* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Andrew Baker - Georgetown Commons
Internalism and externalism wikipedia , lookup
Virtue ethics wikipedia , lookup
Business ethics wikipedia , lookup
Kantian ethics wikipedia , lookup
Divine command theory wikipedia , lookup
Paleoconservatism wikipedia , lookup
Bernard Williams wikipedia , lookup
Ethics of eating meat wikipedia , lookup
The Moral Landscape wikipedia , lookup
Individualism wikipedia , lookup
Ethics in religion wikipedia , lookup
Alasdair MacIntyre wikipedia , lookup
Consequentialism wikipedia , lookup
Lawrence Kohlberg wikipedia , lookup
Ethics of artificial intelligence wikipedia , lookup
Moral disengagement wikipedia , lookup
Morality and religion wikipedia , lookup
Critique of Practical Reason wikipedia , lookup
Lawrence Kohlberg's stages of moral development wikipedia , lookup
Morality throughout the Life Span wikipedia , lookup
Moral development wikipedia , lookup
Thomas Hill Green wikipedia , lookup
Moral responsibility wikipedia , lookup
Ethical intuitionism wikipedia , lookup
Andrew Baker Essay Assignment #1 10/21/07 A Critique of Ethical Relativism Both Louis Pojman and Alison Hornsetin hold the belief that ethical relativism is an unacceptable method for analyzing moral differences in the modern world. Due to their loathing of ethnocentrism, people have become overly hesitant to objectively criticize the morality of other cultures. Ethical relativists however assert that “the very validity of the principles is a product of culture” and thus all cultures contain their own varied and inherently justifiable moral codes (Pojman, 1994, p.239). In this essay, I will argue that we should reject ethical relativism as a moral theory because it leads to no intercultural analysis or judgment. To begin any formal critique it is necessary to define the terms upon which the theory is based. Pojman defines cultural relativism as the fact that “moral rules differ from society to society, so that there are no moral principles accepted by all societies” (Pojman, 1994, p.240). Pojman asserts that this anthropological thesis is fairly self evident. There are few, if any, universal moral codes that apply within all cultures. Conventional ethical relativism uses cultural relativism as its base, and further states that “all valid moral principles are justified by virtue of their cultural acceptance” (Pojman, 1994, p.244). This differs with subjective ethical relativism, commonly termed subjectivism, which takes morality as dependent upon the individual him or herself. In his essay, Pojman argues that ethical relativists “cannot rationally criticize anyone who espouses what they might regard as a heinous principle… or anyone outside their own culture. Adolf Hitler’s genocidal actions, so long as they are culturally accepted, are as morally legitimate as Mother Teresa’s works of mercy” (Pojman, 1994, p. 245). Ethical relativists can in no way criticize actions committed by individuals outside of their cultural group. One cannot oppose actions of murder, oppression, rape, etc. as morally reprehensible if they lay within the confines of a given culture’s moral code. One can justify any action by relating it to the accepted judgment of the members of its society. In her essay “The Question that We Should Be Asking”, Alison Hornstein also argues against the tenets of ethical relativism. Placing her critique within the context of the terrorist attacks on 9/11, she notes how her peers were hesitant to place blame on the perpetrators. They were more than willing to acknowledge the underlying cultural circumstances that may have precipitated the event, yet would not agree that a moral wrong had occurred. She attributed this to her generation’s reluctance to impose their standards on other cultures. She says that “being taught to think within a framework of moral and cultural relativity without learning its boundaries has seemingly created a deficiency in [their] ability to make moral judgments” (Hornstein, 2001, p.1). She feels as though some actions, such as rape and terrorism, should be morally reprehensible among all cultures and fair game to moral speculation. Ethical relativism is enticing as a moral theory for a variety of reasons. History has shown that a tendency towards ethnocentrism can lead to disastrous consequences. One must merely look at the case of the Nazi’s, who viewed themselves as the master race, to see the slippery slope which it can ensue. Our society has chosen to endorse the virtues of tolerance and diversity in relations to other cultures. Although different cultural traditions may seem odd, awkward, or even disgusting to us, it does not give us the right to belittle them. One of the reasons that western culture today views tolerance as a virtue is through the condemnation of actions focused on the reverse. It is all too evident that as cultures attempt to impose their will upon others, disastrous consequences follow. This was visible in the Spanish reconquista, where the monarch’s attempt to impose Christianity upon the population led to the emigration of countless Muslims and Jews. This ethnic flight, along with the murder of thousands through the Inquisition, must be seen