* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download The trade-off between intra- and intergenerational equity in climate
Climate sensitivity wikipedia , lookup
Climate change mitigation wikipedia , lookup
Effects of global warming on human health wikipedia , lookup
General circulation model wikipedia , lookup
Climate change feedback wikipedia , lookup
Global warming wikipedia , lookup
Attribution of recent climate change wikipedia , lookup
German Climate Action Plan 2050 wikipedia , lookup
Climate engineering wikipedia , lookup
Climate change adaptation wikipedia , lookup
Media coverage of global warming wikipedia , lookup
Mitigation of global warming in Australia wikipedia , lookup
Climate governance wikipedia , lookup
Stern Review wikipedia , lookup
2009 United Nations Climate Change Conference wikipedia , lookup
Climate change in Tuvalu wikipedia , lookup
Solar radiation management wikipedia , lookup
Climate change and agriculture wikipedia , lookup
Scientific opinion on climate change wikipedia , lookup
Citizens' Climate Lobby wikipedia , lookup
Politics of global warming wikipedia , lookup
United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change wikipedia , lookup
Surveys of scientists' views on climate change wikipedia , lookup
Economics of climate change mitigation wikipedia , lookup
Climate change in Canada wikipedia , lookup
Economics of global warming wikipedia , lookup
Effects of global warming on humans wikipedia , lookup
Public opinion on global warming wikipedia , lookup
Climate change in the United States wikipedia , lookup
Effects of global warming on Australia wikipedia , lookup
Climate change, industry and society wikipedia , lookup
Carbon Pollution Reduction Scheme wikipedia , lookup
11 May 2012 Preliminary draft The trade-off between intra- and intergenerational equity in climate policy1 by Snorre Kverndokk 2, Eric Nævdal 3 and Linda Nøstbakken 4 Abstract This paper focus on two equity aspects of climate policy, intra- and intergenerational equity, that both have an important impact on the optimal response to global warming. We set up an intertemporal two country model where each country suffers from global warming, but also has inequality aversion within the generation. Preliminary results show that inequality aversion within a generation leads to lower consumption in the rich country and higher consumption in the poor country. This also gives higher investments in clean energy in the rich region and higher investments in dirty energy in the poor region, giving a higher abatement burden to the rich region in the baseline. These effects are reinforced in the social optimum. However, consumption levels will converge in the long run. Finally, we study how total emissions will depend on inequality aversion within a generation. JEL codes: D31, Q54, Keywords: Equity, inequality aversion, climate policy 1 This paper is funded by the program MILJØ2015 at the Research Council of Norway. The authors are associated with CREE — Oslo Centre for Research on Environmentally friendly Energy. CREE is supported by the Research Council of Norway. 2 The Ragnar Frisch Centre for Economic Research, Gaustadallèen 21, 0349 Oslo, Norway. E-mail: [email protected]. 3 The Ragnar Frisch Centre for Economic Research, Gaustadallèen 21, 0349 Oslo, Norway. E-mail: [email protected]. 4 Alberta School of Business, University of Alberta, 2-32D Business, Edmonton, Alberta, Canada T6G 2R6. Email: [email protected]. 1 1. Introduction While climate change for many years has been recognized as a threat to the future by most scientists and politicians, there is still an ongoing debate on what to do about this. Researchers may not agree on the optimal emission reductions even if they would agree on the natural science background as well as the costs to abate greenhouse gas emissions. The reason is that optimal emission reductions to a large degree depend on equity issues, and how we discount future climate impacts is especially important, see Dasgupta (2008) for an overview, and Anthoff and Tol (2009) for illustrations. However, ethical issues have not been fully explored in economic analyzes as greenhouse gas (GHG) abatement not only affects the welfare distribution between present and future generations, but also the distribution within a generation such as between rich and poor countries. These two equity aspects are important when studying optimal emissions reductions, and as we explain below, they may work in different directions. The two mentioned dimensions of equity in climate change polices are named intragenerational and intergenerational. The first is mainly about how we should distribute the burdens within a generation, either within the generation living today or in the future, see Kverndokk and Rose (2008). Examples of this can be; who would suffer from climate change (inaction) and how should the burdens of mitigation (action) be distributed? Over the next decades, the world may face large climatic changes in form of increased temperature, sea level rise, changed wind and precipitation patterns, more extreme weather, etc. (IPCC, 2007a). However, the damage of climate change will not be evenly distributed among countries or within a country. Studies such as Tol et al., 2000; Tol, 2002a,b, and Yohe et al., 2007 show that some sectors will lose from climate change while others will benefit, and poor countries are likely to face relatively higher negative impacts than rich countries. Several economic studies also show that the costs of action will vary among countries and sectors, and that it is generally more expensive to abate the more energy efficient the economy is (see, e.g., IPCC, 2007b). Policy instruments implemented to reduce greenhouse gas emissions will also impose different burdens on people, and in general, economic instruments such as carbon taxes, will often be regressive. I.e., the burden will be highest for the poorest, unless special circumstances prevail (see, e.g., Bye et al, 2002). 