Download Why Darwin rejected intelligent design

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts

Hologenome theory of evolution wikipedia , lookup

Natural selection wikipedia , lookup

Introduction to evolution wikipedia , lookup

The eclipse of Darwinism wikipedia , lookup

On the Origin of Species wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
Commentary
Why Darwin rejected intelligent design
As a Cambridge University undergraduate Charles Darwin was fascinated and convinced by the argument
for intelligent design, as set forth in William Paley’s 1802 classic, Natural Theology. Subsequently, during
his five-year voyage on HMS Beagle (1831–1836), Darwin interpreted his biological findings through a
creationist lens, including the thought-provoking evidence he encountered during his historic visit to the
Galápagos Islands in September and October 1835. After his return to England in 1836 and his subsequent
conversion to the idea of organic evolution in March 1837, Darwin searched for a theory that would
explain both the fact of evolution and the widespread appearance of intelligent design. His insight into
the process of natural selection, which occurred in September 1838, provided this alternative explanation.
Darwin’s Origin of Species (1859) exemplifies his skillful deployment of the hypothetico-deductive
method in testing and refuting the arguments for intelligent design that he had once so ardently admired.
1.
Introduction
There is considerable irony in the fact that Charles Darwin was at one time enthralled by the theory
that all species are intelligently designed–a theory he later sought to banish from science in his Origin
of Species (1859). Popularized in the seventeenth century in works such as John Ray’s The Wisdom of
God Manifested in the Works of the Creation (1691), this doctrine sought to unite a celebration of God’s
handiwork in the Creation with the pursuit of natural science. Such theologically inspired arguments
reached their apogee a century later in the writings of William Paley (figure 1). A clergyman like Ray,
Paley set forth his influential ideas in Natural Theology; or, Evidences of the Existence and Attributes of
the Deity, Collected from the Appearances of Nature (1802). The many proofs he adduced in favour of
intelligent design, including the hinges on bivalve shells and the plumes that facilitate wind dispersal of
certain seeds, fascinated and convinced young Darwin (1958 [1876]:87, 119).
2.
Darwin’s youthful commitment to intelligent design
Natural Theology is constructed around the analogy of a watchmaker, a metaphor borrowed from previous
advocates of the design doctrine. Imagine, Paley suggests, that you are walking across a heath and suddenly
encounter a watch lying on the ground. After close inspection of the watch, you would be compelled to
conclude that such an intricate device could not have been constructed otherwise in order for it to work. It
is only reasonable to assume “that the watch must have had a maker; that there must have existed, at some
time and at some place or other, an artificer or artificers who formed it for the purpose which we find it
actually to answer; who comprehended its construction, and designed its use” (1802:3–4). In the case of
living organisms Paley continued, the evidence for design is even stronger “in a degree which exceeds all
computation” (1802:19), and he concluded: “The marks of design are too strong to be got over. Design
must have had a designer. That designer must have been a person. That person is GOD” (1802:473).
The efforts by Ray, Paley, and others to unite natural history with theology were among the
inducements that inclined Darwin, at the age of eighteen, to look favourably on a career in the church.
Sent by his father two years earlier to study medicine at Edinburgh University, Darwin had found himself
uninspired by this profession and revolted by the sight of operations, which at that time were conducted
without the benefit of anesthesia. Worried that his son might turn into “an idle sporting man,” Darwin’s
Keywords. Charles Darwin; intelligent design; natural selection; Origin of Species; scientific method
http://www.ias.ac.in/jbiosci
J. Biosci. 34(2), June 2009, 173–183, © Indian Academy of Sciences 173
Commentary
174
Figure 1. William Paley (1743–1805), archdeacon of Carlisle (from Paley 1860: Frontispiece). Paley’s works were
mandatory reading at Cambridge University from 1787 to 1920. During Darwin’s undergraduate years (1829-1831),
Paley’s influence on the university’s curriculum was second only to that of Isaac Newton (Crimmins 2004).
father, a successful physician, proposed that he attend Cambridge University in preparation for becoming
an ordained minister. “Considering how fiercely I have been attacked by the orthodox,” Darwin reflected
on this youthful career decision in his Autobiography, “it seems ludicrous that I once intended to be a
clergyman” (1958 [1876]:56–57).
