the constraints imposed by T will be a called derivation ofpnfromp1 in T. An expression e (transformational) represents or has a meaning m in a grammar <L T> iff there exists a deri constraints in T such that e is the terminal string of pn and px (Pi-.-Pn) m to the lexicon L. If so, we will also call e a meaning relative represents vation ful expression, pn a surface structure ofe,pn^1 and ... and/?2 intermediate ofe, p? a base structure ofe, and m a meaning ofe (all relative to the grammar <L T>). However, we will call any phrase marker;? a base structure in <L T> iff it represents a meaning relative to L, whether or not it structures structure o/any expression; thus we allow for base structures are filtered out by not being the first term of any derivation in T. The representing relation given by a grammar <L T> is by no means a one-to-one between meanings and expressions. A given correspondence is the base which several different meanings. expression might be ambiguous, representing it several different but cointensive it (If represents however, meanings, to common call it ambiguous; for the notion of might be inappropriate seems to hover between our technical notions of meaning and meaning of intension.) On the other hand, several expressions might be synonymous, a single meaning. We might also call several expressions representing iff they share all their meanings; completely synonymous synonymy and complete synonymy coincide when we are dealing only with unambiguous If several expressions represent different but cointensive we call them If several may meanings, equivalent but not synonymous. same not the but also have a single expressions only represent meaning base structure, we may call them not only equivalent and synonymous but also paraphrases of one another. expressions. This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions GENERAL SEMANTICS 37 Given a representing relation, all the semantic relations defined hitherto for meanings carry over to expressions having those meanings. (If we over to also the and intermediate base, surface, like, they may carry structures between and the expressions.) Thus we know the meanings what itmeans to speak, relative to a given grammar and qualified in cases or 'on all meanings', of the category and of ambiguity by 'on a meaning' at a given index of the extension intension of any meaningful expression; of of the of any expression thing named by a name; appropriate category; of the things to which a common noun applies; of the truth at an index, truth on an occasion, so analyticity, logical truth, etc. of a sentence; and on. should note an oddity in our treatment of logical truth. A synonym of a logically true sentence is itself a logical truth, since it represents the a descendant as the original. Hence same logically true meaning by We of a logical is confined truth is itself a logical truth if the to single lexical items in the base synonym-substitution are groundhogs' comes out not 'All otherwise. woodchucks structure; but 'All squares are equilateral rectangles' comes out logically true, whereas synonym-substitution merely analytic (in the strongest sense). A transformational component may constrain markers in two ways. There is the local constraint sequences of phrase that any two adjacent in a derivation must stand in one of finitely many rela phrase markers tions; these permitted relations between adjacent phrase markers are the constraints transformations. There may also be global derivational speci or relations between markers fying phrase non-adjacent properties of the as a whole. An example is the constraint requiring transfor to mations apply in some specified cyclic (or partly cyclic) order. A transformation-free categorial grammar is a special case of a cate It has a transformational grammar. gorially based transformational derivation no transformations so that the or global constraints, therein are all and only those sequences <[p{) consisting of a single phrase marker. or a I will not attempt to say more exactly what a transformation transformational is. definitions have component Mathematically precise component derivations with been given (for instance in Peters and Ritchie, 1969), but to choose among these would in syntactic involve taking sides on disputed questions no to I I maintain have and my theory. prefer present need neutrality, This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions DAVID 38 for a precise delineation in mind have foremost LEWIS of the class of transformational grammars. I a sort of grammar simplified Aspects-model to I but have said eliminate various alternatives. 1965), (Chomsky, nothing to eliminate generative I have said nothing I have semantics. What to call the 'lexicon' chosen is the initial lexicon. Words not in that lexicon on the way from base to surface, might be introduced transformationally if that seems desirable. It might even be that none of the initial lexical items ever reach the surface, and that all surface lexical items (expressions at terminal nodes of surface structures) are introduced transfor In that case it would be appropriate to use within derivations. mationally found a standardized in all grammars, and to rechristen my base In that case also there might or representations'. not be a level between base and surface at which word-introducing structures initial lexicon 'semantic might transformations are done and other have not yet begun. semantics. This may seem transformations I have also said nothing to eliminate surface are to be determined by strange, since I have indeed said that meanings I rely here on the observation base structures alone. However, (Lakoff, rules are indistinguishable 1970, ? 3) that surface-structure interpretation from global derivational constraints relating three levels: base structures (regarded as semantic representations), deep structures (an intermediate a structures structures. and surface Deep might be ambiguous; level), grammar with two derivations transformational mit base-deep-surface constraints might per <ph...pD...pi} <Pb?jPd?/>!> differing at the base and surface but not at the deep of the forms rule out other derivations level, but it might <j>B?PD?p?y <J>b~-Pd?Ps} In such a case base structure (and hence meaning) would be determined by deep and surface structure together, but not by deep structure alone. Similarly, we might have constraints relating base structure not only to structure to structure at various other inter and but surface also deep mediate I have levels. said nothing to eliminate a non-trivial phonological component; This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions GENERAL SEMANTICS 39 The relocate it as part of the transformational component. derivation might go from the usual last few steps of a transformational surface structure to a post-phonological surface struc pre-phonological ture whence the output expression can be obtained simply by concate but I would nation of terminal nodes. an elaborate to eliminate said nothing system of selection on the lexical in as not will but restrictions these appear restrictions; and base structures but as transformational sertions between meanings I have filtering later on. There will be base structures representing the meanings sentences as 'Seventeen eats beans' and 'He sang a of such questionable But these base structures need not be the first terms toothbrush'. pregnant so these meanings may be unrepresented of any derivations, by sentences. If we restrictions, we might match the lexicon to the trans in such a way as to filter out just those meanings formational component that have the null intension. like selection I have not stipulated that only sentential meanings may be represented; that stipulation could be added if there is reason for it. In fact, the only restriction I place on syntax is that transformational based. In other words: a transforma grammars should be categorially tional component should operate on a set of categorial phrase