* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download How Important is Character in Ethics paper
Cosmopolitanism wikipedia , lookup
Individualism wikipedia , lookup
Business ethics wikipedia , lookup
Happiness economics wikipedia , lookup
Secular morality wikipedia , lookup
Critique of Practical Reason wikipedia , lookup
Potentiality and actuality wikipedia , lookup
Contentment wikipedia , lookup
Neeti Sastra wikipedia , lookup
De (Chinese) wikipedia , lookup
Hedonic treadmill wikipedia , lookup
Alasdair MacIntyre wikipedia , lookup
Consequentialism wikipedia , lookup
Utilitarianism wikipedia , lookup
Thomas Hill Green wikipedia , lookup
Moral responsibility wikipedia , lookup
Ethics in religion wikipedia , lookup
Help Received: Writing Center, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Illustrated Readings How Important is Character in Ethics? By: Cadet Andrew Smith ERH-207W-02 Mr. Morgan December 10, 2015 Word Count: 1433 Do you believe yourself to be an ethical individual? What, do you think, are the most important components of ethics and being an ethical person? Is character one of those important components? These questions are extremely important for you to answer in your own mind and then to keep at the forefront of your thought process throughout the argument of this paper. This paper will answer the question of whether or not character is important to ethics and present differing views on the topic to give voice to all relevant arguments. After having presented the arguments, this paper will try to convince the logical audience that truly ethical decisions are impossible to make without good character. This paper will use terms in the argument that, while common to society, are sometimes defined differently from that of a philosophy stand point and therefore must be correctly defined before moving on. The first of the words to be defined is Character: character is defined as a distinctive mark used to distinguish one item from another or a group of qualities that distinguish one individual from another (Homiak). The second word is Virtue: virtue is defined as moral character. The third word is Disposition: disposition is defined as a character trait with which the character of a person is built. Fourth is the word Faculty: faculty can be defined as an aptitude or talent for doing something. Next is the word Ethics: ethics is concerned with distinguishing between good and evil in the world, between right and wrong human actions, and between virtuous and nonvirtuous characteristics of people. Finally, the word Vice: vice can be defined as an immoral or wicked personal characteristic; the opposite of a virtue. 2 In Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics Book II, he states that there are two types of virtue: moral and intellectual. Intellectual virtues are taught to us throughout our lives with no real action required while moral virtues are learned through practice and repetitive action on our part. Every human is born capable of being morally virtuous but we must continuously train ourselves to behave in a virtuous manner. We cannot learn to be virtuous by thought alone; we must practice (Nicomachean Ethics). Since every human and situation is different, there are no set guidelines with which to gauge whether or not a person is virtuous. However, Aristotle states that good character can be identified as being the mean between two extremes. The two extremes to any virtue are deficiency or excess of that virtue. For example, courage is a virtue but the extremes would be cowardice and rashness. There are a few actions which are never virtuous. As I said before, virtues do not have specific guidelines and situations vary greatly but so does the acceptable level of that virtue from one person to another. An example of this would be the courage that is acceptable for a child and the courage acceptable for a full grown adult. The child is still maturing and learning while the adult is expected to be more developed. One of the biggest obstacles to overcome in order to be a morally virtuous individual is how to act when faced with pleasure and pain. Aristotle believes that there are both inappropriate pleasures and pains. For example, an alcoholic feels inappropriate pleasure when he drinks and becomes drunk and feels inappropriate pain when he is unable to drink. A more virtuous and temperate person would feel appropriate pleasure abstaining from alcohol or drinking in moderation. Since there are no concrete rules to govern conduct, Aristotle offers three principles to identify a person with morally virtuous character as opposed to those who appear virtuous by accident: first, a virtuous 3 person is aware that he is behaving in a virtuous manner; second, he behaves in a virtuous manner for the simple reason that it is virtuous; third, this continues virtuous behavior evolves into a constant, virtuous disposition. Virtue is not a feeling or a faculty but a disposition. Feelings influence us to act in a certain way while our faculties dictate our ability to feel. Virtue is a more permanent action; therefore virtue disposes us to act in a good way. Through this logical succession, Aristotle came to the conclusion that virtue was a disposition that compelled us to consistently behave in an acceptable way; a mean between the two extremes. In some cases, and depending on the person, the mean is closer to one extreme than to the other. For example, courage is closer to the excess of rashness than to the deficiency of cowardice. This is because humans tend to have more of a problem with cowardice than rashness and courage is more closely aligned with rashness than cowardice. There are many virtues that have either a deficiency or an excess that we as individuals are more prone to gravitate to. This thought leads to Aristotle’s three rules of conduct: first, avoid the extreme that is farthest from the mean; second, notice what areas we are particularly susceptible to and avoid them diligently; and third, be wary of pleasure, as it often impedes our judgment. Aristotle’s believes that virtues are dispositions and fundamental in understanding how humans behave. Someone who has been taught to act a certain way all of their lives does not simply change because we give them a reason to. People are imprinted with behaviors that become their character early in their childhood. Now that I have covered Aristotle’s views on virtue being crucial in the building of ones character, I will transition to John Stuart Mill’s opposing view of Utilitarianism. 4 John Stuart Mill’s theory of Utilitarianism or Greatest Happiness principle states that “actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness, wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness.” Mills sole definition of happiness is the absence of pain. He states that there are varying degrees of happiness that should be ranked according to the level of happiness they provide; that some pleasures hold more weight because they are rooted in ones higher faculties. One way to tell if a pleasure is of a higher quality or not is if the person would trade that quality for another or keep it regardless of if it was also accompanied by some amount of pain. He believes that an individual should only be virtuous if that action gives that individual pleasure. Mill argues that happiness is the basis of justice and that all actions are rooted in a desire to find happiness. This being the case, Mill says that a human would not choose a lower level of existence to avoid pain. For example, a well educated individual would not want to downgrade to an ignorant individual but would instead prefer to preserve his dignity as an educated member of society and endure whatever pain that comes with that responsibility. Along with that point, Mills utilitarianism looks at the happiness of the whole society, not just the individual, so if an individual possess a character trait that is somewhat less desirable to that individual but makes the society better off, this quality trait is more desirable by all because it brings more happiness to more people. These two views are very different. While they are both proponents of happiness, one puts a large emphasis on character and how it is necessary to achieve Eudaimonia (Hursthouse) and allow for justice in society. The other puts less of an emphasis on character, believing that the only way to achieving happiness is by experiencing pleasure. I agree wholly with Aristotle in the fact that virtue and what is right must govern our 5 character and how we act, sometimes regardless of how we feel about achieving that action. We must put our own personal interests aside sometimes for the betterment of those around us. If we were guided solely by what made us happy, society would be chaotic because some people would only be happy through virtue deficient actions and justice would not be prevalent if happiness was the sole dictator of ones actions in life. 6 Bibliography Mill, John Stuart. Utilitarianism. 1861. Book 1, 2 and 5. Print. Ross, W.D., trans. Nicomachean Ethics. 359. Book 1-3. Print. Homiak, Marcia, "Moral Character", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2015 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/moral-character/>. Hursthouse, Rosalind, "Virtue Ethics", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2013 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/ethics-virtue/ 7