At Christ’s College, Cambridge, Darwin was assigned the same rooms that Paley had occupied
more than a half century earlier (Browne 1995:93). Paley’s Principles of Moral and Political Philosophy
(1785) and his Evidences of Christianity (1794) were among the books selected as examination topics
for Darwin’s BA degree in 1830. Darwin studied these works diligently, as he later recalled in his
Autobiography:
I am convinced that I could have written out the whole of the Evidences with perfect
correctness, but not of course in the clear language of Paley. The logic of this book
and as I may add of his Natural Theology gave me as much delight as did Euclid. The
careful study of these works, without attempting to learn any part by rote, was the only
part of the Academical Course which, as I then felt and as I still believe, was of the
least use to me in the education of my mind. I did not at that time trouble myself about
Paley’s premises; and taking these on trust I was charmed and convinced by the long
line of argumentation. (1958 [1876]:59)
On the very day of publication of the Origin of Species three decades later, Darwin reiterated his praise
for Paley in a letter to his neighbour in Downe, John Lubbock: “I do not think I hardly ever admired a
book more than Paley’s Natural Theology: I could almost formerly have said it by heart” (1991:188). Even
after the Origin had finally turned the tide in thinking about the theory of evolution and had introduced
Darwin’s even more controversial mechanism of evolutionary change–natural selection–Darwin was still
subject to the compelling lure of the design doctrine. The Duke of Argyll reported a conversation he had
had with Darwin on this issue during the last year of Darwin’s life. The Duke had maintained that he could
not look upon certain adaptations, such as those found in orchids, “without seeing that they were the effect
and the expression of mind. I shall never forget Mr Darwin’s answer. He looked at me very hard and said,
‘Well, that often comes over me with overwhelming force; but at other times,’ and he shook his head
vaguely, adding, ‘it seems to go away’” (Darwin 1887, 1:316).
J. Biosci. 34(2), June 2009
Commentary
175
3. The Beagle voyage (1831–1836)
What triggered Darwin’s dramatic change of mind about the origin of species was his five-year voyage
around the world on HMS Beagle, and especially his five-week visit to the Galápagos Islands in
September and October 1835. Legend has it that Darwin underwent a eureka-like conversion to the theory
of evolution during this brief visit. Shorn of the legend, the actual story of Darwin’s conversion, which
only occurred a year and a half later, after his return to England, tells us far more about how science is
really done, especially how theory guides observation and prepares the mind, and how dogged persistence
is often required to transform controversial theories into widely accepted facts.
While in the Galápagos, creationist theory primed Darwin in key ways for what he observed and
understood there. Just as important, this theory also dictated what he failed to observe and understand.
Commenting on his extensive efforts to collect specimens on Charles Island, the second of the four
islands he visited, Darwin recorded in his personal journal, “It will be very interesting to find from future
comparison to what district or ‘centre of creation’ the organized beings of this archipelago must be attached”
(1988:356). He was clearly trying to reconcile the new and strange creatures he was encountering in this
remote archipelago with the prevailing creationist paradigm. According to this theory, different “centres
of creation” explained why the earth’s flora and fauna differed from one region to another–for example,
between continents. What is apparent from Darwin’s reference is that he did not yet realize that such a tiny
portion of the globe as the Galápagos archipelago might actually be its own “centre of creation.”
Today, as a result of Darwin’s change of scientific heart, the Galápagos are widely recognized as a
classic laboratory of evolution in action, and hence (to use the pre-Darwinian terminology) as a unique
centre of creation in their own right. In significant part, the islands owe their biological celebrity to the
fact that they are geologically young–about 3 million years old, although a few former islands, now eroded
down by the ocean and submerged beneath the sea, date back as much as 17 million years (Christie et al.
1992; Werner and Hoernle 2003). Based on his own geological observations, Darwin correctly realized
that life in these distant islands had been given a new beginning. He later reflected on this conclusion in
his Journal of Researches:
Seeing every height crowned with its crater, and the boundaries of most of the lavastreams still distinct, we are led to believe that within a period geologically recent
the unbroken ocean was here spread out. Hence, both in space and time, we seem
to be brought somewhat near to that great fact–that mystery of mysteries–the first
appearance of new beings on this earth. (1845:377–378)
Certain unexpected facts about the Galápagos undermined the credibility of a creationist solution to
this “mystery of mysteries.” In particular, each island in the Galápagos group has evolved many of its own
distinct species over time, following the stocking of the islands by chance colonists who managed to arrive
there from the Central and South American mainland, almost 600 miles away. Darwin was first alerted
to this possibility by Nicholas Lawson, the vice-governor of the islands, whom Darwin encountered on
Charles Island. As he reported in his Journal of Researches, Lawson insisted that “the tortoises differed
from the different islands, and that he could with certainty tell from which island any one was brought”
(1845:394). Unfortunately, Darwin did not at first pay sufficient attention to the vice-governor’s testimony,
in part because of an error in the contemporary zoological literature. Like other naturalists, Darwin was
under the mistaken impression that the Galápagos tortoise, which was at that time classified under the
misleading scientific name Testudo indicus, was not native to the Galápagos but had been transported there
by buccaneers or ocean-going Polynesians, from islands in the Indian Ocean, where similar forms of giant
tortoise are found (Darwin 1839:465, 628; FitzRoy 1839:505). Only after Darwin’s return to England did
it become clear that these two taxa were separate species (Sulloway 1982b).
There was a second reason why Darwin initially overlooked the vice-governor’s remarks about the
tortoises. Creationist theory held that species can and do change in response to local environments.
Like an elastic band that resists being stretched, any discrepancies among varieties from the supposedly
immutable specific type were thought to be temporary deviations, maintained by unusual ecological
conditions. During his Galápagos visit, Darwin therefore appears to have concluded that possible islandto-island differences among the giant land tortoises were no more remarkable than if introduced goats
were also to differ from island to island in characteristics such as colour and size. These sorts of local
J. Biosci. 34(2), June 2009
Commentary
176
differences were readily interpretable as short-term perturbations somehow induced by transport to new
and demanding environments.
As a result of his creationist perspective on species and varieties, Darwin–astonishingly, from
our modern evolutionary viewpoint–failed to collect a single specimen of giant tortoise for scientific
purposes during his Galápagos stay. After he had left the Archipelago and was sailing to Tahiti, Darwin
had one last opportunity to rectify this collecting oversight. The Beagle had stocked 48 tortoises from
Chatham, the first of the four islands Darwin had visited. As they sailed across the Pacific, Darwin and
his fellow shipmates gradually ate their way through the evidence that was later, in the form of hearsay, to
revolutionize the history of science. The carapaces of these 48 tortoises, which could have been compared
with other specimens in European museums, were unfortunately all thrown overboard with the rest of the
Beagle’s garbage (Sulloway 2009).
This same creationist mindset helps to explain why Darwin at first failed to understand the most
famous Galápagos exemplar of evolution in action–namely, Darwin’s famous finches. Fourteen species of
finches have evolved in the Galápagos Islands from an ancestral form now known to be a close relative
of the Tiara group (grassquits), which is found in Central and South America (Petren et al. 1999). Over
the last 2 million years or so, this evolutionary process has resulted in such impressive adaptive radiation
into diverse ecological niches that some of these 14 Galápagos species are not particularly finchlike in
appearance. Although 4 of the 14 species feed primarily on seeds, as finches generally do, another 2 species
feed on the fruits, flesh, and flowers of cactus. Seven additional species are primarily insectivorous, and
one very remarkable species feeds almost exclusively on leaves (Lack 1947; Grant and Grant 2008). It is
not surprising, then, that Darwin was fooled by some of these finches into thinking they were not finches
at all but the species they had come to mimic through a process known as convergent evolution (Sulloway
1982a). In his specimen notebook, for example, he listed the warbler finch as a “Wren”–which is what
this bird, to an untrained eye, appears to be. Similarly, he listed the cactus finch, which has a long pointed
bill for getting at the fruits and flowers of the Opuntia cactus, as a member of the Icteridae, which is the
family of meadowlarks and orioles.
So confusing was the case of the Galápagos finches that Darwin did not grasp, at the time of their
collection, that all these birds were closely related or that the peculiarly large number of species in this
one avian group might result from their having evolved on different islands. He therefore made no effort
to label his ornithological collections by island, something he was later to regret when he finally surmised
the evolutionary origins of this peculiar group of birds (Sulloway 1982c). Nor did Darwin have the
opportunity to observe these finches in sufficient detail to realize that their beak sizes and shapes were
closely related to their diets, an important insight that the legend wrongly ascribes to him.
4.
Darwin’s conversion to evolution (1837)
Despite being armed with an inadequate theory during his Galápagos visit–a theory that served to
undermine his collecting methodology by causing him to believe that the Galápagos Islands were part of
a much larger centre of creation–Darwin was too good a naturalist not to notice that the four mockingbird
specimens he had collected, each from a different island, were either distinct varieties or species (figure 2).
Not being an expert in ornithology, Darwin was unsure just what to make of this anomaly, but he did
record localities for these four specimens. In July 1836, nine months after his Galápagos visit, Darwin
reflected on this unusual case of the mockingbirds and recalled as well what he had been told about the
tortoises:
When I see these Islands in sight of each other, & possessed of but a scanty stock of
animals, tenanted by these birds, but slightly differing in structure & filling the same
place in Nature, I must suspect they are only varieties. . . . If there is the slightest
foundation for these remarks the zoology of Archipelagoes–will be well worth
examining; for such facts would undermine the stability of Species. (1963 [1836]:262)
The key to interpreting this famous passage–which broaches the Darwinian revolution only to back
away from it–is the phrase “I must suspect they are only varieties,” a presumption that Darwin understood
to be fully consistent with creationist theory (Sulloway 2009). What kept Darwin from taking the crucial
step from scientific orthodoxy to heterodoxy at this point in the Beagle voyage was a lack of information
J. Biosci. 34(2), June 2009
Commentary
177
Figure 2. Darwin’s Galápagos mockingbird specimens (genus Nesomimus). From top to bottom, the birds
are arranged in the order Darwin collected them (on Chatham, Charles, Albemarle, and James). The first two
specimens (N. melanotis and N. trifasciatus) are considered separate species from the third and fourth specimens
(N. parvulus). The three species differ in bill length, eye colour, and plumage. (Courtesy of the Natural History
Museum, Tring.)