markers a set of meanings generated by some lexicon. But categorial representing are that this restriction is not at all severe. I claim bases varied enough that whatever familiar sort of base component you may favor on syn tactic grounds, you can find a categorial base (i.e. a suitable part of the system of meanings, lexicon) that re generated by a suitable chosen sembles the base you favor closely enough to share its attractive proper ties. Indeed, with a few preliminary you can rearranging transformations go from my categorial base structures to (notational variants of) more familiar base structures; then you can proceed exactly as before. I shall not marshall evidence for this claim; but I think that the following explo treatments of quantification will exhibit ration of alternative categorial the close treatments and several categorial to choose If it were necessary alternative familiar base components. for semantics and a non between a categorial base that was convenient syntax, I might categorial base that was convenient for transformational similarities between these the former. But I deny the need to choose. of my proposed the exposition system completes still choose This of categories, This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions DAVID 40 LEWIS - either intensions, and meanings. Now I shall consider how this system as is or slightly revised might be applied to two difficult areas: the semantics of quantification and the semantics of non-declaratives. The are intended only as illustrations, however; many following are further alternatives possible, and might be more convenient for syntax. treatments VII. TREATMENT OF QUANTIFICATION AND NOUN PHRASES Let us consider such expressions as 'a pig', 'most pigs', 'seventeen pigs', 'roughly seventeen pigs', 'some yellow pig', 'everything', 'nobody', and the like. We call these quantifier phrases (presupposing that they should in our system is this? category belong to a common category). What sort of intensions do quantifier phrases have? What to make combine with verb phrases sentences: Quantifier phrases 'Some pig grunts', 'Nobody grunts', 'Roughly seventeen pigs grunt', and the like. Names do this, since the category verb phrase is the derived But category S/N. quantifier phrases cannot be names, under our se treatment of mantic names, because they do not in general name any thing. ('The pig' could be an exception at indices such that exactly one pig existed at the world and time given by the index.) The absurd conse quences of treating 'nobody', as a name, for instance, are well known (Dodgson, 1871). If a quantifier phrase combines with an S/N to make an S, and yet is not an N, it must therefore be an S/(S/N). Except perhaps for one-word 'nobody', 'every quantifier phrases common nouns. thing', and such quantifier phrases contain constituent as in 'every These may be either simple, as in 'some pig' or compound, a we common nouns wins blue that ribbon'. may regard Indeed, pink pig simply as predicates from Montague, used 1970a.) to restrict quantifiers. The expressions 'a', (This suggestion 'the', 'some', and so on which derives 'every', combine 'no', with 'most', 'seventeen', 'roughly seventeen', common nouns (simple or compound) to make quantifier phrases and which are variously called quantifiers, determiners, or articles must there of quantifiers like fore belong to the category (S/(S/N))/C. And modifiers to with make which combine certain 'roughly' quantifiers quantifiers, must belong to the category ((S/(S/N))/C)/((S/(S/N))/C). Selection re by means of transformational of quantifiers like 'roughly the'. strictions filtering could be used to dispose This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions GENERAL The SEMANTICS 41 of 'some pig' may be taken as that function (?>from S/N such that if (?)xis any S/N-intension, (?)2 is the * then and is anY index, <t>(<t>\), intension intensions S-intension to S-intensions *2(0 truth if, for some N-intension = (j>3, </>3(/) is a pig and if 04 is (?>1(4>3) then 04(O is truth falsity otherwise. be taken as that function 0 from C-inten such that if (?)1is any C-intension, (?)2 is the $4 is the S-intension S/(S/N)-intension <H0i)> $3 is anY S/N-intension, I is then and anY index, 02(03)> The intension of 'some' may sions to S/(S/N)-intensions *4(0 rrwr/?if, for some N-intension (?>5,(?)5(i) is a member of (?)i(i) and if 06 is 03(</>5) then </>6(0 is rntf? = falsity otherwise. I spare you the intension of 'roughly'. Other intensions might be specified for 'some pig' and 'some' that would differ from these only when a quantifier phrase was applied to a verb phrases verb phrase. If there are no non-extensional non-extensional in English, is arbitrary. then the choice among these alternatives This treatment of quantifier phrases ismotivated by a desire to handle as as sentences involving quantifier phrases straightforwardly simple use of transformations. But it raises problems. the possible, minimizing Quantifier phrases seemingly occur not only as subjects of sentences but also as objects of verbs or prepositions. And in all their roles - as subjects or as objects - they are interchangeable with names. That is why it is usual to have a category noun phrase comprising both quantifier phrases and names. We might try the heroic course of doubling all our object-takers. We could have one word 'loves' which is an (S/N)/N and takes the object 'Petunia' another to make it and alongside 'loves Petunia'; phrase is an (S/N)/(S/(S/N)) and takes the object 'some the verb phrase 'loves some pig'. But we need not decide the verb 'loves' which pig' to make how much we mind It would since it does not work doubling, for 'Every boy loves some girl' : the sentence can be true even if each boy such extravagant give us one meaning anyway. on which the weaker meaning, loves a different girl. But the sentence is ambiguous; where This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions shall we get DAVID 42 a stronger meaning, on which LEWIS the sentence - is true only if a certain girl (There are those who do not is loved by all boys? perhaps this ambiguity; but we seek a treatment Zuleika, to general enough of do.) The method doubling object look to the method rather we must of variable perceive handle the idiolects of those who is a blind takers alley; routinely used in the semantic binding, symbolic logic. The quantifiers analysis of standardly formulated of symbolic logic belong to the category S/NS, taking to make a sentence. The name must be a variable; a name and a sentence other could be disposed of by transformational filtering. the 'some' takes the variable V and instance, logician's quantifier the sentence 'grunts x9 to make a sentence translatable into English as combinations For 'something grunts'. The logician's 'some' has as its intension that function to S-intensions and S-intensions such that if (?)l is <j>from N-intensions the wth variable intension for any number is <t>(<?>i<?>2), and i is any index, then n9 <?>2is any S-intension, 03 ' truth if, for some index / that is like / except perhaps at tne wtn term ?f tne assignment coordinate, a. /-\_ (?>2(?) is truth falsity otherwise; that is not a variable intension and and such that if <f>xis any N-intension then <?(0i<?2) is the null intension. The intension <j>2is any S-intension, of the logician's quantifier 'every' is specified similarly, with 'for every index /'...' It would replacing some index /'...'