as a moral catastrophe. Even today, societies attempt to influence and modify others based on their predilections. The United States felt that it was their duty to impose a democratic regime upon an Iraqi people who had been living under authoritarian leaders and monarchs for centuries. The result has been disastrous; hundreds of thousand have died and the country is in political and economic shambles. The concept that there are universal moral codes or tendencies seems to be preposterous. The spectrum of acceptability varies incredibly within cultures; who is to say which are truly moral? Indeed, even within one culture the moral rules appear to change over time. In the past, slavery was seen as an acceptable American institution, yet today it is morally abhorrent. If one group of people themselves cannot codify a timeneutral moral code, how can they believe that their present judgments are correct? The logical conclusion is that morality derives from cultural determinants, and moral judgments can only be made within the confines of a particular culture. Pojman and Hornstein would both argue that the moral price one pays for advocating strict ethical relativism outweighs the gains from increased tolerance. I agree with their assumption that to be a consistent ethical relativist requires that you refrain from judgment of others’ practices, no matter how repugnant. To adhere to its principles means that you forgo your right to morally judge another society in any way. No outsiders may protest human rights violations, ethnic cleansings, or genocide. Instead we would live in a world partitioned by cultures able to act on their own interpretation of morality no matter how detestable. Ethical relativism is based on the concept that people are divided clearly into separate societies, each having its own moral code. Yet in reality, classifications prove much more complicated. Must a society be a nation, or can it constitute a region, or even a city? Overlapping societies may contain contradictory moral policies, in which case the individual is stuck in an ethical quandary. Pojman states that due to these clarification issues, conventional relativism will “reduce to subjectivism” as the guideline of what constitutes a group becomes increasingly more muddled. Pojman argues that subjectivism as a concept cannot coexist with any valid interpretation of morality (Pojman, 1994, p. 247). One of the precepts of ethical relativism is that a belief that one’s own moral judgments are closer to the truth leads towards ethnocentrism. Ethnocentrism is defined as “the uncritical belief in the inherent superiority of one’s own culture” (Pojman, 1994, p.238). However, merely objecting to ethical relativism does not inevitably include uncritical thinking. One can believe in the values and edicts of one’s own culture, while still engaging in a critical discussion. Indeed, it is my opinion that a belief in a certain moral code is essential to a critical assessment of morality. If one has no partiality towards its own moral code, then why do they differ so greatly? I believe that there are indeed universal moral codes. The mere acknowledgment of differing cultural values does not exonerate a person who commits rape, murder, or pillage. As Hornstein ascertains, “there comes a point where the refusal to take a stand on what is wrong results in its victory” (Hornstein, 2001, p. 1). The international community has backed this claim through the adoption of the United Nations Charter: the Universal Declaration of Human Rights. With this declaration, it was agreed by the members of the United Nations General Assembly that all human beings deserve the right to a “dignified and secure existence.” In it lies the prohibition of torture and slavery, the right of political asylum, citizenship in some country, and the right to the “freedom of thought, conscience, and religion” (United Nations, 1948, p.268-269). Even though the people of the world live in varying societal situations, they all deserve a minimum level of existence. This, in and of itself is a universal moral code. Although the concepts of tolerance and diversity are noble in personal relations, they need not be incorporated into the realm of ethics and morality. Merely stating that cultural relativism exists does not make ethical relativism a necessity. Although many values may be left to cultural preference, there are certain moral codes which must be applied universally. Due to this belief, I reject ethical relativism as a moral theory and instead advocate increased discourse on the subject of moral superiority. The questions that remain lie in the clarification of these universal principles. Certainly there will be disagreements among cultures, but it is only through passionate discussion that moral progress can be made. Bibliography Hornstein, A. (2001, December 17). The Question that We Should Be Asking. Newsweek, 14. Pojman, L. (1994). Who’s to Judge? In Vice & Virtue in Everyday Life (p. 237250). Orlando, FL: Harcourt College Publishers. United Nations. (1948). The United Nations Charter: The Universal Declaration of Human Rights. In Vice & Virtue in Everyday Life (p.268- 275). Orlando, FL: Harcourt College Publishers.