* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Contemporary Civilization and Women
Raunch aesthetics wikipedia , lookup
Feminist Theory: From Margin to Center wikipedia , lookup
Women in ancient Egypt wikipedia , lookup
Second-wave feminism wikipedia , lookup
Socialist feminism wikipedia , lookup
First-wave feminism wikipedia , lookup
Feminist theology wikipedia , lookup
Feminism (international relations) wikipedia , lookup
Feminist movement wikipedia , lookup
Gender roles in Islam wikipedia , lookup
New feminism wikipedia , lookup
Attributed To: Contemporary Civilization Instructor Staff Date: Electronic Version, August 1998 Contemporary Civilization and Women: Plato, Aristotle, Livy and Machiavelli Plato and Aristotle: As Susan Moller Okin notes in her book, Women in Western Political Thought (Princeton University Press, 1979), till very recently social and political thought has been written for men, about men, and by men. One of the reasons for this, Okin argues, is that this tradition of thought is flawed at its very roots by assumptions concerning the naturalness of hierarchy and inequality -- between classes, races and nations) but also between the two sexes. Both Plato and Aristotle formulated arguments that have had powerful and enduring consequences. So there are a number of ways in which the utility of examining Plato’s Republic and Aristotle’s Politics can be justified in terms of the current debate concerning feminism and the ‘nature’ and ‘proper place’ of women. Firstly as Okin does most directly, we can see the philosophical roots of both the de jure and de facto subordination of women in Western society. And furthermore, we can understand why, when women’s de jure position has been formally equalized with that of men, the de facto situation of subordination and inequality largely remains. That is to say woman as household manager and bearer/raiser of children has relegated her to the private, familial sphere, and to virtues and a nature appropriate to this role and function. Secondly, and a corollary of the first, an examination of Plato’s and Aristotle’s thought injects us into the mainstream of the fundamental debate about nature and convention. Here, the debate over the naturalness as against the historically (conventionally) of the family, and thus the proper sphere of women: (public or private?), is central to the thought of both Plato and Aristotle. Thirdly, one can come to appreciate the extent to which sexist attitudes have been constantly reproduced by reputable scholars --sometimes even importing a more intense sexism into their interpretations of thinkers (like Plato) than is in fact there. Here I am thinking particularly of Strauss’ and Bloom’s deformations of Plato. Fourthly, and most generally. attention to the portrayal of women in the tradition of Western socio-political thought can fundamentally transform the way we see not only that tradition, but also Western history itself. Plato's Republic (It may be useful to note that Plato’s ideas do not just come bolting out of the blue, and that by the 4th. C. BCE the status of women was a live issue in Greek politics and thought). The first mention of women in the guardian class is made in Book IV 423e/424a. Socrates’ friends remind him of this in Book V 449c and press him on the necessity to elaborate this proposal. This discussion continues till 466e. Along the way, even in Book V, there are some paradoxes to resolve, e.g. at 469d where stripping a corpse slain in battle is described as "womanish and small-minded". Such comments can -– though need not necessarily nor convincingly -- be resolved by treating them as references to the way women were in contemporary Athenian society -- subordinate (and distorted and stunted)--and have no necessary bearing on their potential, or intrinsic nature; or as merely literary devices, a matter of the quasi- ‘novelistic’ structure. References to women in the Republic other than in Book V which are less than flattering to women/femaleness, can be found at 387d/e; 388; 395d; 398e; 431c; 579b/c; 557a-c; 563b; There is one major affirmation of the presence of women in the guardian class outside of Book V to balance the above disparaging passages at 540 c/d, which stresses the difficulty of such a proposal, but that it is "somehow possible". There have been various approaches to Plato that have been taken on this issue: 1.Plato is making absurd proposals just to show in fact that the ideal city à la Republic is impossibly utopian (Bloom, Strauss) 2.Plato’s logic and philosophy here suffer "lapses." (Cornford) 3.Plato fully shared the misogynistic tradition of classical Greece but the nature and momentum of his argument in the Republic in re communal property and wives, and the abolition of the family, both enabled and forced him to make a step forward concerning women--but which remained consistent in general terms with the ‘misogynistic tradition’: i.e. Plato gives women ‘equal opportunity’, even though they are usually inferior to men. (Okin) 4."It is quite wrong to think of Plato as ‘the first feminist his arguments are unacceptable...and the proposals made in Republic Book V are irrelevant to the contemporary debate." Julia Annas ‘Plato’s Republic arid Feminism’ Philosophy 51 1976 (p.307) 5."The feminism of Plato is exemplary and unparalleled in philosophy or political theory." A. Rosenthal Monist ‘Feminism Without Contradictions’ 1973 The Bloom/Strauss interpretation seems basically to be one to save Plato from the common charge of making utopian, impractical, irrational, or, more usually, unnatural proposals here. Given the obvious defensiveness of Plato, it is easy to see how Strauss and Bloom came up with their thesis--which yet betrays a sexism greater than Plato’s! See Okin’s critique, esp. pp. 40, 305-8; also Christine Pierce ‘Equality: Republic V’ Monist vol. 57, No. 1 Jan. 1973. Essentially, to accept Bloom’s and Strauss’ overly gymnastic arguments you have to see Plato as saying one thing but really meaning something quite different. The problem with this is that Plato is continually having Socrates stress how his ideas may seem new and strange, but that they indeed possible to implement. It seems to me that Okin and Pierce effectively impugn the Bloom/Strauss thesis that Plato has merely contrived an elaborate and subtle joke in the Republic. It is concluded that Plato is serious and sincere in his proposals. But what is the true nature of these proposals? Here Annas’ article is useful. She ridicules the idea of Plato as a feminist, while conceding that he made some important steps forward in this respect. She stresses how Plato’s argument for allowing women into the guardian class is cast entirely in utilitarian terms, and that Plato has no conception of rights; nor is he concerned with the happiness or fulfillment of women, or that liberating them from the (stifling) confines of the conventional Athenian role can be a sufficient motive here.(Of course, it is not surprising that Plato doesn’t talk of Women’s rights, because he doesn't have a theory of rights at all--he doesn’t talk of men’s rights either). Annas notes, too, amongst other points repeated by Okin that outside of the guardian class, Plato leaves women in their traditional subordination (and household/procreative roles) even in his ideal state. Annas’ conclusion is that: "Mill begins the subjection of women with the statement that the subordination of one sex to the other is wrong in itself. It seems...[to me] that to be a feminist one has to begin from this point. But it is a point that Plato never reaches. And it is not surprising that he never reaches it, for he is not going in that direction at all." Okin’s treatment of Plato (and Aristotle) and women is the fullest we have: she argues, in effect, that Plato could have been a feminist if only he had followed his own fundamental, general principles through to their logical conclusions. That is to say, Plato does not follow his own admonitions in his discussions of women: his warning that superficial appearances often don’t indicate the essence of something; and that to discover the nature of something we have to disentangle the impact of environment from nature. According to 0kin, the important point is that Plato accorded greater weight to education and the environment over innate qualities. Given Plato’s priority on nurture, why does he not then argue that) due to the injustices etc. of contemporary Athenian society, no one knows what the essential nature of women really is. This clearly is the logical implication of Plato’s general argument in re the impact of education and environment i.e. Plato does not employ his ‘environmentalist’ argument to win over his skeptical audience. Why is this? Okin’s cake-and-eat-it-too thesis. Plato can (a) retain the misogynistic tradition (b) yet still admit women to the guardian class on the basis of equal opportunity (c) retain the sympathies of his audience -- concede something to deeply-felt traditional attitudes so he could avoid being dismissed as a completely ridiculous crank. More importantly,(d) the power and momentum of his communistic argument carry him to a conclusion that he had not foreseen and which he is somewhat uncomfortable with. 0kin adduces support for this view from: (1) the inconsistencies and paradoxes of Plato’s thought here, and (2) the general context of classical Greece’s patriarchal, elitist and misogynistic culture. It should be noted, nevertheless, that according to Okin, Plato is distinctive in the classical tradition in that he applied a single standard of human morality and excellence to all, regardless of their role and position in society (Okin, p. 66) And here 0kin is prepared to say that the "importance" of Plato’s passages in the Republic on arete and the irrelevance of gender to it(to an extent "in the gradual universalizing of ethical values must not be underestimated." Aristotle’s Politics To Aristotle, women are not merely conventionally --factually, actually -- deprived of the highest good. but also constitutionally--naturally, by their very make-up, intrinsically-unfitted for and incapable of that good. They are the "monstrous regiment... [of] infertile males." Book I and the opening pages of Book II have much that is directly relevant to this issue. Aristotle’s examination of various associations and their internal authority structures has him employing the central-idea of a compound and the naturalness of its division into ruling and ruled elements for the benefit of both. Throughout, Aristotle is committed to the idea of the naturalness of the family -- unlike Plato who regarded it as merely an institution existing by convention and the abolition of which both freed and forced him to open up the guardian class to women. It is vital to note here, then, the crucial linkage between the idea of the naturalness of the family and women’s subordination to men, the assumption of their intrinsic (incorrigible) inferiority, and their relegation to the private and familial sphere. Aristotle describes the husband’s rule over his wife as "that of a statesman over fellow citizens", which he distinguishes from the father’s relationship to his children which is more like that of a "monarch over subjects". Aristotle continues: "The male is naturally fitter to command than the female, except where there is some departure from nature." etc. Such views are subsumed within Aristotle’s well-known views on the variegated, functional nature of goodness. and the naturalness of the hierarchy based on ruling and ruled elements as a "general law"(I, Ch. XIII #6). See also 1277b #16-18, 1278b #7 from Bk. II. In Book II Aristotle focuses on rejecting Plato’s proposals in the Republic -- natural enough given the arguments and conclusions he had reached in Book I. Aristotle is not always accurate or fair in his criticisms of Plato here. Okin stresses that Aristotle’s counter-arguments are weak, and thus that their significance lies in the fact that Aristotle finds them sufficient , and thence he is able to conclude that the private household and family is the natural and necessary base for social life. Like Plato, Aristotle assumes that once this is settled, so is woman’s natural/required place and role. Hence, he feels it unnecessary (and doesn't) to address the issue of equal education and opportunities for women of Plato’s Book V. It is essential to note too that Aristotle is firmly within the classical Greek tradition of a variable application of terms and standards. People are capable of a goodness and excellence consonant with their natures. And, in particular, women are not capable of the highest arete was entirely masculine, noble and leisured). This was the powerful tradition that Plato(via Socrates) was challenging in the Republic. It is the tradition which Aristotle fully accepts. See also 1269b #5-13; 1270a #11; 1278b #7; Thereafter, direct references to women are few and far between till Book V, Ch. XI 1313b #7; 1314b #23 Book VI, Ch. IV 1319b; See also Aristotle’s discussion of marriage, procreation and the foetus: Book VII, Ch. XVI. esp. 1335a #6, #8 Okin writes in some detail about the difference in temper between Aristotle -and Plato: the latter critical, questioning, capable of quite radical proposals, the former seeking to find out how the world is and why, and tending to see what is as what must be and could only be. This attitudes pervades all of Aristotle’s thought--natural ethical, political. Aristotle’s assumptions and inclinations are conservative and function not merely to explain but also to justify the status quo(Okin pp. 73-4, 80-i). Why? 0kin sees Aristotle as pushing an essentially functionalist argument: if something exists it must have a purpose, if it continues to exist it must be performing its proper function. The guiding conviction and assumption of Aristotle that leads to all his subsequent reasoning here is that the good life is attainable only by a small minority of one sex. Why? One needs the requisite intrinsic capacity and sufficient possessions to enable leisure and the cultivation of reason: i.e. riches, friends, leisure, noble birth etc. This elitism is defined not merely in terms of gender but class(artisans etc) and nature independent of gender(slaves). Okin is useful also for the context and tradition in which Aristotle’s thought is imbedded and for some of his important and revealing ideas in sources other than the Politics. Okin concludes with her fundamental point: the circularity of Aristotle’s reasoning "proving" the inferiority of women. He begins from the initial assumption that the free, leisured male is the top of the human scale and all other humans are defined by their function in relation to him. These hierarchical, patriarchal, and functionalist assumptions then lead ipso facto to proving what he wanted to prove ab_initio. What Okin sees Aristotle doing is (ahistorically) arguing the naturalness of the Athenian socio-political structure and the familial basis it rested on --and thus concluding the natural inferiority of women. Okin’s fundamental theses The conception of women formulated by Aristotle and Plato derives from their conceptions of the woman’s relationship to the family. If the family is regarded as natural or necessary they define woman according to her sexual, procreative, child-rearing and household functions. This produces a code of morality and a conception of ‘rights’ distinctly different from that prescribed for men. Biological differences via the naturalness or necessity of the family produce and legitimate conventional and institutional differences according to gender. (See Barber’s review of Okin’s book attached). See also William J. Booth’s ‘Politics and the Household: A Commentary on Aristotle’s Politics Book One’ History of Political, Vol. II No. 2 Summer June 1981. Booth explains at length how Aristotle’s conception of the naturalness of the family and of the authority structures within--which involves the natural, permanent condition of slavery the natural, permanent condition of being ruled for the wife and daughters; the natural, temporary condition of being ruled for the male children -- is crucial for his reaching a solution to the political problem: who should have authority, and why. SOME ADDITIONAL NOTES ON PLATO, ARISTOTLE,AND WOMEN It should now be clear that a substantial historiographical debate emerged, especially in the seventies, as to (a) whether Republic V reveals Plato as a precocious feminist,and/or (b) the nature and extent of this alleged feminism. While this historiography varies in tone and intent, it largely falls within the ‘Greeks as misogynists’ approach, with Plato as the best of a less than desirable bunch-- Arlene Saxonhouse’s articles are interesting exceptions here. The following articles continue the debate: Brian Calvert ‘Plato and the Equality of Women’ Phoenix 28-29 1974-75 An article of general usefulness, more immediately accessible than some, which concentrates on Republic V. .Rejects the Grote, Barker, Bloom claim that Plato envisages even the best women as inevitably inferior to the best men, since Calvert argues this would make the inclusion of women in the guardian class as logically contradictory to Plato’s own definition of justice. Calvert concedes that Plato says that men as a class are superior to women but he understands Plato as also arguing that some women are as worthy as the best men, and hence deserve inclusion in the guardian class. Though rescuing Plato from the charge of inconsistency here, Calvert nevertheless concludes that, overall, Plato is inconsistent, hesitant, and vacillating in his attitudes toward women, and that his reasoning suffers "backsliding" and lapses": Plato cannot fully break away from his chauvinist society: novel and traditional views are intertwined, eg. women can be guardians, but they are owned as communal property by the male guardians (see the debate on this point between Pomeroy and Fortenbaugh, reference below). In his overall thesis Calvert is, I think, somewhat vulnerable. Dorothea Wender ‘Plato: Misogynist, Paedophile, and Feminist’ Arethusa vol. 6, (1973)1. Witty, even cheeky, speculative. Plato as the "woman-hater who championed women", and yet was "extraordinarily full of the tension of ambivalence". Wender’s thesis centres directly on Plato’s homosexuality: Since he disliked women he was not averse to schemes to change them; and he was not particularly afraid of them, since they couldn’t use their sexuality against him. Plato, as a homosexual, was temperamentally subversive (!) hence the congeniality to him of revolutionary proposals in-re Women. Thus, Wender sees Plato as a feminist because he was a misogynist. Wender develops this argument rather sketchily. S.B. Pomeroy ‘Feminism in Book V of Plato’s Republic’ Apeiron VIII (1974) No. 1 W. Fortenbaugh ‘On Plato’s Feminism in Republic V’ Apeiron IX: (1975) No. 2 In two very brief articles, Pomeroy claims, and Fortenbaugh rejects. that women guardians are owned as communal property by the men guardians. If Pomeroy is correct-and this can only by judged by those with the appropriate language skills--this would threaten Okin’s thesis of the connection between private property, monogamous marriage, and the inferior status of women.