. in a grammar quantifiers are unrestricted, ranging 'Some pig grunts', for instance, to employ logician's In the first place, these quantifiers for English. over everything. would 'for be troublesome The base structure of come out as S/NS some S N x S S/SS S and S/N N ! x pig S/N N Ill grunts This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions x GENERAL in which 'pig' and structures SEMANTICS 43 there is no constituent to 'some pig' and in which corresponding are into the put 'grunts' category S/N. (It was with like this in mind that Ajdukiewicz saw fit to omit the category to with attempt dispense quantifier phrases in favor of unre alike C.) This stricted quantifiers taking compound fails entirely for quantifiers such as sentences is clumsy at best, and 'most' (see Wallace, 1965). In the second place, by having the quantifier itself do the binding of variables, we require there to be bound variables wherever there are quantifiers. We get the unnecessarily base structure complicated S/NS SN I x some I /\S/N N i, grunts x i for 'Something grunts', whereas if we had employed quantifier phrases take verb phrases and do not bind variables, we could have had which something with three constituents grunts instead of six and no work for the transformations to do. It is not that the quantifier itself should bind necessary, however, variables. We can stick with verb-phrase-taking quantifier phrases of the category S/(S/N), restricted by constituent common nouns in most cases, and bind variables when necessary - but only when necessary - by means of a separate constituent called a binder: a certain sort of (S/N)/S that a sentence and makes an extensional takes verb phrase by binding a at all its free occurrences (if any) in the sentence. To every a binder. Suppose there corresponds '*' is a variable; we may write its corresponding binder as *x9 and read it as 'is something x such that'. (But presumably binders may best be treated as base constituents that never reach the surface; so if the words 'is something x such that' variable variable This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 44 DAVID LEWIS ever appear in a meaningful expression, they will be derived not from an 'x' in base structure but in some other way.) For instance, the following base structure using a binder is equivalent to 'grunts' and might be read loosely as 'is something x such that x grunts'. S/N The following McCawley, might be a base structure for 'Porky loves himself. (Cf. 1969.) (S/N)/S (Provided there is no ambiguity among our variables, we can use them in this way to keep track of coreferentiality, rather than subscripting the This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions GENERAL names SEMANTICS 45 in S/N N N (S/N)/N loves Porky Porky we are dealing with one Porky or two.) binder 6x9 intension, then the corresponding has the nth binder intension : that function to S/N from S-intensions </> such that if <?>1is any S-intension, intensions is the <?>2 S/N-intension to indicate whether If 'x9 has the ?th variable <M0i)> $3 is anY N-intension, </>4is the S-intension (?)2((j)3), i is any index, and /' is that index which has cb?>(i) as the nth term of its assignment = coordinate and otherwise is like i, then <)!>4(/) It can be verified 0i(Othat this intension justifies the reading of 'x9 as 'is something x such that'. supply of variables and binders, however large, would lead to the mistaken omission of some sentences. To provide an infinite supply by means of a finite lexicon, we must allow our variables and binders to A finite be generated as compounds. We need only three lexical items :one simple variable having the first variable intension; an N/N having as intension a function whose value, given as argument the nth variable intension for is the (n+ l)th variable intension; and an ((S/N)/S)/N any ?^1, having as intension a function whose value, given as argument the nth variable intension for any ri^\, is the nth binder intension. The first item gives us a starting variable; the second, the other iterated, manufactures binders out of variables. However, variables; the third manufactures will continue to abbreviate base structures by writing variables binders as if they were simple. we and introduces a sort of spurious ambiguity called alpha Variable-binding could have not only the structure betic variance. 'Porky loves himself 'x' and '?' are replaced by 'y9 and 'j>', shown but also others in which or V and 'f, etc. Since different variables may have different intensions, to infinitely many different but cointensive these structures correspond for 'Porky loves himself. The simplest way to deal with this meanings nuisance is to define an ordering of any such set of meanings and employ This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions DAVID 46 LEWIS in the set filtering to dispose of all but the first meaning to the ordering). (according been discussed by logicians, under the name Binders have occasionally or 'lambda 'abstraction operators' operators'. (Church, 1941; Carnap, and Stalnaker, 1958, ? 33; Thomason 1968.) transformational to complete our account of the category in a position of quantifier phrases, using binders as needed. verb-phrase-taking S/(S/N) The base structure for 'Every boy loves Zuleika' may be simply Now we are (S/(S/N))/C every C(S/N)/N boy N loves Zuleika to make work for the transfor no unnecessary variable-binding is another base structure with variable There mational component. we read which may roughly as 'Every boy is something x such binding it represents a different but equivalent meaning. that x loves Zuleika'; with can structure and another (but or for 'Every boy loves Zuleika' get rid of them by equivalent) meaning transformational filtering. The base structure for 'Lothario loves some is girl' We either let these be another base the quantifier phrase which is the surface object of 'loves' is the variable treated as subject of a verb phrase obtained by binding structure is the base object of 'loves'. To reach an intermediate which in which This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions GENERAL SEMANTICS 47 the quantifier phrase is relocated as the object of 'loves', we that moves the subject of a verb have recourse to a transformation phrase made by variable binding into the place of one (the first?) occur in which must rence of the bound variable and destroys the variable-binding apparatus. that, if desired, this transformation might apply beneath an inter most closely to the ordinary level of deep mediate level corresponding structure. The two base structures for 'Every boy loves some girl' are Note for the weak (S/(S/N))/C C some girl (S/ND/S S^ N S/N y (S/N)/N N loves y x sense, and (S/(S/N))/C C N (S/N)/N every boy loves for the strong - Zuleika - sense. It may be that quantifier-phrase 'Lothario seeks a girl', altogether. phrased as 'Lothario structure x objects should not be abandoned in the sense in which it can be para seeks a certain particular girl', can have This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions the base DAVID 48 LEWIS (S/(S/N))/C but what it the base about the sense in which any old girl would do? We might give structure S (S/N)/(S/(S/N)) S/(S/N) seeks (S/(S/N))/C objects. The alternative using a second 'seeks' that takes quantifier-phrase to is let the word 'seeks' be introduced rather than transformationally so that the descendant of 'strives-to-find', lexically, as a transformational base structures would be S This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions GENERAL for the sense in which SEMANTICS a certain particular 49 girl is sought and S/N (S/N)/S i strives S/(S/N) S/N (S/(S/N))/C C a girl (S/N)/SS x N S/N (S/N)/N N Lothario finds for the sense in which this treatment to 'conceives any old girl would do. But it is controversial whether we ought to let words be introduced transformationally in this way; and (as remarked in Montague ,1969) it is not clear how to apply of a tree'. Perhaps to-exist, but perhaps not. This completes one treatment conceiving-of is imagining of quantifier phrases, carried out with no modification of the system I originally presented. It is straightforward from the semantic point of view; however, it might result in excessive to transformational syntax. Ordinary bases have a category complications noun phrase which combines quantifier phrases and names; and transfor seem to work well on bases of that sort. By dividing the category mations to be doubled (or of noun phrases, I may require some transformations are etc.). Moreover, my structures involving variable-binding so remote and from the with surface, by doing away complicated quanti com lots of work for the transformational fier-phrase objects I make ponent. It might be, therefore, that this treatment is too costly to syntax. quadrupled, Therefore phrase. let us see how we might reinstate the combined category noun are two methods: we might try to assimilate names to or we to assimilate try might phrases, quantifier phrases to There quantifier names. The method of assimilating names to quantifier phrases proceeds This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions as DAVID 50 LEWIS follows. For every name in our lexicon, for instance 'Porky', we add to our lexicon a corresponding pseudo-name in the category S/(S/N). If the intension of the original name 'Porky' is the N-intension then the </>1? intension of the corresponding pseudo-name 'Porky*' should be that to S-intensions function such that for any S/N <?