about proper ornithological classification, which would only become available to him back in England
through access to museum collections and especially the judgements of expert ornithologists, who were
much more familiar than Darwin was with the defining features of species and varieties, especially in the
particular Galápagos taxa he had collected. Faced with an absence of crucial information to resolve the
issue, Darwin continued to give a nod toward the prevailing creationist assumption that variation within
immutable species can lead to new varieties or subspecies that are adapted to local environments. Despite
any doubts Darwin may have entertained on this subject during the remainder of the Beagle voyage, this
scientific position was perhaps the most responsible one for him to have taken at that time.
Darwin returned to England on 2 October 1836. Three months later, he deposited his Beagle collections
of birds with John Gould, the ornithological expert at the London Zoological Society. Gould, who was
in the process of becoming famous for his beautifully illustrated monographs on birds of the world,
immediately realized the extraordinary nature of Darwin’s Galápagos specimens and described them first,
ahead of other birds from the Beagle voyage (Gould 1837a, b).
Darwin did not obtain a full report on Gould’s findings until early March 1837, when he moved
from Cambridge to London. After the two men had discussed these findings in detail, Darwin’s life and
scientific thinking were never the same. Gould informed Darwin that 3 of his 4 specimens of Galápagos
mockingbird were distinct species, new to science and different from all known mockingbirds. Gould
also informed Darwin that his collection included 13 or possibly 14 species of very unusual finches, all
so closely related that Gould had placed them in a single new group. As for the land birds as a whole, 25
of the 26 species were judged to be new to ornithology and unique to the Galápagos, something Darwin
could not have known without access to the museum collections and previously published descriptions
J. Biosci. 34(2), June 2009
Commentary
178
available to Gould. All of a sudden, following Gould’s taxonomic analyses, the Galápagos Islands had
become their own distinct “centre of creation.” Darwin now found himself directly confronted by the
problem of the origin of species in a way he had not been when he was visiting those islands.
Darwin appears to have been stunned by Gould’s conclusions. He quickly realized that if Gould was
right about the mockingbirds–and Darwin (1841:63–64) pressed him on this point to be certain–the
supposedly immutable barrier that exists between separate species had somehow been broken by these
birds, isolated on the different islands of the Galápagos group. Gradual evolution through geographic
isolation was the only plausible explanation, unless one believed that God, like an obsessive-compulsive
gardener, had gone from one island to the next in the Galápagos group whimsically creating separate but
closely allied species intended to fill the same ecological niches. As for the much more complex case
of the finches, once Gould had convinced Darwin that these birds were all closely related by analogy
with the simpler and more compelling case of the mockingbirds, Darwin was able to see the finches in a
radically new light (figure 3). As he later observed in his Journal of Researches: “Seeing this gradation
and diversity of structure in one small, intimately related group of birds, one might really fancy that from
an original paucity of birds in this archipelago, one species had been taken and modified for different
ends” (1845:380). Only now did he appreciate the extent of his previous oversight in failing to label the
bulk of his Galápagos birds by island. Such evidence, he realized, would help to account for why so many
different species of finches lived in this archipelago.
Fortunately, Darwin knew that three other collectors on the Beagle (Captain FitzRoy, FitzRoy’s
steward Harry Fuller, and Darwin’s own servant, Syms Covington) had also collected specimens in
the Galápagos. All of these specimens turned out to have been labelled by island; significantly, it was
the nonscientists on the Beagle, who were not as theory-driven as Darwin, who recorded the scientific
evidence that Darwin, based on a creationist approach, had considered superfluous. After his meeting
with Gould, Darwin diligently sought out this locality information, and he later used it to support his case
about the mockingbirds and tortoises, although the evidence was still uncomfortably tenuous (Sulloway
Figure 3. Four of the 14 species of Darwin’s Galápagos finches (Geospizinae), as illustrated in the second edition
of Darwin’s Journal of Researches (1845:379). Top left, the large ground finch; top right, the medium ground finch;
bottom left, the small tree finch; bottom right, the warbler finch, which is closest genetically to the common ancestor
of this avian group. (Woodcut by James Lee.)
J. Biosci. 34(2), June 2009
Commentary
179
1982c, 1984). Fortunately, additional sources of information over the next two decades, which were drawn
in part from reports about other oceanic archipelagos, would transform this suggestive evidence into
incontrovertible fact.
