* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download the modern evolutionary theory
Adaptive evolution in the human genome wikipedia , lookup
Transitional fossil wikipedia , lookup
Artificial gene synthesis wikipedia , lookup
Quantitative trait locus wikipedia , lookup
Dual inheritance theory wikipedia , lookup
Polymorphism (biology) wikipedia , lookup
Group selection wikipedia , lookup
Population genetics wikipedia , lookup
THE MODERN EVOLUTIONARY THEORY ERNST MAYR Museum of Comparative Zoology, 26 Oxford Street, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA 02138 Capstone Address, Presented at the 75th Annual Meeting of The American Society of Mammalogists, Burlington, VT, June 1995 Of all of Darwin's evolutionary theories, the one that encountered the greatest resistance, and was therefore the last one to be accepted, was the theory of natural selection. It was only about 1940 that it was adopted by the majority of biologists. In order to understand why it encountered this resistance, it is necessary to survey the history of evolutionary biology. When Darwin, in 1859, proposed his theory of natural selection, it was opposed at once not by just one but actually by four different counterproposals. One, of course, was Creationism, the other three were purely scientific theories, without any invocation of supernatural factors. These three theories were transmutationism, the claim that evolutionary novelties originate by major mutations and by the saltational origin of new kinds of organisms, and two transformational theories, which explained evolution in terms of the gradual change of a preexisting entity. These transformational theories took their cue from ontogeny, and believed that just as the fertilized egg is gradually transformed into an adult individual, so an evolutionary lineage is gradually transformed. There are two very different conceptions of the nature of this transformation, that is, how the transformation is caused. One of them, orthogenesis, is the theory that in the world of life there is some built-in tendency or drive toward progression, improvement, and finally, perhaps, even perfection. The other, Lamarckism, is based on the belief in a direct influence of the environment on the genetic material and an inheritance of acquired characters. From 1859 to about 1940, these three opposing theories were Journal of Mamma!ogy. 77(1):1-7, 1996 actually far more popular than natural selection. In the years from 1930 to 1936, several leading scholars stated with conviction that each of these opposing theories had so much support that there was no hope for a consensus in the near future. Actually, this was achieved with incredible rapidity in the 15 years or so, beginning in 1937. However, before natural selection could be victorious, the three mentioned countertheories first had to be refuted. I shall say nothing about Creationism, because with its reliance on supernatural forces, it is outside the realm of scientific investigation. But how were the other three counter-theories refuted? Let me begin with saltationist transmutationism. This was the theory of evolution that was supported by all essentialists. They simply couldn't see how one could get from one type to another type without a saltation. This theory was popular from Darwin's time on. It was supported by T. H. Huxley, also by some leading German biologists, and it had support from the early Mendelians, because Bateson, de Vries, and Johannsen were saltationists. And as late as 1940 and 1950 it had suppofiers among paleontologists, and in Goldschmidt and the botanist Willis. This theory was refuted when evolutionists pointed out that organisms are not types but populations, and that no population as a whole could ever be converted into a new type by a single step. Furthermore, since an organism is controlled by an elaborate and harmonious genotype, it is quite inconceivable to expect that a new viable harmonious genotype could be produced by a single step. Goldschmidt 2 JOURNAL OF MAMMALOGY frankly admitted that ordinarily such saltations would only produce "monsters," but he expressed his faith that once in a while there would be a "hopeful monster" that would indeed be adapted for some new ecological niche. However, it was shown by the naturalists that the large quantity of unsuccessful mutations that was postulated by the saltationists could not be found. More importantly, the naturalists showed through the study of geographic speciation that the origin of new species was a gradual process, as had been postulated by Darwin, and that there was no need to invoke saltations. The post-Mendelian generation of geneticists also showed that the frequency of viable large mutations was very low, and that most mutations were very small and not in any way able to produce the kind of transmutationist novelties. Both B. Rensch and G. G. Simpson showed that morphologists could explain macroevolution without difficulty in terms of selection and very small mutations. And that was the end of transmutationism. The second of the opposing explanatory schemes was orthogenesis. Among orthogenetic theories were nomogenesis of