>from S/N-intensions = a a intension sentence As such as 'Porky result, (?)290(02) 02(0i)can either of structures be the base grunts' given S/CS/N) S/N Porky* and will have grunts the same intension either way. The category S/(S/N) may noun phrase. It contains our former quantifier phrases our new pseudo-names. It does not contain names them now be renamed together with selves. Names are now unnecessary as subjects, but still needed as objects; so the next step is to replace all name-takers except verb phrases by noun For instance, the category (S/N)/N of transitive verbs is phrase-takers. to be replaced by the category (S/N)/(S/(S/N)) of pseudo-transitive verbs. are related to the intensions of the intensions of the replacements a I in which shall not bother to specify. Names way systematic originals now serve no further purpose, having been supplanted both as subjects so the next step is to remove names and as objects by pseudo-names; The the lexicon. The category N is left vacant. for noun-phrase Since we have provided objects we can have also pseudo-names, quantifier-phrase from down on variable-binding. For instance, for the sake of the objects so cut and we have S/(S/N) S/N (S/(S/N))/C every C boy S/CS/N) (S/N)/(S/(S/N)) loves (S/(S/N))/C C I some This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions girl I GENERAL as the base structure no work for SEMANTICS 51 for 'Every boy loves some girl' in the weak sense, the transformations. cannot do away with We leaving variable-binding altogether, however. The base structure loves some girl' in the strong - Zuleika - sense is now CS/(S/N))/C every C boy for 'Every boy (S/N)/(S/(S/N)) S/CS/N) loves x* the seeming noun-phrase object 'some girl' is treated as subject noun phrase of a verb phrase obtained by binding the pseudo-variable 'x*' which is the real object of'loves'. Variables are names, of course, and in which are replaced by pseudo-names just as any other names are; no in is the binders. made, however, corresponding change we not So far have departed from the system I presented originally, and we could stop here. It is now advantageous, however, to take the step therefore of eliminating the category N altogether and promoting the category verb a a new to from derived basic category S/N category VP. Accord phrase noun of becomes the category ingly, phrases S/VP; the category of quan of transitive verbs becomes the category (S/VP)/C; and the category which includes binders becomes VP/S. VP/(S/VP); We can also reopen the question of letting verb-phrase intensions be rather than We this compositional. rejected Carnapian simplification rule which was before, principally because it would require a projection tifiers becomes not of our general function-and-arguments form; but that consideration no longer holds after names and verb-phrase-plus-name combinations are done still applies: the simplification away with. A lesser objection If any non-extensional verb for extensional verb works only phrases. phrases exist, they cannot go into our new basic category VP with Carnapian intensions. They will have to go into the category This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions S/(S/VP) DAVID 52 LEWIS to Carnapian for the now-basic intensions verb a I most other intensions in which need systematic way phrases changes not stop to specify. We turn last to the opposite method, in which quantifier phrases are to names to give an undivided assimilated category of noun phrases. instead. This will manner The switch require discussed and intensions of names in a revising the extensions Mates by 1968) and Montague (Mates, (Montague, 1969 and 1970b). In the dark ages of logic, a story something like this was told. The a we names call the existentially 'some may strange thing phrase pig' some has which that those generic pig just properties pig has. Since some pig ismale, some pig (a different one) is female, some pig is pink (all over), and some pig is grey (all over), the existentially generic pig is simultane he (she?) is in the female, pink, and grey. Accordingly, ously male, extensions both of 'is male' and of 'is female', both of 'is pink all over' and of 'is grey all over'. The phrase 'every pig' names a different strange thing called the universally generic pig which has just those properties that every pig has. Since not every pig is pink, grey, or any other color, the universally generic pig is not of any color. (Yet neither is he colorless, - indeed not since not every any pig is colorless). Nor is he(?) male or female (or neuter), since not every pig is any one of these. He is, however, a pig and an animal, and he grunts; for every pig is a pig and an animal, and grunts. There are also the negative universally generic pig which has that no pig has (he is not a pig, but he is both a just those properties stone a number), that more the majority generic pig which has just those than half of all pigs have, and many more. A properties sentence formed from a name and an extensional verb phrase is true (we may add: at an index i) if and only if the thing named by the name (at /) and belongs to the extension of the verb phrase (at i); and this is so regardless of whether the name happens to be a name like 'Porky' of an ordinary a or name like 'some pig' of a generic thing. thing since nothing, however recondite, can possi story is preposterous or one more than of a set of incompatible and jointly ex have less bly haustive properties. At least, nothing can have more or less than one of This them as its properties. But something, a set, can have any combination in that. there is no contradiction of them as its members; Let us define the character of a thing as the set of its properties. This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Porky's GENERAL SEMANTICS 53 that is that set which has as members just those properties not as could do and The various has not, generic pigs Porky properties. of the but their characters The character do. universally possibly, exist; just those proper generic pig, for instance, is the set having as members ties that every pig has as properties. character is any set of properties. A character is individual iff it is a so that something could possess set of properties, compatible in it; otherwise is contained the character all and only the properties A character maximal generic. Since no two things share all their properties (on a sufficiently inclusive to their individual conception of properties) things correspond one-to-one to replace things by their characters. We can exploit this correspondence have even tried to philosophers eliminate things altogether in favor of their characters, saying that things are 'bundles of properties'. (Such a system is proposed as a formal recon in Mates, individuals struction of Leibniz's doctrine of possible 1968.) characters We whenever convenient. need not go so far. We will extensions of and names, Some replace as members things by individual of extensions of characters common as nouns. However, we may keep the things themselves as well, taking them to be related to their names via their characters. Having made this substitution, we are ready to assimilate quantifier phrases to names by letting them also take characters - in most cases, generic characters - as extensions. 