Jolted by the Galápagos results, and struck by similar evidence about geographic distribution that
began to emerge from taxonomic judgements about his South American collections, Darwin began a
search in the spring of 1837 for a mechanism that would explain not only evolutionary change but also the
most elusive puzzle about species–their highly adaptive nature. As he later recorded in a private journal:
“In July [1837] opened first note book on ‘Transmutation of Species’–Had been greatly struck from about
Month of previous March on character of S. American fossils–& species on Galapagos Archipelago.
These facts origin (especially latter) of all my views” (Darwin 1959:7).
Based on the evidence of the Galápagos mockingbirds, Darwin now understood that geographic
isolation was a crucial part of the answer to how species transform themselves over time (Sulloway 1979;
Mayr 1982). But isolation, although it could account for the origin and multiplication of new species
over time, was insufficient to explain the often remarkable adaptations that species manifest to local
environments. After exploring and rejecting a number of hypotheses about evolutionary change, Darwin
happened to read, in September 1838, the 1826 edition of Thomas Malthus’s Essay on the Principle of
Population. Malthus argued that populations have an inherent tendency to grow geometrically. Yet, in
nature, the food supply is limited, so most offspring do not survive, being killed by predators, famine, and
diseases. On reading Malthus’s book, Darwin immediately realized that in the ever-present struggle for
existence, slight variations of a beneficial nature would tend be naturally selected, leading to increased
survival and hence an increase in adaptive traits, just as the breeder of domesticated animals achieves
desired traits by selecting the qualities that are esteemed in these animals. “Here, then,” Darwin remarked
in his Autobiography, “I had at last got a theory by which to work” (1958 [1876]:120). Here also was a
credible answer to William Paley–one entailing a natural (as opposed to a supernatural) explanation of
adaptations. Natural selection, Darwin realized, was none other than Paley’s designer, an equivalence that
later sometimes led Darwin to personify this evolutionary process, as in this celebrated passage from the
Origin: “It may be said that natural selection is daily and hourly scrutinising, throughout the world, every
variation, even the slightest; rejecting that which is bad, preserving and adding up all that is good; silently
and insensibly working, whenever and wherever opportunity offers, at the improvement of each organic
being in relation to its organic and inorganic conditions of life” (1859:84).
5.
Intelligent design tested and refuted
Inspired by the striking evidence from the Galápagos Islands, and armed with his novel theory of natural
selection, Darwin began to reexamine the basic assumptions of creationism and to compare the predictions
one would make based on these two radically different theories. The more extensive his reexamination
became, the more he realized that the theory of intelligent design, which gave creationism its scientific
legitimacy, was overwhelmingly contradicted by the available evidence. Darwin’s reassessment reached
its culmination twenty-one years later in On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, a book
that Darwin himself aptly characterized toward the end as “one long argument” (1859:459). It was as
much an argument against creationism, and especially against the validity of intelligent design, as it was
an argument for evolution, as Mayr (1991) has emphasized. Although Paley is mentioned only once in the
Origin, his specter is everywhere apparent in Darwin’s repeated discussions highlighting the lack of truly
intelligent design in nature. Indeed, Darwin’s “one long argument” was in many ways a direct response to
“the long line of argumentation” by which Paley had charmed young Darwin as a Cambridge University
undergraduate (1958 [1876]:59).
Not surprisingly, the evidence about geographical distribution, particularly about oceanic islands and
their biological relationships with the nearest continents, plays a substantial role in Darwin’s argument.
The numerous problems that such islands raised for creationism had been surprisingly overlooked prior to
Darwin’s discussions of the subject, and this powerful class of evidence was the only topic to which Darwin
devoted two whole chapters in the Origin. The Galápagos, for example, are home to various species of
animals and plants closely allied to those from the neighbouring American continent, yet the environmental
features of these islands do not at all resemble those of the nearest parts of the continent, which are tropical.
J. Biosci. 34(2), June 2009
Commentary
180
By contrast, the harsh volcanic environment of the Galápagos does closely resemble that of the Cape Verde
Islands, 400 miles west of Africa. Yet the Cape Verdean flora and fauna are most strongly allied to species
living on the African mainland, not to those in the Galápagos. Why would a Designer, Darwin asked, place
two completely different creative stamps–one African and one American–on species that live in nearly
identical environments and fill similar ecological niches? Creationist theory, he argued, ought to predict that
such island species would either be identical or closely allied, based on the similar environments to which
they are supposedly adapted by intelligent design. But the true circumstances are “utterly inexplicable on
the ordinary view of independent creation of each species” (1859:406). By contrast, anyone who accepts
the theory of evolution would expect precisely this sort of evidence.
Elsewhere in the Origin, Darwin generalized this argument about oceanic islands, which he described
as having “the widest application throughout nature” (1859:403). One of the additional examples he
offered was alpine species, which are almost always more closely related to nearby lowland forms than
to alpine forms found in other parts of the world. Similarly, the same kind of geographic relationship was
generally observed among so-called relict populations on continents, such as the blind organisms (rodents,
reptiles, insects, crustaceans, and fish) that live within deep caverns. Few environments, Darwin argued,
are more similar than the habitats characterizing cavern systems, because these systems are insulated
from major changes in temperature, humidity, and the seasons. Yet blind cave animals, which often have
rudimentary eyes that serve no purpose, are not most closely allied to other blind cave animals living in
different parts of the world. Instead, these organisms closely resemble the surface-dwelling organisms on
each of the continents where the caverns are found and from which their denizens have been derived by
descent with modification (Darwin 1859:138, 404). In short, such facts about relict populations do not
admit of a rational explanation in terms of the theories of independent creation and intelligent design. Such
facts do, however, agree with expectations derived from evolutionary theory.
Islands like the Galápagos focused Darwin’s attention on another class of facts inimical to the theory of
intelligent design. Remote oceanic islands have very skewed floral and faunal distributions. Absent from
such island populations are large terrestrial mammals as well as amphibians (frogs, toads, and newts).
Yet bats, which can reach oceanic islands by flight, are regularly found to inhabit the islands of every
major ocean. The physical conditions of such islands, Darwin maintained, do not explain the absence
of amphibians and large terrestrial mammals, for when such animals have been introduced to oceanic
islands–and Darwin presented relevant evidence in the Origin from numerous island localities–they have
generally flourished “so as to become a nuisance” (1859:393). Although creationism and intelligent design
supplied no explanation of such facts, this evidence was perfectly consistent with colonization by accidental
transport. As Darwin noted, amphibians and their eggs are easily killed by immersion in salt water. By
contrast, reptiles, which are often found on remote islands, are much better able to survive extraordinary
ocean journeys.
The ease with which exotic animals and plants, brought by occasional visitors and colonists, have
become naturalized on remote islands provided Darwin with another example of a fundamental weakness
in design theory. Almost everywhere that animals and plants have been introduced to oceanic islands,
the introduced forms have largely exterminated the native forms. When Darwin visited the Galápagos
in 1835, this pernicious process had just begun, so he could refer to the looming problem there only
in general terms. Commenting on the extreme tameness of the birds and animals in these islands–a
disposition that allowed them to be easily killed by the colonists for food or sport–Darwin remarked,
“What havoc the introduction of any new beast of prey must cause in a country, before the instincts of the
indigenous inhabitants have become adapted to the stranger’s craft or power” (1845:401). In support of
this Galápagos observation, Darwin drew in the Origin on cases of oceanic islands that had been colonized
much earlier. Of New Zealand he noted that the endemic organisms were “now rapidly yielding before the
advancing legions of plants and animals introduced from Europe,” and the original and highly endemic
flora of Ascension Island, he reported, was all but extinct (1859:201).
Had the native animals and plants on those islands been specially designed by God for residing there,
surely they ought to have prevailed over introduced organisms, which were presumably designed to live
elsewhere. In contrast, evidence showing the consistent superiority of introduced forms was fully in
accord, Darwin argued, with the theory of evolution by natural selection, because natural selection acts
only on organisms as they compete with one another within local communities. Hence this evolutionary
J. Biosci. 34(2), June 2009
Commentary
181
process “will produce perfection, or strength in the battle for life, only according to the standard of that
country.” Remote islands, which typically have a meager collection of denizens compared with mainland
ecological communities, have generally experienced less intense selection over time, and their residents
“often yield, as we see they do yield, to the inhabitants of another and generally larger country” (1859:
205).
Once Darwin began to catalog instances of imperfect design in nature, more and more examples came
to his attention through the revealing lens of evolutionary theory. In the Origin he provided scores of
additional examples, drawn from biological domains such as morphology, classification, and embryology.
The ultimate message in his relentless critique was simple: Any theory of the origin of species had to
account not only for adaptations but also for their frequent imperfections. The main problem with the
creationist doctrine was the copious evidence of poor design. To account for such evidence, Paley and
his predecessors had to assume that their presumed Watchmaker was somehow lacking in foresight and
sometimes just plain derelict or even malicious. Darwin, of course, was careful not to push that argument
too far, lest he offend his more theologically-minded readers. But he did allude more than once in the
Origin to the dark side of intelligent-design doctrine; for instance, he noted that it seemed preferable
to explain the behaviour of baby cuckoos ejecting their foster siblings from the nest, or parasitic wasps
injecting their eggs into caterpillars (which are then devoured alive by the larvae) as “small consequences
of one general law, leading to the advancement of all organic beings” rather than as the outcome of
“specially endowed or created instincts” (1859:244). Privately he was more forthcoming. To botanist
Joseph Hooker he wrote in 1856, “What a book a Devil’s Chaplain might write on the clumsy, wasteful,
blundering low & horridly cruel works of nature!” (1990:178).
6.
Darwin’s use of the hypothetico-deductive method
Ultimately, what Darwin’s transformation from creationist to evolutionist reveals about him, and about
science more generally, is that the best science is conducted in the service of a really good theory.
Darwin’s own scientific methodology was remarkably modern for a period when Baconian induction–
supposedly letting the facts speak for themselves–was the predominant scientific philosophy. Although
Darwin sometimes implied that he was a Baconian scientist in his methods (doubtless to assure people
of his efforts to be unbiased) he was anything but a Baconian in practice; throughout his long career he
employed what is known as the hypothetico-deductive method, by which hypotheses are used to generate
predictions and to guide the collection of relevant evidence–information that is then used either to confirm
or reject the hypotheses (Ghiselin 1969).
During the Beagle voyage, Darwin was guided by creationist theory. As a result of his fateful Galápagos
visit and certain other voyage experiences, he discovered that this theory led to false expectations–and
also encouraged, as one unfortunate consequence, inappropriate collecting methods. The deeper Darwin
probed, the more he realized that creationist theory was abundantly contradicted by the available
biological and paleontological evidence. So he rejected this theory and eventually developed a better one,
the theory of evolution by natural selection. He then turned this new theory on the same set of phenomena
he had once sought to explain by means of creationism and its explanatory handmaiden, intelligent design.
Patiently, over the next two decades, Darwin sifted through scientific journals, old tomes about voyages of
exploration, gardeners’ magazines, and numerous other sources of scientific data, and he also continually
prodded his colleagues for pertinent facts–all in a search for evidence that could be used to test his theory
against the creationist doctrines he had imbibed prior to the Beagle voyage (figure 4).
In 1859 Darwin’s revolutionary argument was startling to many, and it provoked enormous controversy
on publication (Glick 1972). But it eventually carried the day, as Darwin’s scientific contemporaries,
following in Darwin’s intellectual footsteps, addressed the many problematic theoretical issues,
highlighted by abundant empirical evidence, that he had raised in the Origin. In doing so, most of them
came to realize, just as Darwin had previously done, that intelligent design fails to explain anything that
cannot be fully explained by natural selection–and far more damningly–that whatever this theory does
claim to explain, it explains badly or not at all.
In current debates about intelligent design, it is often asserted that this theory is unscientific because
it is untestable. The real problem with this doctrine, however, is that numerous straightforward tests have
J. Biosci. 34(2), June 2009
Commentary
182
Figure 4. Darwin (ca. 1854), as he was beginning to write the Origin of Species (from Seward 1909: Frontispiece).
Darwin’s understanding of the hypothetico-deductive method is exemplified by a remark he made to economist Henry
Fawcett in 1861: “About thirty years ago there was much talk that geologists ought only to observe and not theorise;
and I well remember some one say that at this rate a man might as well go into a gravel-pit and count the pebbles and
describe all the colours. How odd it is that anyone should not see that all observation must be for or against some view
if it is to be of any service!” (Darwin 1903, 1:195).
overwhelmingly failed to support it. In lucid and cogent prose, Darwin’s “one long argument” in the
Origin of Species tells us not only why he was personally compelled to reject intelligent design but also
why any well-informed person ought to reject it.
Acknowledgements
This article is a revised and expanded version of an essay first published by Vintage Books in Intelligent
Thought (Sulloway 2006), edited by John Brockman.
References
Browne E J 1995 Charles Darwin: Voyaging (New York: Alfred A Knopf)
Christie D M, Duncan R A, McBirney A R, Richards M A, White W M, Harpp K S, and Fox C G 1992 Drowned
islands downstream from the Galapagos hotspot imply extended speciation times; Nature (London) 355 246–248
Crimmins J E 2004 William Paley; Oxford Dictionary of National Biography 42 445–451
Darwin C R 1839 Journal of researches into the geology and natural history of the various countries visited by H.M.S.
Beagle, under the command of Captain FitzRoy, R.N. from 1832 to 1836 (London: Henry Colburn)
Darwin C R (ed.) 1841 The zoology of the voyage of H.M.S. Beagle, under the command of Captain FitzRoy, R.N.,
during the years 1832–1836. Part III: Birds (London: Smith, Elder)
Darwin C R 1845 Journal of researches into the natural history and geology of the various countries visited during
the voyage of H.M.S. Beagle round the world, under the command of Capt. Fitz Roy, R.N. (2nd edition) (London:
John Murray)
Darwin C R 1859 On the origin of species by means of natural selection, or the preservation of favoured races in the
struggle for life (London: John Murray)
Darwin C R 1887 The life and letters of Charles Darwin (3 vols) (ed.) F Darwin (London: John Murray)
Darwin C R 1903 More Letters of Charles Darwin (2 vols) (eds) F Darwin and A C Seward (New York: D Appleton
and Company)
J. Biosci. 34(2), June 2009
Commentary
183
Darwin C R 1958 [1876] The Autobiography of Charles Darwin, 1809-1882 (New York: W W Norton)
Darwin C R 1959 Darwin’s journal (ed.) G de Beer; Bull. Brit. Mus. (Nat. Hist.) Hist. Ser. 2 (1)
Darwin C R 1963 [1836] Darwin’s ornithological notes (ed.) N Barlow; Bull. Brit. Mus. (Nat. Hist.) Hist. Ser. 2 (7)
Darwin C R 1988 Charles Darwin’s Diary (ed.) R D Keynes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
Darwin C R 1990 The correspondence of Charles Darwin: volume 6: 1856–1857 (eds) F Burkhardt and S Smith
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
Darwin C R 1991 The correspondence of Charles Darwin: volume 7: 1858–1859 (eds) F Burkhardt and S Smith
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
FitzRoy R 1839 Narrative of the surveying voyage of His Majesty’s ships Adventure and Beagle between the years
1826-1836, describing their examination of the southern shore of South America, and Beagle’s circumnavigation
of the Globe. In three volumes (Vol. 2) (London: Henry Colburn)
Ghiselin M T 1969 The triumph of the Darwinian method (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California
Press)
Glick T (ed.) 1972 The comparative reception of Darwinism (Austin: University of Texas Press)
Gould J 1837a Remarks on a group of ground finches from Mr. Darwin’s collection; Proc. Zool. Soc. London 5 4–7
Gould J 1837b Three species of the genus Orpheus, from the Galapagos, in the collection of Mr. Darwin; Proc. Zool.
Soc. London 5 27
Grant P R and Grant B R 2008 How and why species multiply: The radiation of Darwin’s finches (Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press)
Lack, D 1947 Darwin’s finches (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
Malthus T R 1826 An essay on the principle of population; or, A view of its past and present effects on human
happiness; with an inquiry into our prospects respecting the future removal or mitigation of the evils which it
occasions (3 vols) (6th edition) (London: John Murray)
Mayr E 1982 The growth of biological thought: Diversity, evolution, and inheritance (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press)
Mayr E 1991 One long argument: Charles Darwin and the genesis of modern evolutionary thought (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press)
Paley W 1785 The principles of moral and political philosophy (London: R Faulder)
Paley W 1794 A view of the evidences of Christianity (London: R Faulder)
Paley W 1802 Natural theology; or, Evidences of the existence and attributes of the Deity, collected from the
appearances of nature (London: R Faulder)
Paley W 1860 The works of William Paley, D. D. (London: T Nelson and Sons)
Petren K, Grant B R and Grant P R 1999 A phylogeny of Darwin’s finches based on microsatellite DNA length
variation; Proc. R. Soc. London B 266 321–329
Ray J 1691 The wisdom of God manifested in the works of creation (London: Samuel Smith)
Seward A C (ed.) 1909 Darwin and modern science (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
Sulloway F J 1979 Geographic isolation in Darwin’s thinking: The vicissitudes of a crucial idea; Stud. Hist. Biol. 3
23–65
Sulloway F J 1982a Darwin and his finches: The evolution of a legend; J. Hist. Biol. 15 1–53
Sulloway F J 1982b Darwin’s conversion: The Beagle voyage and its aftermath; J. Hist. Biol. 15 325–396
Sulloway F J 1982c The Beagle collections of Darwin’s finches (Geospizinae); Bull. Brit. Mus. (Nat. Hist.) Zool. Ser.
43 No. 2
Sulloway F J 1984 Darwin and the Galapagos; Biol. J. Linn. Soc. 21 29–59
Sulloway F J 2006 Why Darwin rejected intelligent design; in: Intelligent thought: Science versus the intelligent
design movement (ed.) J Brockman (New York: Vintage) pp 107–126
Sulloway F J 2009 Tantalizing tortoises and the Darwin-Galápagos legend; J. Hist. Biol. 42 3–31
Werner R and Hoernle K 2003 New volcanological and volatile data provide strong support for the continuous
existence of Galápagos Islands over the past 17 million years; Int. J. Earth Sci. 92 904–911
FRANK J SULLOWAY
Institute of Personality and Social Research,
4125 Tolman Hall, University of California,
Berkeley, CA 94720-5050, USA
(Email, [email protected])
ePublication:20 May 2009
J. Biosci. 34(2), June 2009