the Russian E. S. Berg, aristogenesis of H. R Osborn, and the omega principle of Teilhard de Chardin. Its supporters believed that there was a built-in tendency in evolutionary lineages toward ever greater complexity and perfection. However, neither could the geneticists find any genetic mechanism that could make such a tendency toward perfection possible, nor did the analysis of the paleontologists support the claim of a steady trend toward perfection. Indeed, one encountered reversals and rather drastic shifts to new directions in most well-analyzed evolutionary lineages. So-called excess structures such as the antlers of the Irish elk and the tusks of the Babirussa were claimed by the orthogenesists to be obviously deleterious developments that could be explained only by the existence of a non-stoppable trend. However, it was shown by the Darwinians that Vol. 77. No.1 the antlers of the Irish elk, supported by sexual selection, were by no means excessive, and furthermore could also be explained in part by allometry, that is, the correlated growth of a structure with an increase in body size. Orthogenesis, of course, was in a way a byproduct of the prevailing deterministic thinking of this period and became unpopular when the shortcomings of determinism were revealed. In the last analysis, the whole orthogenesis concept was a misguided analogy with ontogeny. The proponents of orthogenesis thought that just as in ontogeny eventually the adult characters arise inevitably, so evolution also was in a way programmed and would ultimately lead to certain end results that had been programmed in their genotype from the beginning. The Darwinians countered this argument by pointing out that evolution was not the gradual transformation of a type but was a populational phenomenon. This Darwinian concept of evolution was completely opposed to the conceptual framework of the orthogenesists. The frequency of extinction and the equally high frequency of ultimately deleterious evolutionary pathways demonstrate the improbability of such orthogenetic programs particularly well. Of course, the genetic analysis after 1910 found no evidence whatsoever for the existence of any orthogenetic programs. Finally, there was the school believing in a direct effect of the environment and in an inheritance of acquired characters. They believed that the genetic material was plastic and their genetic theory was referred to as the theory of soft inheritance. This theory was rather thoroughly refuted by Weismann as early as 1883, but continued to have support. This support was particularly strong in the early years of this century owing to the saltationist claims of the Mendelians and their opposition to natural selection. Anyone believing in gradual evolution, as did most of the naturalists, was almost forced to accept Lamarckism although, like Darwin, at the same time also accepting natural February 1996 MAYR-CAPSTONE ADDRESS selection. The main contribution made by the inheritance of acquired characters, according to this school, was to supply abundant variation to serve as material for natural selection. Darwin himself, of course, believed in an inheritance of acquired characters, and many of the later Lamarckians also believed in natural selection and actually considered themselves to be good Darwinians. A major target of the opposition was Darwin's claim that all evolutionary change, and particularly adaptation, is controlled by natural selection. If we assume that a structure or behavior or any attribute of an organism is adapted, it follows that it must have been incorporated into the genotype owing to natural selection. The opposition of the anti-Darwinians was not so much based on concrete evidence as on an intuitive aversion to the so-called "mechanistic" Darwinian interpretation and to the large role of chance in the Darwinian explanation. Even though Weismann in 1883 had denied categorically any existence of an inheritance of acquired characters, naturalists, and in fact, almost all evolutionary biologists still more or less believed in it for another 50 years. Some of them devoted many years to experimentation to prove it. All experiments, however, turned out to be negative. Furthermore, the detailed genetic analysis, beginning in 1910 in Morgan's laboratory, found no evidence for it whatsoever. The most decisive refutation, however, was eventually supplied by molecular biology when it showed that information could be transferred from nucleic acids to proteins, but no information could be transferred from the proteins of the body to the nucleic acids of the germplasm. This is called the central dogma of molecular biology. During the first quarter of the 20th century the support for the three non-Darwinian evolutionary theories, saltationism, orthogenesis, and Lamarckian inheritance was far greater than the support for natural selection. Indeed, natural selection was not 3 widely adopted until these three competing theories had been thoroughly refuted. The credit for the decisive refutation of the three non-Darwinian explanations of evolution is shared by genetics, systematics, and paleontology. The defeat of the