'Porky' has as extension Porky's individual character; 'every pig' has as extension the generic character of the universally generic pig. Even 'no the set of just those properties that nobody has. body' has an extension: as follows. Our basic categories are We revise the system of meanings ex sentence (S), noun phrase (NP), and common noun (C). Appropriate are truth values extensions for noun ; appropriate exten phrases are characters, either individual or generic; appropriate sions for common nouns are sets of individual characters. Intensions are tensions for sentences for basic categories, functions from some or all indices to ap for a derived category (c/c1...cn), functions from propriate extensions; ..., and ??-intensions to c-intensions. A name is an NP that q-intensions, as before: never has a generic character of quantifiers becomes NP/C; as its extension at any index. The category the category of verb phrases becomes S/NP. take NP objects which may or may not be names. Some Object-takers still is required; the two base structures for 'Every boy variable-binding This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions DAVID 54 LEWIS loves some girl' are S/NP NP NP (S/NP)/NP loves C NP/C C every boy I I some for the weak NP/C girl sense and S/NP*" (S/NP)/S x S/NP NP (S/NP)/NP NP loves x C NP/C every boy for the strong sense. Variables are names: the nth variable intension now that assigns to every index / the character at that NP-intension becomes the world coordinate of / of the thing that is the nth term of the assign ment of i. The coordinate VIII. intensions TREATMENT OF of binders are revised to fit. NON-DECLARATIVES A meaning for a sentence, we said initially, was at least that which deter mines the conditions under which the sentence is true or false. But it is sentences that can be called true or false in any straight only declarative sentences: commands, forward way. What of non-declarative questions, as they are commonly and so on? If these do not have truth-values, supposed not to, we cannot their truth conditions. One method of treating very well say that their meanings non-declaratives is to analyze determine all sentences, This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions GENERAL SEMANTICS 55 a sentence radical or non-declarative, into two components: that specifies a state of affairs and a mood that determines whether the declarative is declaring that the state of affairs holds, commanding that it or it whether the what. of hold, asking holds, (I adopt terminology one a are recent to of such Stenius, 1967, view.) We exposition regard the sentences speaker It is the case that you are late. it the case that you are late! Is it the case that you are late? Make or more idiomatically You are late. Be late! Are you late? as having a common sentence-radical specifying the state of affairs con of but im your being late, declarative, differing in their moods: sisting structures be the and base given interrogative. They might perative, late be with S now understood will induce different the different sentences as the category sentence radical. Different moods transformations of the sentence radical, leading to above. The sentence radical is not a declarative If it is represented on the surface at all, it should be represented as the clause 'that you are late'. All that we have said about sentences sentence. be taken as applying rather to sentence radicals. It is sentence as extensions, from indices to that have truth-values functions as intensions, truth-values and meanings the with category S and an should radicals S-intension at the topmost node. We may grant that a declarative This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions sentence DAVID 56 LEWIS radical has the value truth ; if we liked, we or other non-declarative call an imperative or interrogative sentence true iff its sentence radical has the value truth, but we customarily se the entire apparatus of referential do not. Fundamentally, however, is called could true iff its sentence also mantics or otherwise) (whether done on a categorial base as I propose, to sentence radicals and constituents thereof. The semantics of pertains mood is something entirely different. such as these (adapted from Stenius, It consists of rules of language use 1967): an S of the mood the combination declarative with representing m only if m is true on the occasion in question. to a sentence the combination of the mood representing imperative with an m (if adressed over in a suitable to you by a person relation of authority S-meaning in such a way as to make m true on the occasion in question. you) by acting Utter a sentence meaning React the theory of language use, a a, be pair of a mood and an S-mean simply identified with some arbitrarily chosen entities). In abstract meaning semantics, for a sentence as distinct from should ing (moods being of sentence The method requires a substantial revision of my for declaratives, imperatives, and yes-no questions. radicals system. It works well It is hard to see how it could be applied sentences like 'Hurrah for Porky!' to other sorts of questions, or to I prefer an alternative method of treating non-declaratives that requires no revision whatever in my system of categories, intensions, and mean dis ings. Let us once again regard S as the category sentence, without crimination of mood. But let us pay special attention to those sentential meanings that are represented by base structures of roughly the following form. Such meanings can be represented by performative sentences these. This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions such as GENERAL SEMANTICS 57 I command you to be late. I ask you whether you are late. but, as will 1962, for the standard account of performatives; (See Austin, be seen, I reject part of this account.) Such meanings might also be repre elaborate transformational derivation, sented, after a more by non declaratives. Be late! Are you I propose of late? that these non-declaratives the corresponding to be treated as paraphrases the same base structure, having ought performatives, intension, and truth-value at an index or on an occasion. And of these that there is no difference in kind between the meanings and and of the non-declaratives the performatives ordinary meanings meaning, I propose sentences declarative considered previously. we would sentences as classify the performative If not, then we can divide sentential meanings into declara sentential meanings and non-declarative the sentential meanings, It is not clear whether declarative. tive latter being both by performatives and by imperatives, represented as etc. But if, as I would prefer, we classify performatives then the distinction between declarative and non-declarative declarative, sentences becomes a purely syntactic, surface distinction. The only dis questions, tinction is the distinction between those sentential among meanings can sentences that be and those declarative meanings only represented by can that be represented either by suitable declarative sentences (performa thereof. Let us call the latter tives) or by non-declarative paraphrases I need not delineate the class of per sentential meanings. performative formative sentential meanings precisely, since I am claiming that they do not need to be singled out for special semantic treatment. The method of paraphrased performatives those non-declaratives that resisted treatment radicals. Not spond can easily be extended to of sentence by the method only yes-no questions but other questions to performative sentences. The sentences below I ask who Sylvia as well is. Who is