2 While intragenerational equity is important, most of the equity debate on climate change issues in the economic literature has been on intergenerational equity issues, i.e., distributions across generations, focusing on how much emissions reduction we should aim for, or how large the atmospheric GHG concentration or global mean temperature ceiling should be. This involves the distribution of burdens between the current generation and future generations as the burdens of mitigation - the costs - have to be taken by the present generation while the benefits of mitigation will be felt by future generations. There are several reasons for extensive mitigation today such as attitudes to risk as well as concerns about catastrophic events (Weitzman, 2007a), but most of the discussion has been about the appropriate discount rate to use for climate change policy decisions, as the optimal level of abatement is very sensitive to the choice of discount rate. Discount rates are weights put on future benefits of climate change policies in order to compare the future benefits to the present costs. If we measure costs and benefits in consumption units, the main reasons for discounting are that we may treat different generations differently (the pure rate of time preferences, PRTP), and that the benefit of a consumption unit differs depending of the consumption level. While a positive number on the PRTP means a discrimination of future generations, the second argument is that a high level of consumption gives a low marginal utility of an additional unit, represented by the elasticity of the marginal utility of consumption (EMUC). Thus, a high consumption level for future generations may be an argument for paying less attention to these generations, e.g., mitigate less as the benefits of this in consumption units have low impact on future welfare levels. In this way the EMUC represents intergenerational equity preferences. 5 Both the choice of the PRTP and the EMUC then represent ethical choices. The consumption discount rate (CDR) that is used in economic analyses combines these two arguments. The choice of the appropriate discount rate has been a controversial issue for years. For instance, the Stern Review (Stern, 2007) used a quite low CDR and, therefore, found a high level of optimal abatement compared to other studies such as Nordhaus (1993) and Nordhaus and Boyer (2000). This created a lively debate where, e.g., Nordhaus (2007) and Weitzman (2007b) argued against the choice of the low discount rate based on observed values of the 5 Note that the EMUC is often referred to as the coefficient of risk aversion or the inequality aversion coefficient, in addition to being the elasticity of the marginal utility of consumption. Thus, it plays a triple role. An attempt to separate inequality aversion from risk aversion and to quantify them using experiments, is found in Carlsson et al. (2005). 3 long-run return to capital. However, Heal (2009) shows that equality between CDR and the return to capital only holds under idealized conditions, such as a one-good model and perfect market assumptions such as lack of external effects, which obviously do not hold in the presence of climate change. The one-good model has also been criticized by Hoel and Sterner (2007) and Sterner and Persson (2008) who pointed out that if there is consumption of an environmental good in addition to a produced consumption good, the environmental good will become more scarce over time relative to the produced good as we experience more climate change. This could be an argument for using a low and even negative CDR for environmental services. The problem is that most studies choose to focus on either an intragenerational or an intergenerational distributive justice problem, and then assume that these problems are autonomous, i.e., that they can be treated separately. However, choices that affect the intergenerational distribution also have impacts on the intragenerational distribution between rich and poor countries. As Heal (2009) points out there are two ways preferences for equality affect the choice of action when it comes to climate change. First, a high EMUC will lead to less aggressive action if we believe that consumption is growing over time. The reason is that this makes future generations richer, and if we care about inequality between the present and future generations, we place a lower value to the richer future generations (intergenerational equity). But there is also another effect. The rich countries are mainly responsible for the aggregate level of greenhouse gases in the atmosphere, while, as mentioned above, the poor countries are likely to suffer most from climate change. Thus, if we put a low weight on future outcomes, climate change is more likely to happen and poor countries may suffer more (intragenerational equity). The gap between the welfare levels of the rich and the poor may, therefore, be higher. Based on the latter effect, stronger preferences for equality should, therefore, go in the direction of more action to prevent climate change. These two effects of inequality aversion go in different directions and the impacts of stronger preferences for equity on the level of greenhouse gas abatement are ambiguous. The problem is that the global models that are used to determine the optimal level of greenhouse gas emissions only take the first effect into account. This means that a greater preference for equality in these models actually induces a low abatement level as found in, e.g., Nordhaus and Boyer (2000). 