nonDarwinian theories during the synthesis was so complete that since about 1950 no creditable author has come out to support any of them. At the present time, there are no longer any serious followers of saltationism, orthogenesis, or an inheritance of acquired characters. THE EVOLUTIONARY SYNTHESIS Much of the refutation of the non-Darwinian theories took place already prior to 1935, and yet, there still didn't seem to be any signs of a consensus among the evolutionary biologists. One could recognize two major camps of Darwinians at that time, and in fact, even today these two camps can still be distinguished. The one camp is that of the laboratory geneticists who study evolution with the help of experimentation and mathematical models. The other camp consists of the naturalists whose interpretation of evolution is based on the study of populations in the field. In 1935 there was still a rather strong saltationist bias in the thinking of the geneticists, a remnant of the thinking of the early Mendelians, while owing to their strong emphasis on the gradualness of evolution there was still a tendency among the naturalists to believe in soft inheritance, that is, the capacity of the genome to be affected by the environment. The two camps were quite suddenly brought together to a consensus through the publication in 1937 of Dobzhansky's Genetics and the Origin of Species. Dobzhansky was the ideal person to initiate the reconciliation of the two camps because he himself actually belonged to both of them. By background he was a naturalist, and while still in Russia he was a taxonomist of a group of beetles, the Coccinellidae. In 1927, he came to the United States and 4 Vol. 77, No.1 JOURNAL OF MAMMALOGY worked for 10 years in the laboratory of T. H. Morgan, where he became thoroughly acquainted with the thinking of the geneticists. Perhaps I should describe the differences in the thinking of the two camps in a little more detail. The geneticists were strict reductionists. For them the gene was the target of selection, and they were only interested in, and able to investigate what happens in a given gene pool, that is, the origin and maintenance of adaptedness. Their concept of evolution was, so to speak, a vertical one, that is, relating to the changes that happen over time in a given gene pool. The naturalists-taxonomists differed by considering the individual as a whole as the target of selection. For them the population was the unit of evolution. Their chief interest was the origin of diversity. They developed the new biological species concept, they solved the riddle of speciation through the theory of geographic speciation, and they demonstrated a continuity between speciation and macroevolution. For them all evolution was populational, except for a few special phenomena such as polyploidy, and therefore all evolution by necessity was gradual. The naturalists were at that time still rather unaware of the drastic changes in the thinking of the geneticists between the time of Mendelism and the 1930s, and in particular with the shift in the genetic concept of mutation. Because the geneticists were always working with a single population, a single gene pool, they in turn were quite unaware of the variation of populations and of the problems connected with the origin of organic diversity. Dobzhansky in his Genetics and the Origin of Species (1937) presented the views of both camps. He showed that there was no conflict between their ideas. Furthermore, he showed that they very happily complemented each other, and that the gaps in the theories of the geneticists were filled by the theories of the naturalists and vice versa. Dobzhansky's thesis was soon taken up by the other so-called architects of the evolutionary synthesis, Julian Huxley, Ernst Mayr, and G. G. Simpson, in Germany by Rensch, and in botany by Stebbins. The long set of controversies, that had begun with the publication of Darwin's Origin of Species in 1859, was now terminated after 80 years and there was a remarkable consensus in the early symposia after 1937. It was obvious that a synthesis of concepts had taken place in evolutionary biology. But actually, as several recent historians have pointed out, the impact of this synthesis extended way beyond evolutionary biology. Indeed, the synthesis achieved a unification of all of biology. This was perhaps best expressed by Dobzhansky in his well known saying, "Nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of evolution." Eventually, the synthesis was joined even by the developmental biologists who had opposed Darwinism at least up to the 1960s. One might think that the almost explosive development of molecular biology after 1953 might have led to a drastic revision of the beliefs of the evolutionary synthesis, but this did not take place. As Maynard Smith had convincingly demonstrated, molecular biology was an almost continuous and gradual change from classical genetics. At the very beginning this was not so obvious because the first molecular biologists were actually biochemists and were, on the whole, rather hostile toward biology. But as the next generation of molecular biologists developed, most of them trained as biologists, this hostility disappeared, and now almost every molecular biologist includes evolutionary studies in his program, because by now everybody knows that biological macromolecules experience as much evolution as does any macroscopic organ system. ACHIEVEMENTS What the synthesis also achieved was a substantial clarification of all Darwinian concepts. February 1996 MAYR-CAPSTONE ADDRESS Let us begin with natural selection. His opponents at first referred to Darwin's theory as "evolution by accident." This is, of course, a total misconception. We now know that natural selection is a two-step process. The first step produces genetic variation and Darwin, from the beginning, postulated the availability of an enormous amount of variation in populations. Darwin did not know where it came from but he knew it was there. He even erroneously invoked soft inheritance to generate some of this variation. The geneticists always attributed variation to mutation and ultimately, of course, this is indeed the source of all genetic variation. But the genotypic difference between one generation and the next is mostly the product of genetic recombination. But whether due to mutation or to recombination, the variational difference between one generation and the next is entirely due to chance, except for some instances of socalled biased variation, which I do not have time to discuss. The second step is that of the real selection. Darwin's choice of the metaphor selection was not altogether a happy one. He was at once asked: who selects? Darwin said "nature." Well, said his opponents, this is the same agent we call God. Herbert Spencer saw the weakness in Darwin's terminology and suggested instead an emphasis on survival. But the formulation "survival of the fittest" was also attacked as being circular: who are the fittest?-those who survive. A good replacement description of natural selection is "non-random elimination." Selection, then, is the elimination of the less well adapted individuals, hence obviously a non-random elimination. Evolutionists had long distinguished a normalizing selection, which was exactly the elimination of all less well adapted individuals. The new metaphor simply says that all selection is normalizing selection, except that every generation may have its own norm, determined by the prevailing environment of the mo- 5 ment. There is no trace of circularity in this formulation. The wording "non-random elimination" also makes it clear that Darwin's natural selection is not a teleological process. It never has a definite goal; there is always a chance component in the selection of the lucky survivors. SPECIATION It is one of the great ironies in the history of biology that Darwin failed to settle the problem of speciation in the volume entitled On the Origin of Species. He had the right solution in his early writings from 1837 to about 1852, but then he got all confused by not realizing tha~ he applied the term 'varieties' to two entirely different phenomena. We now know that speciation in sexually reproducing organisms is normally a populational process, that is, the acquisition of isolating mechanisms by a population. And normally this can only ha.ppen in geographic isolation. What has become clear since the evolutionary synthesis is that there are actually two forms of geographic speciation. Speciation by secondary isolation, also referred to as the dumbbell model of speciation, takes place when a widespread species is cut through by a newly arisen barrier, either water or an unsuitable vegetation belt, and the two. isolated portions become two species. The Pleistocene ice and climate in the Mississippi Valley produced a large number of such species pairs in refuges east and west of the Mississippi, even though the isolation was often not long enough for the speciation process to be completed, resulting in widespread hybrid belts such as between yellow shafted and red shafted flickers. The other process of speciation, speciation by primary isolation, also called peripatric speciation, occurs when a founder population is established beyond the periphery of the species range and gradually evolves into a new species, owing to the acquisition of isolating mechanisms. The JOURNAL OF MAMMALOGY 6 special aspect of founder populations is that they usually have only a small fraction of the genes of the parental population, and then are exposed both to inbreeding and entirely new selection pressures. As a result, such a population has a chance to shift to an entirely new adaptive zone, accompanied by drastic genetic restructuring. This is why peripatric speciation is so important for macroevolution. The recently published detailed analysis of the evolution of fossil bryozoans is completely consistent with this theory of speciational evolution, called by Eldredge and Gould the theory of punctuated eqUilibrium. At this mammal meeting I will not discuss sympatric speciation because there are no niches of mammal species that would be suitable for sympatric speciation. Even in insects where a shift to a new host plant would seem to make sympatric speciation possible, the