Sylvia? This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions corre DAVID 58 for have instance, might structure something LEWIS a common meaning represented is Sylvia by a base like this. the sentences And I cheer Porky. Hurrah for Porky! might have this base structure. duced transformationally.) (Thus the word 'Hurrah' would be intro s S/N N (S/N)/NNI I I cheer We may structures We to also as meanings represented by these base performative. truth-values. common sentential at the outset noted lack the classify Porky are commonly supposed sentence radicals this respects that non-declaratives The method of to sentence fundamentally are under no compulsion to a as sentence sentence of the its truth-value non-declarative regard sharing radical, and we have chosen not to. The method of paraphrased perform atives, on the other hand, does call for the assignment of truth-values to truth-values opinion by assigning rather than to whole sentences. We radicals is not that of the assigned to sentence the radical), however, but (corresponding I of If that the paraphrased say to you 'Be late!' performative. non-declarative embedded rather sentences. The truth-value sentence and you are not late, the embedded sentence is false, but the paraphrased This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions GENERAL SEMANTICS 59 is true because I do command that you be late. I see no performative have the truth-values of the perform problem in letting non-declaratives atives they paraphrase; after all, we need not ever mention their truth values if we would rather not. So far, I have assumed that performatives themselves do have truth but that also been has denied. values, (Austin, 1962, Lecture I.) I would wish to say that T bet you sixpence it will rain tomorrow' is true on an of utterance iff the utterer does then bet his audience sixpence rain on the following day; and, if the occasion is normal in is true. certain respects, the utterer does so bet; therefore his utterance nor Austin says it is obviously neither true false, apparently because to utter the sentence (in normal circumstances) is to bet. Granted; but why occasion that it will is that a reason to deny that the utterance is true? To utter T am speaking' is to speak, but it is also to speak the truth. This much can be said in Austin's defense: the truth-values that is inten (and truth conditions, are easily ignored just and their paraphrases sions) of performatives to be anything but true on an because it is hard for a performative Hard but possible: you can be play-acting, or an and say T command officer elocution, practicing impersonating that you be late' falsely, that is, say it without your thereby commanding in which audience to be late. I claim that those are the very circumstances of occasion its utterance. is it, like the performative, falsely say 'Be late!'; otherwise no when it is It if uttered because and uttered. is wonder the truth truly of the sentences embedded conditions in performatives and their non you could tend to eclipse the truth conditions of the per paraphrases and non-declaratives themselves. sentences of This eclipsing is most visible in the case of performative or T declare that-'. the form T state that-' If someone says T declarative formatives is flat' (sincerely, not play-acting, etc.) I claim that so he has spoken truly: he does indeed declare. I claim this not only for sense. Yet one might the sake of my theory but as a point of common be tempted to say that he has spoken falsely, because the sentence em - the content of his bedded in his performative the belief he declaration, avows - is false. Hence I do not propose to take ordinary declaratives as declare that the Earth in Ross, that paraphrased performatives (as proposed 1968) because would get their truth conditions wrong. If there are strong syntactic reasons for adopting Ross's proposal, I would regard it as semantically This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions DAVID 60 a version structures of the method that LEWIS radicals, even if it employs base like the base structures employed in the of sentence look exactly of paraphrased performatives. I provide only one meaning for the sentence T command you to be late'. Someone might well object that this sentence ought to come out because it can be used in two ways. It can be used to com ambiguous, method as 'Be late!', and it is true when it can be paraphrased because it is uttered. It can be used circumstances just to describe what I am doing; thus used, it cannot be paraphrased thus used, mand; uttered in normal instead as an imperative, and it is likely to be false when uttered because it is am I that difficult to issue a command and simultaneously say doing so. I be but the commanding by signing my possible: might doing (Difficult name on a letter while describing what I am doing by talking.) I agree that there are two alternative uses of this and other performative use and the non-performative sentences : the genuinely performative self use. occur can I non-declarative also that the agree paraphrase descriptive use. It still does not follow in the performative the case of these two sentences. meanings. Compare only I am talking In hexameter The latter can be used that there are two in trochaic hexameter. trochaic am I talking. to talk in trochaic hexameter and is true on any former cannot be so of its correctly accented utterance. The occasion used and is false on any occasion of its correctly accented utterance. Yet a sentence can be the two sentences are obviously paraphrases. Whether The is not a matter of its meaning. used to talk in trochaic hexameter using a sentence to talk in trochaic hexameter or not so using it is one sort of distinction; between using a the distinction it sentence and is self-descriptively using performatively performative A is instructive. distinction sort. Still I think the another parallel quite distinction between in uses need not involve a distinction in meanings of the sentences used. in conversational in surface form; or distinction or some other sort. of distinction and intentions, expectations; setting, in meanings I see no decisive reason to insist that there is any distinction It can involve distinction associated with the difference uses of performative sentences, between performative if the contrary and assumption self-descriptive is theoretically convenient. This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions GENERAL 61 SEMANTICS of sentence radicals and the We may ask to what extent the method are compatible. In particular: given of paraphrased performatives can can mood and into be sentence that sentence-radical, any analyzed intension from the meaning we recover the mood and the sentence-radical method of paraphrased performatives? according to the method of sentence can do this, but not quite. On the method and the between difference the self-descriptive uses radicals, performative sentences must be treated as a difference of meanings. of performative of the sentence We almost we will get two pairs of a sentence meaning, So given a performative to the two uses. intension corresponding mood and a sentence-radical a are we sentential meaning represented by performative given Suppose a base structure like this, for instance. command you (S/N)/(C/C) be I S/N N C/C you I late the self-descriptive use, we do just what we would do for a non sentence take the mood to be declarative and the meaning: performative In intension to be the intension of the entire meaning. sentence-radical to sentence the radical would be the intension this case, it corresponding 'that I command you to be late'. For the performative use, we take the For mood to be determined the sentence-radical at node <1, 1>, and at node <1, 3>. In this of 'command', which determines by the (S/N)/NS-intension intension to be the S-intension case, these are respectively the intension sen of the embedded is imperative, and the S-intension that the mood to the sentence radical 'that you