4 So far we are not aware of any studies that take both inequality aversions into account when finding the optimal abatement level for greenhouse gas emissions. Thus, this paper closes this gap, by showing how inequality aversion may affect the optimal policy response to address climate change. We ask the following question: is climate policy a good thing when policy makers have preferences for both inter- and intragenerational equity? A simple model of two regions, a rich and a poor, are set up that explicitly takes into account preferences for the two aspects of equality, before finding the optimal climate policy. Preferences for intragenerational equality will go in the direction of reducing consumption in the rich region and increasing consumption in the poor region, which may both have impacts on emissions that follow from production of an aggregate macro good. This socially optimal policy will be compared to business-as-usual where there is no coordinated action, as well as to the optimal policy under standard preferences in the economics of climate change, i.e., no explicit modeling of inequality aversion within a generation. Finally, we study how inequality aversion within a generation affects greenhouse gas emissions, i.e., the distribution of welfare across generations. 2. A model of inequality aversion 2.1 The starting point Following Rawls (1971), we consider a veil of ignorance situation where representative individuals from prospective countries around the world meet to design the future organization of the society. All individuals know that some countries are going to be rich and some poor, and that economic activity will result in greenhouse gas emissions that will have a negative impact on them in terms of climate change. However, they do not know if they are going to live in a rich or in a poor country. The question they would like to answer is: Is climate policy a good thing? The reason why we ask this question is that climate policies may have different effects on distribution in an intragenerational and an intergenerational perspective. Widespread mitigation today may affect developing countries more negatively than industrialized countries as it may harm economic growth and their possibility to develop, but may be good in the future as it reduces future damages. 5 All the representative individuals behind the veil of ignorance care about inequality, but some more than others; preferences are heterogeneous, but they do not change even when they learn their position in the society. In addition to this, individuals have preferences about future welfare (welfare of future generations) compared to the welfare of the present generation. These preferences are represented by the concavity of the utility function; the elasticity of the marginal utility of consumption, and the pure rate of time preference. Behind the veil of ignorance, the representative individuals agree on the social planner’s decision problem: Since climate change is a global problem, the representative individuals or countries will not have the incentive to pursue the global social optimum. Thus, they decide to follow the policy that comes out of the social planner’s optimization problem. Further, they agree on the rate of pure time preferences: Since the social planner has to make decisions across generations, they need to agree on a proper time preference rate. In addition to this, the distribution of the different inequality parameters of the representative individuals is known behind the veil of ignorance, and submitted as input to the social planner. The social planner also takes into account other preferences, the development of the environment, and the available technologies. In the following we set up a simple model to illustrate the problems described above. We simplify the set up by a considering a representative consumer or country of the poor and the rich region and study their choices without the social contract before comparing those to the decisions under the contract. 