evidence is still ambiguous. AFfER THE SYNTHESIS One of the totally unanticipated byproducts of the synthesis was the unification of biology, but this is now considered by some philosophers of science to be the most important achievement of the synthesis. But, was the synthesis really a success as far as evolution is concerned? How complete was the synthesis of the two opposing camps of the early 1930s? Well, I am afraid one must admit that it was not entirely complete. The naturalists still considered the individual-as-a-whole to be the major target of selection, while the geneticists, for the sake of their calculations, preferred to consider the gene as this target. Therefore, they left out of their calculations all the evolutionary consequences of the interaction of different genes. In fact, even today most of the geneticists ignore a fact, which has been established many times, namely that the same gene may have a different selective value in one genotype than in another one. The emphasis on the gene also is responsible for the so-called theory of neutral evo- Vol. 77, No. 1 lution. Kimura and others showed that some mutational allele replacements have no effect on the fitness of the new genotype. He called such changes neutral mutations and refers to their incorporation into the genotype as neutral evolution. However, there is obviously no selection of such neutral mutations. They are simply accidental members of successful genotypes, and even though the genotype on which they became part of the popUlation, was favored by selection, the neutral genes only came along, so to speak, as hitchhikers. Such neutral mutations are evolutionary "noise" rather thim evolution. By concentrating on single genes rather than on individuals-as-awhole, geneticists also have more difficulty in studying bottleneck effects as well as the role of inbreeding in very small populations. A second area where the synthesis has not yet been entirely successful is the replacement of typological by population thinking. This is most evident in physical anthropology where Australopithecus africanus, Homo habilis, Homo erectus, and other formerly existing hominid taxa are still conceived of rather typologically. The same is true in much of paleontology. And typological thinking is still rather widespread in the study of microorganisms and fungi, in part by necessity, because asexual organisms do not form Mendelian populations. What is most characteristic for science is the steady advance in our theories and our thinking. It is therefore quite legitimate to ask questions about the future of the evolutionary synthesis. For instance, has any part of the synthesis been refuted, as has been claimed by quite a few critics? The clear answer is no. The so-called theory of punctuated equilibria, for instance, is merely an elaboration of my own theory of speciational evolution, published in 1954. There I pointed out quite clearly that this is a populational theory, and even though it results in a rather remarkable speeding up of evolution, it is not saltational at all and February 1996 MAYR-CAPSTONE ADDRESS is nowhere in the slightest conflict with the synthesis. The next question we can ask is whether any other evolutionary theory has been proposed in the last 50 years that would seem to be a threat to the evolutionary synthesis. The answer again is no. No such theory has ever been proposed. Finally, one might ask whether there are any parts of the existing Darwinian theory that look as if they were in need of replacement? Again I must say no. To be sure, there are still large areas in biology where our knowledge is incomplete, one might even say quite insufficient. However, invariably this has to do with the properties of complex systems. The three systems that are particularly obvious in this respect are first the neuronal system of the brain, the second, the problem of the translation of the genetic program of the fertilized egg through development into the adult organism, and third, the interactions that occur within an ecosystem. Whatever the solution to these three great 7 sets of problems will be, I am quite convinced that none of these solutions will be in any conflict whatsoever with the theory structure of the evolutionary synthesis. It is therefore no exaggeration to claim that the evolutionary synthesis was one of the most remarkable and successful events in the history of biological science. Thank you. Addendum by Ernst Mayr, 14 September 1995. To those who want to make a more thorough study of the history of modern evolutionary theory, I recommend these books. D. (ED.) 1985. The Darwinian heritage. Princeton University Press, Princeton, New Jersey, 1138 pp. MAYR, E. 1982. The growth of biological thought: diversity, evolution, and inheritance. The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 974 pp. - - - . 1988. Toward a new philosophy of biology: observations of an evolutionist. The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 564 pp. - - - . 1991. One long argument. Charles Darwin and the genesis of modern evolutionary thought. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 195 pp. KOHN,