are late'. tence meaning, corresponding of apart from fineness of individuation, advantage, as rather than markers semantically interpreted phrase taking meanings of constituents from as single intensions :we can recover the meanings Note here a second the meanings of their compounds. This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions DAVID 62 indices appendix: LEWIS expanded Indices are supposed to be packages of everything but meaning into determining extensions. Do we have everything? Let me on several expansions of the indices that might prove useful. that goes speculate the sentence 'This is older than this9. I might say it a at I at a 1962 when the first 'this' and 1963 say Volkswagen pointing on I sentence the true when second 'this'. The should be say Volkswagen consider First, such an occasion; but how can it be? Using the intension of 'this', with its sensitivity to the indicated-objects coordinate, we obtain the intension sentence; then we take the value ofthat intension at an index and contextual coordinates determined by features of the over of utterance. indices alike except at the (We generalize of the whole with world occasion assignment assignment but we can consider any one of these, since the to the sentence in question.) This that the indicated object changes part-way coordinate; coordinate is irrelevant ignores the fact the occasion of utterance. So the sentence through on should any occasion when the indicated object procedure comes out false, as it stays the same. a solution would be to semantics, On a more extensional approach easy. We could take the two extensions of 'this' on the two occasions of its utterance and use these, rather than the fixed intension of 'this', to determine the truth-value of the sentence. The intension and the occasion of utterance of the sentence as a whole would drop out. But since the are not in general determined by the extensions extensions of compounds of their constituents, this extensional solution would preclude a uniform treatment of semantic projection rules. An acceptable solution has been suggested to me by David Kaplan, as follows. Let the indicated-objects be not just one set of coordinate objects capable of being pointed at but an infinite sequence of such sets. the indicated-objects coordinate determined by a given occasion of of a sentence have as its nth term the set of things pointed to at the nth utterance of 'this' during the utterance of the sentence so long Let utterance as n does empty not exceed set when the number n does exceed of such utterances, and let it be the that number. Let there be an infinite 'this/, 'this2',... with intensions such that 'thisn' depends for its extension at an index on the nth term of the assignment coordinate. So that the lexicon will remain finite, let all but 'this/ be sequence of constituents This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions GENERAL SEMANTICS 63 to 'this/. compounds generated by iterated application of a suitable N/N Let all members of the sequence appear as 'this' in surface structure. Use transformational filtering to dispose of all base structures except those an so arranged that if the initial segment of the 'this'-sequence employing were carried to the surface, they would appear in numerical subscripts order without repetition. than this' will be is older Thus than the only base solution must for 'This is older this2 which will be true on occasions The structure be modified of the sort in question. to allow for the fact that I omit details. the only demonstrative; are for other similar solutions possible, Similar 'this' is not difficulties contextual arise, and coordinates: time, audience, and perhaps speaker. Second, consider the sentence 'The door place, is open'. This does not mean that the one and only door that now exists is open; nor does it mean that the one and only door near the place of utterance, or pointed at, or mentioned in previous discourse, is open. Rather it means that the one and only door among the objects that are somehow prominent on the occasion is open. An object may be prominent because it is nearby, or pointed at, or mentioned ; but none of these is a necessary condition of contextual prominence. So perhaps we need &prominent-objects coordi a new coordinate contextual nate, independent of the others. It will be on a given occasion of utterance of a sentence, by mental determined, factors to bring such as the speaker's expectations to the attention of his audience. regarding the things he is likely 1968; Donnellan, Third, consider the suggestion (Kaplan, 1970) that the extension of a personal name on a given occasion depends partly on the causal chain leading from the bestowal of that name on some person to the later use of that name by a speaker on the occasion in question. We might wish to accept this theory, and yet wish to deny that the intension or meaning of the name depends, on the occasion This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions in question, DAVID 64 upon the causal history to give up the common LEWIS of the speaker's use of it; for we might not wish that the meaning of an expression presumption on mental factors within him. We might solve only for a speaker depends in Lewis, 1968b) by including a causal-history this dilemma (as proposed coordinate in our indices and letting the intensions of-acquisition-of-names their extensions only relative to that of names for a speaker determine coordinate. Fourth, we have so far been ignoring the vagueness of natural language. Perhaps we are right to ignore it, or rather to deport it from semantics to the theory of language-use. We could say (as I did in Lewis, 1969, V) that languages themselves of a population, linguistic conventions a fuzzy region a not but select point Chapter are free of vagueness but that the or the linguistic habits of a person, in the space of precise languages. it might prove better to treat vagueness within However, we could do so as follows. (A related treatment, developed is to be found in Goguen, 1969.) and semantics, independently, that the only vagueness of 'cool' and is the vagueness are 'warm' ; and suppose for simplicity that these extensional adjectives. Let the indices contain a delineation coordinate: a positive real number, temperature between cool and warm things. regarded as the boundary Pretend first at an index i the extension of 'cool' is the set of things at the world of i having temperatures and time coordinates less (in degrees Kelvin) or coordinate of i; the extension of 'warm' than equal to the delineation is the set of such things having temperatures greater than the delineation coordinate. A vague sentence such as 'This is cool' is true, on a given at some but not all delineations; that is, at some but not all occasion, Thus indices that are alike except in delineation and have the world and contex determined by the occasion of utterance. But sentences tual coordinates are not necessarily vague: 'This is cool or warm, with vague constituents but not both' on an occasion is true at all delineations, even if the indicated object is a unique indicated object, The delineation coordinate on which there is lukewarm. is non-contextual. It resembles the assign in that we will ordinarily generalize over it rather than coordinate, hold it fixed. We may say that a sentence is true over a set s of delineations at an index /, iff, for any index V that is like / except perhaps at the ment the sentence is true at V if and only if the deline coordinate, ation coordinate of V belongs to s. Given a normalized measure function delineation This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions GENERAL SEMANTICS 65 we can say that a sentence is true to degree d at i iff it over delineations, is true at i over a set of delineations of measure d. Note that the degree of truth of a truth-functional of sentences not a function is compound of the degrees of truth of its constituent : sentences 'x is cool' and 'x is warm' may both be true to degree .5 at an index /, but 'x is cool or x is cool' is true at / to degree .5 whereas 'x is cool or x is warm' is true at / to degree 1. semantics makes for simple specifications Treating vagueness within of the intensions of such expressions as 'in some sense', 'paradigmatic', than'. The idiom '_ish', and instance, is an S/S related to the delineation 'possibly' is related to the world operator 'in some '_er contemporary is that function sense' coordinate coordinate. 