2.1 The basics of the model The utility of a representative consumer/country in region i at time t is: U i= u (ci ,t , St ) − α i max ( c j ,t − ci ,t , 0 ) − βi max ( ci ,t − c j ,t , 0 ) ,t where c is consumption and S is the state of the environment. Preferences for equality are modeled as inequality aversion following Fehr and Schmidt (1999). Based on this, consumers have inequality aversion in such a way that they dislike having a higher consumption/income than others, but they dislike even more having a lower consumption/income than other consumers they compare themselves to. Let α be a parameter representing the negative feeling 6 (1) of being worse off than other individuals, while β is the parameter representing the negative feeling of being better off than other individuals. We then have that α ≥ β. We ignore strategic interactions by assuming that each region, North and South, consists of many identical countries that do not have any market power and cannot individually affect environmental quality. Without loss of generality, let us assume that the population sizes of the two regions are equal and normalized to unity. Thus, ci is also per capita consumption in region i. Further, we model each region's representative country's production of an aggregate macro good, Yr,t, with two types of inputs, clean and dirty that are perfect substitutes, = Yr ,t Yr ,c ,t + Yr ,d ,t (2) Yr ,c ,t = Ac ,t K rγ,cc ,t (3) Yr ,d ,t = Ad ,t K rγ,dd ,t (4) where subscript c and d denote clean and dirty. Thus, the clean input is produced using clean (green) capital, while the dirty input is produced using dirty (brown) capital. We assume diminishing returns to scale so that ϒc and ϒd have values less than one. The productivity of dirty capital is higher than for clean capital, i.e., Ad,t > Ac,t for all t . Further, we assume that the technologies are exogenously given and constant over time ( Ajt = Aj , j = c, d ). A country can invest in clean and dirty capital, with capital dynamics given by: K r , j ,t +1 = n, s, j = c, d , (1 − δ j ) K r , j ,t + I r , j ,t , r = where δ j is the capital depreciation rate . The environment is modeled as a stock variable. It deteriorates with the aggregate use of the dirty capital and regenerates naturally at a rate σ : 7 (5) St +1 = σ S + (1 − σ ) St − ηYd ,t , (6) Yd ,t is aggregated dirty input over the two regions, and η is emissions per unit of dirty input. The environmental quality is constrained as follows: St ∈ 0, S , where S is the level of environmental quality in absence of pollution (dirty production). Note that in the absence of pollution, S will converge asymptotically to S . Thus we treat climate change as a reversible process in the long run. Let n denote a representative consumer in the developed region (North) and s a representative consumer in the developing region (South), where consumption initially is larger in the North than in the South, i.e., cn ,1 > cs ,1 ., as North is endowed with more initial productive capital than the South. Thus, we can write the utility functions as: U n ,1= u ( cn ,1 , S1 ) − β n ( cn ,1 − cs ,1 ) (7) U s ,1= u ( cs ,1 , S1 ) − α s ( cn ,1 − cs ,1 ) (8) 2.2 Business as usual Now, assume that the policy makers in the different regions want to maximize the utility of a representative consumer. Let us start with the business as usual problem (BAU), i.e., the optimization problem of the policy makers when there is no coordinated action or environmental agreement. This would be the situation without the social contract (social optimum). As mentioned above, consumption in n is larger than in s at the starting point, period 1, i.e., cn ,1 > cs ,1 . Would consumption in s ever be higher than consumption in n? Assume first that α s = α n and β s = β n , i.e., all inequality preferences are equal. In this case consumption in s will never exceed consumption in n in the non-cooperative Nash equilibria in BAU, as otherwise cn ,1 > cs ,1 would not follow from utility optimization. 8 Then consider the case where α s ≠ α n and β s ≠ β n . Assume that environmental quality S is considered exogenous, i.e., each country disregards its impact on the environment as it is so small that its impact is approximately zero. In this case, if consumption in the initial period is found as the non-cooperative Nash equilibria in BAU, we will reach a steady state BAU path where consumption in s never exceeds consumption in n. If that was the case, n would not initially consume more than s. Can we achieve convergence of consumption in the two regions? Inequality aversion gives an incentive to equalize consumption in the two regions, and we will discuss this further below. Based on this, we can set up the BAU optimization problem as consumers maximizing t= t= ∞ ∞ t −1 t −1 n ,t n ,t =t 1 =t 1 (9) t= t= ∞ ∞ t −1 t −1 s ,t s ,t =t 1 =t 1 (10) ∑ρ ∑ρ U U = ∑ρ = ∑ρ u ( c , St ) − β n ( cn ,t − cs ,t ) u ( c , St ) − α s ( cn ,t − cs ,t ) respectively, given the technology (2)-(5), environmental constraint (6) and the goods market constraints cr ,t =Yr ,t − I r ,c ,t − I r ,d ,t , for r = n, s . ρ is the time preference rate, which is set equal for both consumers in order not to have the effects of inequality aversion confounded by the effects of discounting. Note that by substituting in for investment, I r ,c ,t and I r ,d ,t , using equation (5), the goods market constraint for a country in region r can be rewritten as: = Yr ,t K r ,c ,t +1 − (1 − δ c ) K r ,c ,t + K r ,d ,t +1 − (1 − δ d ) K r ,d ,t + cr ,t . (11) To find the non-cooperative Nash equilibria for the two regions, we first define the Lagrangian for the two regions. For region n the Lagrangian is BAU = ∞ ∑ρ t =1 t −1 {u(c n ,t , St ) − β n ( cn ,t − cs ,t ) } +λn ,t Yn ,t ( K n ,c ,t , K n ,d ,t ) − K n ,c ,t +1 + (1 − δ c ) K n ,c ,t − K n ,d ,t +1 + (1 − δ d ) K n ,d ,t − cn ,t 9 (12) where λn,t > 0 is the shadow price on capital. Recall that we made the assumption of each representative country being so small that its impact on the dynamics of environmental quality is approximately zero. Hence, (12) is maximized over consumption, and dirty and clean capital stocks, but not over environmental quality. First order conditions are: ∂BAU = ρ t −1 u 'ct − β n − λ= 0 n ,t ∂cn ,t { } (13) ∂Y ∂BAU = − δ c − ρ t −1λnt 0 ρ t λn ,t +1 n ,t +1 + 1= ∂K n ,c ,t ∂K n ,c ,t +1 (14) ∂Yn ,t +1 ∂BAU ρ t λn ,t +1 δ d − ρ t −1λn ,t 0 = +1− = ∂K n ,d ,t +1 ∂K n ,d ,t +1 (15) These first order conditions can also be written as: [cn ,t ] : u 'ct − β n = λn ,t (16) ∂Yn ,t +1 : 1 λ ρλ δ + − [ K r ,c ,t= ] +1 n ,t n ,t +1 c ∂K n ,c ,t +1 (17) ∂Y [ K r ,d ,= λn ,t ρλn ,t +1 n ,t +1 + 1 − δ d t +1 ] : ∂K n ,d ,t +1 (18) The first order conditions for region s are similar apart from the determination of consumption which is found from: [cs ,t ] : u 'ct + α s = λs ,t (19) Equations (16) and (19) show that in optimum, the present marginal benefit from increased consumption should equal the opportunity cost of increasing the consumption, i.e., the shadow price of capital. 10 Compared to standard preferences, i.e., without any inequality aversion (αr = βr = 0, r = n,s), the marginal benefits of consumption would be lower in n in our case, while it will be higher in s, indicating a lower level of consumption in n and a higher level of consumption in s. This gives us the first proposition: Proposition 1: Inequality aversion within one generation will reduce consumption in the North in Business-As-Usual. For South we find the opposite result. Equations (17) and (18) determine the investments in clean and dirty capital, respectively. The interpretations of these equations are that the benefits of increased capital in period t should equal the social costs of these capital investments. For both types of capital, the cost of investment is lower consumption in the previous period. Using equations (17) and (18), we can eliminate λn ,t , λn ,t +1 , and ρ . This yields the following relationship between clean and dirty capital in region r = n, s : ∂Yr ,t ∂K r ,d ,t − ∂Yr ,t ∂K r ,c ,t δd − δc . = (20) Equation (20) states that the country should adjusts its stock of clean and dirty capital so that the difference in the marginal productivities of clean and dirty capital equals the difference in capital depreciation rates. Hence, if clean and dirty capital depreciates at the same rate, the country should adjust its capital stocks so that the marginal productivity of each type of capital is the same. Given that dirty capital is more productive than clean capital, this implies that all countries will have more dirty than clean capital in the business-as-usual case, regardless of equality preferences. How would inequality aversion affect investments in clean and dirty capital in the two regions respectively? Consider first region n. In this region inequality aversion leads to a lower consumption. This will further lead to lower investments in dirty capital and higher investments in clean capital. The intuition behind this is that a lower consumption would not require investments in the most effective capital (dirty) and also that investments in clean capital will reduce emissions of greenhouse gases and thereby improve the environment. A better environment will increase utility and therefore work as a substitute to lower consumption in the utility function in n. In s, the intuition works the other way around and 11 investments in dirty capital will increase while investments in clean capital will be lower. In general we cannot say whether this improves the environment compared to the case without inequality aversion. [Note that the argument assumes that the consumers are aware of their impacts on the environment. If they take the environment as exogenous as specified above, the only way to reduce consumption without increasing consumption in the future is to invest in the most ineffective technology, i.e., the clean technology]. This gives the following proposition: Proposition 2: Inequality aversion within one generation will increase investments in clean capital and reduce investments in dirty capital in the North in Business-As-Usual. For South we find the opposite result. 2.3 The social contract Within this modeling framework and with a social planner determining production, consumption, and capital investment in every country (region), consumption in the North would never exceed consumption in the South (per capita). Instead, we expect to see convergence over time. Hence, we can use the simplified utility functions (7) and (8). The social planner seeks to maximize the sum of discounted welfare across all countries, where welfare in period t is defined as: = Wt u (cn ,t , St ) + u (cs ,t , St ) − ( β n + α s ) ( cn ,t − cs ,t ) (21) The maximization problem can then be expressed as: ∞ max {cnt ,cst , K nct +1 , K sct +1 , K ndt +1 , K sdt +1 , St +1 } ∑ ρ ∑ u (c t r ,t t =0 r , St ) − φ ( cn ,t − cs ,t ) , where φ ≡ ( β n + α s ) , which is a constant, subject to (2), (5), (6), and the goods market constraints (11). The Lagrangian of the maximization problem (22) can now be expressed as follows: 12 (22) SO = ∞ ∑ ρ ∑ u(c t =1 t −1 r ,t , St ) − φ ( cn ,t − cs ,t ) r + ∑ λr ,t Yr ,t ( K r ,c ,t , K r ,d ,t ) − K r ,c ,t +1 + (1 − δ c ) K r ,c ,t − K r ,d ,t +1 + (1 − δ d ) K r ,d ,t − cr ,t (23) r + µt St +1 − σ S − (1 − σ ) St + η ∑ Yr ,d ,t ( K r ,d ,t ) r First order conditions include: [cn ,t ] :t = 0, 1, 2,⋅⋅⋅ ∂u (cn ,t , St ) λn ,t −φ = ∂cn ,t (24) [cs ,t ] : t = 0, 1, 2,⋅⋅⋅ ∂u (cs ,t , St ) λs ,t +φ = ∂cs ,t (25) [ K r ,d ,t ] : t = 1, 2,⋅⋅⋅ [ K r ,c ,t ] : t = 1, 2,⋅⋅⋅ [ St ] : t = 1, 2,⋅⋅⋅ ∂Yr ,t λr ,t ∂K r ,d ,t ∂Yr ,d ,t −1 λr ,t −1 , r n, s + 1 − δ d + µt η= ρ= ∂K r ,d ,t ∂Yr ,t (26) λr ,t 1 = + 1 − δ c ρ −= λr ,t −1 , r n, s ∂K r ,c ,t (27) ∂u (cr ,t , St ) −1 ∑ = µt (1 − σ ) − ρ µt −1 ∂ S t r (28) Clearly, an important question when analyzing the optimal solution is whether consumption in the two regions will in fact converge to the same level in the long run. We therefore start by investigating this. 2.4 Will consumption levels converge in the long run? In the long run, the economy will enter a steady state. In steady state there will be no growth in any of the model variables since there is no technological progress. We can therefore rewrite the first order conditions (24)-(28) for the steady-state levels of the variables: ∂u (cn , S ) λn −φ = ∂cn (29) ∂u (cs , S ) + φ = λs ∂cs (30) 13 ∂Yr ∂Yr ,d −1 λr , r n, s + 1 − δ d + µ η = ρ= K K ∂ ∂ r ,d r ,d (31) λr ∂Yr 1 λr , r n, s + 1= − δ c ρ −= ∂K r ,c (32) ∂u (cr , S ) −1 ∑ ∂S = µ (1 − σ ) − ρ r (33) λr From equation (32) it is clear that the long-run capital level must be the same in the two regions. Since ρ and δ c are the same for both countries, the marginal product of clean capital must be the same in the two regions, and with a production function that is increasing monotonically in clean capital, this implies that K= K s ,c ≡ K c* in equilibrium. n ,c Let us next consider the long-run levels of dirty capital, given by equation (31). Equation (31) can be rewritten as follows: ∂Y µ ∂Y 1 r + 1 − δ d + η r ,d − = r n, s 0, = ∂K r ,d λr ∂K r ,d ρ λr (34) Hence, we can write: λn MPn ,d + 1 − δ d + where MPr , j ≡ 1 1 µ µ η MPn ,d = − λs MPs ,d + 1 − δ d + η MPs ,d − , λn ρ λs ρ (35) ∂Yr is the marginal productivity of capital j in region r . ∂K r , j Let us first assume that the south never catches up with the north, so that cn > cs in steady state. From (29) and (30) we know that the shadow price of capital then must be lower in the in the north than in the south ( λn < λs ), since north has a higher consumption level and thus a lower marginal utility from goods consumption. Next, by introducing this into condition (35) we see that the marginal productivity of capital must be higher in the north than in the south for the condition to hold. However, if cn > cs it must also be the case that K nd > K sd , since we already established that the level of clean capital is the same in the two regions in the long run. Since the marginal productivity is decreasing in the level of dirty capital, this implies that 14 MPnd < MPsd when cn > cs . Hence, condition (35) cannot hold unless cn = cs , which means that the consumption level of the two regions must converge in the long run. This gives us Proposition 3: Proposition 3: In the long run, the social optimal consumption levels of North and South will converge. 2.5 Optimal policy We have established that the optimal policy requires the consumption levels of the regions to converge toward the same level in the long run. This implies that also the levels of dirty capital in the two countries converge in the long run. Let us now consider how inequality aversion affects the optimal consumption and capital paths in the two regions. We start out by looking at optimal consumption. From and we know that optimality requires that the marginal utility from goods consumption and inequality ( φ ) must equals the shadow value of capital. For the North, this implies that an additional unit of consumption today yields higher utility from consumption but disutility from more inequality. In the South, we have the opposite effect of inequality aversion. An additional unit of consumption today increases utility both from consumption and from reduced inequality. Consequently, introducing inequality aversion shifts the consumption path of the North downwards compared to the case without inequality aversion, while the consumption path of the South shifts upwards. Next, by eliminating φ from the two equations, we find that: λn + λs = uc′n + uc′s . Hence, the sum of the two regions' shadow values of capital must equal the sum of their marginal utility of goods consumption. Hence, we do not need the shadow price of capital to equal the marginal utility from consumption in each region, as long as the condition holds at the aggregate level. This result holds regardless of preferences for equality. Let us now compare the optimal consumption levels under the social contract with the BAU levels of consumption by comparing equations (24) and (25) to equations (16) and (19). The difference in the optimality conditions for consumption is that each country under the social contract takes into account both countries disutility from inequality, not just its own disutility. 15 Hence, the North reduces (and the South increases) consumption more under the social contract than in the business-as-usual case, all else equal. We summarize this result in proposition 4: Proposition 4: Inequality aversion within one generation will lead to a larger reduction in consumption in the North and increase in consumption in the South under the social contract than in the business-as-usual case. For the North to reduce consumption and the South to increase consumption relative to the case without inequality aversion, North invests relatively more in clean capital while South invests relatively more in dirty capital. It follows that the North is taking a bigger hit to improve the environment, which can be thought of as an indirect transfer of welfare from North to South. This also implies that a stronger concern for equality causes the two regions' consumption levels to converge faster. Next, consider the optimal capital paths. By eliminating common terms from the two regions' optimality conditions for clean capital (27) and rearranging, we obtain the following condition: ∂Ys ,t ∂K s ,c ,t − ∂Yn ,t ∂K n ,c ,t = λs ,t λ − n ,t . ρλs ,t +1 ρλn ,t +1 (36) In the short run, before the two regions converge at time t = t * , we know that the North has more capital and a higher share of clean capital than the South. Hence, it must be that K n ,c ,t > K s ,c ,t for t < t * , which implies that the marginal product of clean capital is higher in the South than in the North over this time period. It follows that the left hand side of (36) is positive. This implies that: λs ,t λs ,t +1 > , λn ,t λn ,t +1 which means that the difference in the shadow value of capital between the south and the north decreases over time until convergence is reached in the long run (at time t * ). 16 (37) In a similar way, we can also find that the south has more dirty capital than the north, but that there will be a convergence over time as the consumption levels also converges. We can also do the same comparison between the social contract and BAU for regional capital stocks. This involves comparing optimality conditions (27) and (28) to conditions (14) and (15). The optimality condition for clean capital is the same in the two cases. However, the optimality condition for dirty capital under the social contract includes an additional term compared to the BAU case. This term represents the marginal effect of more dirty capital on environmental quality. The inclusion of this term in the social contract case implies lower investment in dirty capital under the social contract compared to the BAU case, since the environmental externality is internalized. 2.6 The impact on the environment How does inequality aversion across a generation affect greenhouse gas emissions? The steady-state condition for environmental quality can be rearranged and expressed in terms of the shadow prices of the environment: µ= uS′ ( cn , S ) + uS′ ( cs , S ) 1 − σ −1 ρ (38) It follows that the steady-state value of the shadow price of the environment ( µ ) increases in the marginal utility of environmental quality, given by the numerator in equation (38), and increases in the replenishment rate of the environment and decreases in the discount factor. Equation (38) also reveals that the steady-state level of environmental quality does not depend directly on the regions’ preferences for equality ( φ ), but is indirectly affected by inequality preferences through other variables, such as consumption. As seen above inequality aversion will reduce emissions in North, but increase them in South before the steady-state solution is reached. If there is a trade-off between inequality across and within a generation, the introduction of the Fehr-Schmidt utility functions will increase emissions, i.e., ∂S ∂S < 0 . Thus, to study the conditions for this to happen, we need to find ∂φ ∂φ in the steady-state. The steady state level of environmental quality is given by: 17 S∞ = σ S − ∑η prYr ,d ,t ( K r ,d ,t ) r (39) σ It is however hard to pin down exactly what the effect of inequality aversion is, so a numerical experiment is performed. We choose a utility function of the form U r = crθ1,t Stθ2 For numerical simplicity we also slightly modify preferences for inequality to be given by −φ ( cn ,t − cs ,t ) . Solving for the social contract when φ = 0 and φ > 0 gives very different paths 2 for St. These are illustrated in Figure 1. 100 S without inequality aversion S with inequality aversion 90 80 70 60 50 40 30 20 0 50 100 150 200 250 Although S has the same initial value, the case where there is inequality aversion clearly leads to significantly lower levels of environmental quality. 3.6 Extensions So far we have assumed constant population and technology. Would more realistic assumptions change the conclusions above? Let us first start with BAU. The following can be shown within the model: Assume that population is increasing exogenously, but that the growth is higher in s than in n. If we further assume that population also affects production as an input factor, and that we have diminishing returns to scale, production per capita will go down, and the distance 18 between North and South when it comes to per capita production will widen. This will reinforce the arguments above. Now assume an exogenous technological change, i.e., an exogenous increase in Aj,t, j=c,d. If the growth is equal for both technologies, the results above will not change. If there is higher growth in the productivity of the green technology, the incentive to invest in this will be higher. Finally consider an endogenous technological change such as learning by doing, i.e., Ac,t and Ad,t increase as a function of aggregated production of the clean or dirty input in the respective region. In this case, the productivity of clean capital will be higher in North than in South and the difference will increase over time. For dirty capital it will be the other way around. 3. Conclusions While the results are only preliminary, they still show some interesting aspects about inequality aversion and climate policy. Based on our modeling framework, inequality aversion within a generation will reduce consumption and greenhouse gas emissions in the rich region of the world, while consumption and emissions will increase in the poor region. This follows from a transfer from dirty to clean capital in the rich region, while we have the opposite transfer in the south. Whether total emissions will increase depends on the relative size of the emissions reductions in the north compared to the increase in the south, which has to be further analyzed. If total emissions increase, there is a trade-off between inequality across and within generations. In section 2 above, we asked the question: Is climate policy a good thing? In our model with constant population and technology, a reduction in total greenhouse gas emissions will reduce the burdens on future generations. If this increases the overall welfare in the model, climate policies is good from an intertemporal equity perspective. This is the case in the model as the social contract gives lower emissions than in BAU. The reason is that the shadow price of the environment is taken into account in the social optimum and not in the optimization problems for the single countries. However, whether climate policy is good or not in a world with inequality aversion depends on how it is designed. We have shown that if the rich countries take the bulk of abatement, we may achieve equity both within a generation and across generations. 19 20 References Anthoff, D. and R. Tol (2009): The Impact of Climate Change on the Balanced Growth Equivalent: An Application of FUND, Environment and Resource Economics, 43: 351-367. Bye, B. S. Kverndokk and K. E. Rosendahl (2002): Mitigation costs, distributional effects, and ancillary benefits of carbon policies in the Nordic countries, the UK, and Ireland, Mitigation and Adaptation Strategies for Global Change, 7(4): 339-366. Carlsson, F., D. Daruvala and O. Johansson-Stenman (2005): Are People Inequality-Averse, or Just Risk-Averse?, Economica, 72: 375-396. Dasgupta, P. (2008): Discounting Climate change, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 37: 141169. Fehr, E. and K. Schmidt (1999): A theory of fairness, competition, and cooperation. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 114(3), 817-868. Heal, G. (2009): Climate Economics: A Meta-Review and Some Suggestions for Future Research, Review of Environmental Economics and Policy, 3(1): 4-21. Hoel, M. and T. Sterner (2007): Discounting and relative prices, Climatic Change 84: 265280. Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC) (2007a): Climate Change 2007: The Physical Science Basis, Contribution of Working Group I to the Fourth Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK. Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC) (2007b): Climate Change 2007: Mitigation of Climate Change, Contribution of Working Group III to the Fourth Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK. Kverndokk, S. and A. Rose (2008): Equity and justice in global warming policy, International Review of Environmental and Resource Economics, 2(2): 135-176. Nordhaus, W. D. (1993): Rolling the DICE: An optimal transition for controlling the emission of greenhouse gases, Resource and Energy Economics, 15: 27-50. Nordhaus, W. D. and J. G. Boyer (2000): Warming the World: The Economics of the Greenhouse Effect, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Nordhaus, W. D. (2007): A Review of the Stern Review on the Economics of Climate Change, Journal of Economic Literature, 45(3): 686–702. Rawls, J. (1971): A Theory of Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Stern, N. (2007): The Economics of Climate Change: The Stern Review, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK. 21 Sterner, T. and M. Persson (2008): An even Sterner review: Introducing relative prices into the discounting debate, Review of Environmental Economics and Policy, 2: 77-93. Tol, R., S. Fankhauser, R. Richels and J. Smith (2000): How Much Damage Will Climate Change Do? Recent Estimates. World Economics, 1(4): 179-206. Tol, R. (2002a): Estimates of the Damage Costs of Climate Change. Part 1: Benchmark Estimates, Environmental and Resource Economics, 21: 47-73. Tol, R. (2002b): Estimates of the Damage Costs of Climate Change. Part II: Dynamic Estimates, Environmental and Resource Economics, 21: 135-160. Weitzman, M. (2007a): Structural uncertainty and the value of statistical life in the economics of catastrophic climate change, Department of Economics, Harvard University, Working Paper, July. Weitzman, M. (2007b): A Review of the Stern Review on the Economics of Climate Change, Journal of Economic Literature, 45(3): 703–724. Yohe, G. W., R. D. Lasco, Q. K. Ahmad, N. W. Arnell, S. J. Cohen, C. Hope, A. C. Janetos and R. T. Perez (2007): Perspectives on climate change and sustainability, Chapter 20 in Climate Change 2007: Impacts, Adaptation and Vulnerability. Contribution of Working Group II to the Fourth Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK, 811-841. 22