'in some sense', for just as the modal The intension of <?>such that if (^ is any S-intension, (?>2 is (H$i), and / is any index, then = ?2(0 truth if, for some index V that is like i except perhaps at the delineation is truth coordinate, 0i(O otherwise. falsity The comparative '_er such that, for instance, than' is a ((C/C)/N)/(C/C) having an intension than y9 is true at an index i iff the set 'x is cooler 'y is cool' is true at i is a proper subset of the over which 'x is cool' is true at i. It follows that the than Sirius unless in some sense the sun is cool; but over which of delineations set of delineations sun is not cooler seems correct, although I do not know whether to deny than Sirius or to agree that in some sense the sun was suggested to me by David (This analysis of comparatives that conclusion that the sun is cooler is cool. Kaplan.) More generally, be a sequence of expressions will depend for the extensions of (or, if they are not extensional, on terms different of the delineation. More compounds) boundary-specifying for their extensions their extensional the delineation numbers. than one term of the delineation expression. For instance, coordinate Different must vague might be involved for a single of 'green' might involve one term boundary and another regarded as coordinate the intension the blue-green regarded as delineating the boundary. The former but not the latter delineating green-yellow would be one of the two terms involved in the intension of 'blue' ; and so on around the circle of hues. This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 66 DAVID LEWIS BIBLIOGRAPHY 1 (1935) 'Die syntaktische Studia Konnexit?t', Ajdukiewicz, Philosophica as 'Syntactic in S. McCall, Polish translated Connexion' 1-27; 1967, Logic, Oxford as 'On Syntactical Part I translated Review pp. 207-231. Coherence', of Metaphysics Kazimierz 20 (1966) 635-647. to Do How J. L. Austin, 1962. Mass., Yehoshua Bar-Hillel, with Words, Things and Language Harvard Information, Press, University Cambridge, Mass., Reading, Addison-Wesley, 1964. Paul 'What Numbers Benacerraf, Rudolf Carnap, Could Not and Necessity, Meaning 74 (1965) Review Be', Philosophical of Chicago Press, University Chicago, 47-73. Illinois, 1947. Rudolf Carnap, Rudolf Carnap, to Symbolic Introduction and 'Replies Systematic La Salle, Open Court, Aspects of the Theory Rudolf Carnap, Noam Chomsky, New York, Logic, Dover, in P. Schilpp, Expositions', 1963. Illinois, M.I.T. of Syntax, 1958. The Philosophy Press, Cambridge, Princeton University of Mass., 1965. Alonzo The Church, Princeton, N.J., Donald Davidson, of Lambda Conversion, Press, 17 (1967) 304-323. and Meaning', Synthese the Looking-Glass, London 1871. Through and Identifying 'Proper Names Descriptions', Synthese Sinn und Bedeutung', '?ber f?r Philosophie Zeitschrift 'Truth L. Dodgson, Charles Keith Calculi 1941. Donnellan, Gottlob Frege, Kritik phische and M. Geach 100 (1892) 25-50; Translations as translated 'On Sense 21 (1970). und philoso and Reference' in P. T. of Gottlob Frege, Writings 1960. Oxford, 19 (1969) 325-373. of Inexact Concepts', 'The Logic Synthese Foundations David (doctoral dissertation), University of Intensional Logic Kaplan, Ann Arbor, Michigan, 1964. Microfilms, Black, the Philosophical from Blackwell, J. A. Goguen, David 'Quantifying Kaplan, and Paul Postal, Katz Jerrold Press, Edward Cambridge, In', Synthese An Integrated 1964. Mass., 19 (1968) 178-214. Theory of Linguistic M.I.T. Descriptions, A Logical Base for English 1969. (doctoral dissertation, Keenan, duplicated), on Modal Acta Philosophica 'Semantical Considerations Fennica Saul Kripke, Logic', 16 (1963) 83-94. Lakoff, George in Philosophy, Leon Clarence 'On Generative Linguistics, Jakobovits), I. Lewis, in Semantics: Semantics' An Cambridge University 'The Modes of Meaning', Press, (ed. by Danny 1970. Cambridge, Philosophy Reader Interdisciplinary and Psychology Anthropology and Steinberg andPhenomenological Research Journal of Philosophy 4 (1944) 236-249. David Lewis, 'Counterpart 65(1968)113-126. David Lewis, 'Languages of Science. Philosophy David Lewis, Convention: 1969. Mass., John Lyons, 'Towards Theory and Quantified Modal Logic', (1968a). and Language', (1968b). A Philosophical a "Notional" to appear Study, Theory Harvard of in the Minnesota University the "Parts of Studies Press, Speech"', Linguistics 2 (1966) 209-236. This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions in the Cambridge, Journal of GENERAL Benson Mates, III Science on Possible 'Leibniz (ed. by B. 1968. SEMANTICS Worlds' van Rootselaar and 67 in Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of J. F. Staal), North-Holland Publ. Co., Amsterdam, the Base Component James McCawley, of a Transformational 'Concerning 4 (1968) 243-269. Foundations of Language James McCawley, to a 'Semantic paper Representation', presented Studies and Artificial Intelligence Cognitive Research, University for Continuing Center Richard Montague, March Education, 'Logical on symposium of Chicago 1969. Physical Necessity, Grammar', Necessity, Ethics, and Quantifiers', Inquiry 3 (1960) 259-269. - La in Contemporary con 'Pragmatics' Philosophy philosophie R. La Nuova Italia Florence 1968. Klibansky), temporaine (ed. by Editrice, and Some 'Intensional of Its Connections with Ordinary Richard Montague, Logic to the Southern talk delivered California April 1969, Language', Logic Colloquium, Richard and Montague, to the Association Richard Richard Montague, Richard Montague, at Cleveland, I' in Linguaggi of Symbolic Logic meeting as a Formal Language 'English Montague, t?cnica, Edizioni 1969. Ohio, May nella societ? e nella 1970. di Communit?, Milan, 'Universal Grammar', (1970a). Theoria 36 (1970). (1970b). 22 (1971). and Intensional Logic', Synthese 'Pragmatics A Semantics Terence 1968. Parsons, for English (duplicated), On the Generative Power Peters and R. W. Ritchie, P. Stanley of Transformational in Computer Technical of Washington, Science, Grammars, Report University 1969. Seattle, Wash., to appear in Readings in Transformational Sentences', and P. Rosenbaum), Mass. Blaisdell, Boston, (1968). on Modal in Philosophical in Logic: Problems Recent Logic' R. Ross, 'On Declarative Grammar (ed. by R. Jacobs John Dana 'Advice Scotts (ed. by Karel 143-173. Developments 1970, pp. Erik Stenius, D. Lambert), Reidel Company, Publishing Dordrecht, 'Mood and Language-Game', 17 (1967) 254-274. Synthese Mind 'On Referring', 59 (1950) 320-344. 'Der Wahrheitsbegriff in den formalisierten Studia Sprachen', as 'The Concept translated of Truth in Formalized phica 1 (1936) 261-405; 1956. Oxford Semantics, Metamathematics, Logic, ges' in Tarski, and Reference', Richmond Thomason and Robert Nous Stalnaker, 'Modality 359-372. P. F. Strawson, Alfred Tarski, Bruce Vermazen, Linguistic 350-365. review Descriptions, JohnWallace, of Jerrold and Katz Katz, and Paul Philosophy Postal, An of Language, Integrated Synthese Philoso Langua 2 (1968) of Theory 17 (1967) 'Sortal Predicates and Quantification', Journal of Philosophy 62 (1965) 8-13. NOTE This paper is derived from a talk given at the Third La Jolla Conference on Linguistic Theory, March 1969.1 Kaplan, George Lakoff, and suggestions. criticisms am much indebted to Charles Richard Montague, and Frank Heny, David Chastain, Partee for many Barbara valuable This content downloaded from 171.66.240.83 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 13:21:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions