Download KNOWLEDGE, SOCIOLOGY OF

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts

Frankfurt School wikipedia , lookup

Sociology of the family wikipedia , lookup

Symbolic interactionism wikipedia , lookup

Social Darwinism wikipedia , lookup

Reflexivity (social theory) wikipedia , lookup

Social constructionism wikipedia , lookup

Positivism wikipedia , lookup

Social network wikipedia , lookup

Differentiation (sociology) wikipedia , lookup

Sociology of terrorism wikipedia , lookup

Marxism wikipedia , lookup

Social group wikipedia , lookup

Structural functionalism wikipedia , lookup

Social development theory wikipedia , lookup

Public sociology wikipedia , lookup

Sociology of culture wikipedia , lookup

Sociological theory wikipedia , lookup

Index of sociology articles wikipedia , lookup

The Social Construction of Reality wikipedia , lookup

Postdevelopment theory wikipedia , lookup

History of sociology wikipedia , lookup

Sociology of knowledge wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
SOCIOLOGY OF KNOWLEDGE
by LEWIS A. COSER
International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences
Edited by David L. Sills. The Macmillan Co & The Free Press, NY, 1968 Vol. 7, pp. 428-434
The sociology of knowledge may be broadly defined as that branch of sociology which
studies the relation between thought and society. It is concerned with the social or existential
conditions of knowledge. Scholars in this field, far from being restricted to the sociological
analysis of the cognitive sphere as the term would seem to imply, have concerned themselves
with practically the entire range of intellectual products - philosophies and ideologies,
political doctrines, and theological thought. In all these areas the sociology of knowledge
attempts to relate the ideas it studies to the sociohistorical settings in which they are produced
and received.
Assertions as to how social structures are functionally related to categories of thought and to
specific sets of ideas have a long history. At the be ginning of the seventeenth century,
Francis Bacon outlined the general territory when he wrote about
impressions of nature, which are imposed upon the mind by the sex, by the age, by the region, by
health and sickness, by beauty and deformity, and the like, which are inherent and not extern; and
again, those which are caused by extern fortune; as sovereignty nobility, obscure birth, riches, want,
magistracy, privateness, prosperity, adversity, constant fortune, variable fortune, rising per saltum.
per gradus, and the like. ([1605] 1958, p. 170)
This is indeed the field that later systematic sociology of knowledge claimed as its province.
A variety of European thinkers of the seventeenth, eighteenth, and early nineteenth centuries
may be considered among the precursors of the sociology of knowledge. Several of the
philosophes of the Enlightenment (Condorcet in particular) inquired about the social
preconditions of different types of knowledge, and Auguste Comte's famous "law of three
stages"' asserting the intimate relationship between types of social structures and types of
knowledge, might well be considered a contribution to the sociology of knowledge. It
nevertheless remains true that systematic development of the sociology of knowledge as an
autonomous enterprise rather than as a by-product of other types of inquiry received its main
impetus from two trends in nineteenth-century European sociological thought: the Marxian
tradition in Germany and the Durkheimian tradition in France. Although neither these two
mainstreams - nor their tributaries - are by any means identical in their fundamental
1
assumptions, they are the starting point of most theorizing in the field.
Marx and the German tradition
In his attempt to dissociate himself from the panlogical system of his former master, Hegel,
as well as from the "critical philosophy" of his former "young Hegelian" friends, Karl Marx
undertook, in some of his earlier writings, to establish a connection between philosophies and
the concrete social structures in which they emerged. "It has not occurred to any of these
philosophers," wrote Marx in The German Ideology, "to inquire into the connection of
German philosophy with German reality, the relation of their criticism to their own material
surroundings" (Marx & Engels [1845-1846] 1939, p. 6). This programmatic orientation once
established, Marx proceeded to analyze the ways in which systems of ideas appeared to
depend on the social positions - particularly the class positions - of their proponents.
In his struggle against the dominant ideas of his time Marx was led to a resolute
relativization of these ideas. The eternal verities of dominant thought appeared upon
analysis to be but the direct or indirect expression of the class interests of their exponents.
Marx attempted to explain ideas sytematically in terms of their functions and to relate the the
thought of individuals to their social roles and class positions: "The mode of production in
material life determines the general character of the social, political and spiritual processes of
life. it is not the consciousness of men that determines their existence, but on the contrary
their social existence determines their consciousness" ([1859] 1913, PP 11-12). While Marx
was mainly concerned with uncovering the relationships between bourgeois ideas and
bourgeois interests and life styles, he nevertheless explicitly stated that the same relation also
held true with regard to the emergence of new dissident and revolutionary ideas. According to
the Communist Manifesto,
What else does the history of ideas prove, than that Intellectual production changes its character in
proportion as material production is changed? The ruling ideas of each age have ever been the ideas
of its ruling klass. When people speak of ideas that revolutionize society, they do but express the fact
that within the old society the elements of a new one have been created, and that the dissolution of the
old ideas keeps even pace with the dissolution of the old conditions of existence.
(Marx & Engels
1848. p. 91 in 1964 paperback edition)
In their writings of a later period, Marx and Engels were to qualify their somewhat sweeping
initial statements, which had most often been made in a polemical context. They were thus led
to grant a certain degree of intrinsic autonomy to the development of legal, political, religious,
literary, and artistic ideas. They now stressed that mathematics and the natural sciences were
exempt from the direct influence of the social and economic infrastructure. Moreover, they
2
now granted that the intellectual superstructure of a society was not simply a reflection of the
infrastructure but rather could in turn react upon it.
While the original Marxian thesis reinterpreted in this fashion became a considerably more
flexible instrument, it also lost some of its distinctive qualities. Interpreted rigidly, it tended to
lend itself to use as a rather crude tool for debunking all adverse thought; interpreted flexibly,
it became difficult to distinguish from non-Marxian attempts at the functional analysis of
thought. Also, as Merton has pointed out ([1949] 1957, p. 479), when the Marxian thesis is
stated in so flexible a manner, it becomes impossible to invalidate it at all, since any set of
data may be so interpreted as to fit it.
Despite these difficulties, Marxian modes of analysis in this field, as in so many others,
exerted a powerful - if often subterranean - influence on subsequent German social thought.
Major portions of the work of Max Weber can be seen as attempts on the part of this greatest
of all German sociologists to come to terms with the Marxian inheritance and particularly
with the Marxian assertion of the essentially epiphenomenal character of knowledge and
ideas. The twin heritage of Marx and of Nietzsche (particularly the latter's "debunking" attack
on Christianity as a slave philosophy of ressentimen-laden lower-status groups) loomed very
large in the mental climate of pre-World War I Germany. But it remained for two German
scholars, Max Scheler and Karl Mannheim, to develop a corpus of theory that represents the
first systematic elaboration of the sociology of knowledge as a new scientific discipline. Even
though it followed upon the work of Max Scheler. Karl Mannheim's contribution will be dealt
with first, since it is more directly tied to the main themes of Marxian thought.
Mannheim and universal relativism. Mannheim undertook to generalize the Marxian
interpretation so as to divest it of polemical elements; thus he attempted to transform into a
general tool of analysis what for Marx had been primarily a means of attack against
adversaries. Mannheim wished to create a tool that could be used as effectively for the
analysis of Marxism as for any other system of thought. While in the Marxian formulations
attention was called to the function of ideology in the defense of class privileges and to the
distortions and falsifications of ideas that flowed from the privileged class position of
bourgeois thinkers, Marx's own ideas were held by Marxists to be true and unbiased by virtue
of their being an expression of classes that had no privileged interests to defend. According to
Marx, the defenders of the status quo were inevitably given to false consciousness, while their
critics, being affiliated with the emerging working class, were exempt from such distorting
influences and hence had access to "true consciousness" - that is, to nondistorted historical
truth. Mannheim's orientation, in contradistinction, allowed for the probability that all ideas,
3
even "truths," were related to, and hence influenced by, the social and historical situation from
which they emerged. The very fact that each thinker is affiliated with particular groups in
society - that he occupies a certain status and enacts certain social roles - colors his
intellectual outlook. Men "do not confront the objects of the world from the abstract levels of
a contemplating mind as such, nor do they do so exclusively as solitary beings. On the
contrary they act with and against one another in diversely organized groups, and while doing
so they think with and against one another" (Mannheim [1929-1931] 1954, p. 3).
Mannheim was thus led to define the sociology of knowledge as a theory of the social or
existential conditioning of thought. To him all knowledge and all ideas, although to different
degrees, are "bound to a location" within the social structure and the historical process. At
particular times a particular group can have fuller access to the understanding of a social
phenomenon than other groups, but no group can have
total
access
to it.
(At
times,
though, Mannheim expressed the hope that "detached intellectuals" might in our age achieve a
"unified"perspective" free of existential determination. ) The task of the new discipline was to
ascertain the empirical correlation between intellectual standpoints and structural and
historical positions. From its inception Mannheim's thesis encountered a great deal of
criticism, especially on the grounds that it led to universal relativism. It has been said that the
notion of relativism or relation-ism - the term that Mannheim preferred - "is selfcontradictory, for it must presuppose its own absoluteness. The sociology of knowledge ...
must assume its own validity if it is to have any meaning” (Dahlke 1940, p. 87). If it is
assumed that all thought is existentially determined and hence all truth but relative,
Mannheim's own thought cannot claim privileged exemption.
Mannheim did indeed lay himself open to such attacks, especially in his earlier writings;
however, it seems that he did not mean to imply that "existential determination"
(Seinsverbundenheif) is a kind of total determination that leaves no room for an examination
of ideas in other terms. He explicitly stated that in the social sciences, as elsewhere, "the
ultimate criterion of truth or falsity is to be found in the investigation of the object, and the
sociology of knowledge is no substitute for this" ([1929-1931] 1954, p. 4). No matter what
the imprecisions and methodological shortcomings of Mannheim's theoretical statements are
judged to be, he left a number of concrete studies on such topics as "Conservative Thought"
([1922-1940]
1953, pp. 77-164) and "Competition as a Cultural Phenomenon" ([1923-
1929] 1952, pp. 191-229) which have been recognized
as important contributions even by
those who have been critical of Mannheim's theoretical apparatus.
Scheler's "real factors." Marx laid primary stress on economic and class factors in the
4
determination of ideas; Mannheim expanded this conception to include other groupings such
as generations, status groups, and occupational groups. Max Scheler went still further in
widening the range of factors that influence thought forms. According to Scheler there is no
constant independent variable that determines the emergence of ideas; but rather, in the course
of history, there occurs a sequence of "real factors" that condition thought. In nonliteraic
groups, blood and kinship ties constitute the independent variable; later, political factors; and,
finally, in the modern world economic factors are to be considered as the independent
variables to which thought structures have to be related.
Scheler rejected what he considered the "naturalism" and relativism of previous theorizing in
the field and asserted that there exists an atemporal absolute order of values and ideas - that is,
a realm of eternal essences, which is totally distinct from historical and social reality. At
different moments in historical time and in different cultural systems, different "real factors»
predominate. These real factors "open and close, in determinate ways and determinate order,
the sluice gates of the stream of thought," so that different aspects of the eternal realm of
essences can be grasped at particular points in time and in particular cultural systems (1926).
Thus Scheler thought that he had succeeded in reconciling sociocultural relativity with the
Platonic notion of an eternal realm of unchanging essences.
Scheler's theory of eternal essences is metaphysical and hence not susceptible to scientific
validation. However, his proposal to widen the range of existential factors that may be seen as
the source of particular systems of ideas is testable and potentially fruitful for research.
Scheler's own studies provide important examples of the fruitfulness of this type of inquiry:
for example, his studies on the interrelations between the hierarchical medieval world of
communal estates and the medieval con-ception of the world as a hierarchy culminating to
God, between the content of Plato's theory of ideal and the formal organization of the Platonic
Academy, and between the rise of mechanistic models of thought and the rise of bourgeois,
Gesellschaft types of society. (For a different view of Schelez see Ranulf 1938.)
French contributions
Emile Durkheim's contributions to the sociology of knowledge form only a relatively small
part his total work. Although some of his statements this area are mixed with epistemological
speculations that most experts would consider rather dubious, he nevertheless did some of the
most vital pioneering work in the field. In his attempt to establish the social origin and
functions of morals, values, and religion, and in explaining these as different forms of
"collective representations," Durkheim was led to consider a similar social explanation of the
basic forms of logical classification and of the fundamental categories of thought themselves.
5
Durkheim attempted to account: for the origins of spatial, temporal, and other classifications
among nonliterate peoples and concluded that these classifcations closely approximated the
social organization of these peoples (Durkheim & Mauss 1903). the first "classes," he
suggested, were classes of men, and the classification of objects in the world of nature was
but an extension of the social classifcation already established. All animals and natural objects
were classified as belonging to this or that clan, phratry, or residential or kinship group. Be
further argued that, although scientific classifications have now largely become divorced from
their social origins, the very manner in which we classify things as "belonging to the same
family" still reveals the originally social origins of classificatory thought.
In his last major book The Elementary Forms of the Religious Life (1912), Durkheim
returned to these earlier ideas and attempted a sociological explanation of all fundamental
categories of human thought, especially the concepts of time and space. These, he claimed,
are not only transmitted If society, they are social creations. Society is decisive in the genesis
of logical thought by forming the concepts of which that thought is made. The social
organization of the primitive community is the model for the primitive's spatial organization
of
IBS
surrounding world. Similarly, temporal divisions too days, weeks, months, and years
correspond to periodical recurrences of rites, leasts, and ceremonies: "A calendar expresses
the rhythm of the collective activities, while at the same time its function is to assure their
regularity" ([1912] 1954, p. 10).
These Durkheimian notions have been challenged frequently. It has been pointed out, for
example, that Durkheim slighted the importance of the rhythm of natural phenomena by his
overemphasis on social rhythms (Sorokin 1928, p. 477). More fundamentally, Claude LeviStrauss has argued that society "cannot exist without symbolism, instead of showing how the
appearance of thought makes social life altogether possible and necessary, Durkheim tries the
reverse, i.e., to make symbolism grow out of society. . . . Sociology cannot explain the genesis
of symbolic thought, but has just to take it for granted in man" (1945, p. 518).
Durkheim failed to establish the social origins of all categories of thought, but it is
important to recognize his pioneering contribution to the study of the correlations between
specific systems of thought and systems of social organization. It is this part of Durkheim's
contribution, rather than some of the more debatable epistemological propositions found in
his work, that has influenced later developments in the sociology of knowledge. Thus the
eminent Sinologist Marcel Granet (1934) used Durkheimian leads when he related the
conceptions of time and space in ancient Chinese thought to such social factors as the ancient
feudal organization and the rhythmic alterations of concentrated and dispersed group
6
activities. Jane Harrison (1912) and Francis Cornford (1912) renovated classical studies by
tracing Greek religious notions and philosophical ideas to their origins in tribal initiation
ceremonies and to the clan structure of the Greek tribes. Finally. Maurice Halbwachs (1925)
attempted to establish how even such apparently private and intimate mental activities as
dreams and memories need for their organization a stable reference in the group life in which
individuals participate. [See DURKHEIM; GRANET; HALBWACHS.]
American sociology of knowledge
The work of the major American pragmatists - Pierce, James, and Dewey - abounds with
suggestive leads for the sociology of knowledge. To the extent that pragmatism stressed the
organic process by which every act of thought is linked to human conduct and thus rejected
the radical distinction between thinking and acting which had informed most classical
philosophy, it prepared the ground for consideration of the more specifically sociological
links between social conditions and the thought processes. Insofar as the pragmatists stressed
that thought is in its very nature bound to the social situation in which it arises, they set the
stage for efforts to inquire into the relations between a thinker and his audience. Insofar as
they rejected the traditional view according to which an object of thought was to be sharply
distinguished from the thinking subject and stressed the intimate transactions between subject
and object, they prepared the ground for the specifically American contributions to the
sociology of knowledge.
Pragmatic philosophy is not the only American intellectual trend to influence the development
of the sociology of knowledge. American historical scholarship, especially the work of
Charles A. Beard and Vernon L. Parrington, appropriated for its own uses a number of the
orientations of European sociology of knowledge - especially of its Marxian variety - in
efforts to develop new perspectives on American politics and letters by selfconsciously
relating currents of thought to economic interest and social condition. Many of these strains of
ideas had only an indirect impact on American sociology. In contrast, two major American
thinkers, Thorstein Veblen and George Herbert Mead, directly and explicitly influenced
American sociology of knowledge.
Veblen's emphasis on habits of thought as an outcome of habits of life and his stress on the
dependence of thought styles on community organization are well known. Perhaps less well
known is Veblen’s relatively systematic effort to relate styles of thought to the occupational
roles and positions of their proponents. "The scheme of thought or of knowledge," he wrote,
'is in good part a reverberation of the schemes of life" ([1891-1913] 1961. p. 105); hence,
those engaged in pecuniary occupations are likely to develop thought styles that differ from
7
the styles of those engaged in industrial occupations. Magical as well as matter-of-fact ways
of thinking find their proponents among groups of men differentially located in the social
structure and in the economic process. Moreover, Veblen's savage polemics in his Higher
Learning in America (1918) should not be read as polemics alone. The work is also, and
perhaps above all, a seminal contribution to the sociological study of the organization and
functioning of the American university.
Finally, George Herbert Mead's social behaviorism, with its insistence that mind itself is a
social product and is of social origin, provided the social psychological basis for some of the
assertions of previous theorists. For Mead, communication was central to an understanding of
the nature of mind: "Mind arises through communication by a conversation of gestures in a
social process or context of experience" (1934, p. 50). Even when certain epistemological
positions of Mead are not accepted, it would seem very difficult to deny his claim that if
determinants
of
thought
other
than
society itself exist, they can structure mind only
through the intermediary of the social relations in which it is necessarily enmeshed. [See
MEAD.]
Contemporary trends. As the sociology of knowledge has been incorporated into general
sociological theory both in America and in Europe, it has often merged with other areas of
research and is frequently no longer explicitly referred to as sociology of knowledge. Its
diffusion through partial incorporation has tended to make it lose some of its distinctive
characteristics. Thus, the works of Robert K. Merton (1949) and Bernard Barber (1952) in the
sociology of science, the works of E. C. Hughes (1958), T. H. Marshall ([1934-1949] 1950,
chapter 4), Theodore Caplow (1954), Oswald Hall (1948), Talcott Parsons (1938-1953), and
others in the sociology of the professions and occupations, and - even more generally - much
of the research concerned with social roles may be related to, and in part derived from, the
orientations of the sociology of knowledge. Many practitioners of what is in fact sociology of
knowledge may at times be rather surprised when it is pointed out that, like Monsieur
Jourdain, they have been "talking prose" all along.
Given this wide variety of research in which at least certain leads of the sociology of
knowledge have been utilized, it is difficult to delineate the distinctive characteristics of
contemporary or near contemporary developments in the sociology of knowledge in the
United States. Yet one characteristic seems salient. While in the European tradition attention
tended to be centered upon the production of ideas, with the axiomatic assumption that
different strata of society produce different types of ideas, modern American research is
more concerned with the consumption of ideas and the ways in which different strata of
8
society use standardized thought products. To some extent, as Merton has pointed out ([1949]
1957, pp. 440 ff.), the sociology of public opinion and mass communication has pre-empted
the place of the sociology of knowledge in the contemporary United States.
Nevertheless, recent American contributions have by no means been limited to this field.
There has been a significant attempt at stocktaking and at discussing methodological
questions left unresolved by the European tradition. Merton's writings in this area represent
the most sophisticated codification of the problems faced by the sociology of knowledge.
Among other notable contributions to the methodology and theoretical clarification of the
sociology of knowledge are those of the philosopher Arthur Child and the sociologists
Hans
Speier (1938), Gerald DeGre
(1943),
Kurt H. Wolff (1959), Werner Stark
(1958), and C. Wright Mills (1963).
Among substantive American contributions, the work of Pitirim A. Sorokin is of special
note (1937-1941; 1943). Blending an earlier European tradition of large-scale speculation
with American statistical research techniques, Sorokin developed a characteristically idealistic
theory of the sociology of knowledge. Rejecting the prevalent conceptualizations that
consider social classes or other social and economic groups as the independent variable in the
functional relations between thought and society. Sorokin considers variant "cultural
mentalities" or cultural premises as the key variables. He attempts to show that the periodic
dominance of three major cultural tendencies - the ideational, the idealistic, and the sensate
mentality - can account for the fluctuations of types of knowledge that have marked history.
Although his argument often seems to involve a kind of circular reasoning, and although the"
neglect of the existential roots of thought can hardly be justified in view of the promising
results already achieved by Sorokin's predecessors, the many contributions by Sorokin and
some of his students - in, for example, the sociology of science or the elucidation of the
notion of social time - remain noteworthy.
Florian Znaniecki's neglected but important study The Social Role of the Man of Knowledge
(1940) represents, like Sorokin's work, a fruitful blending of the European tradition with
American contributions. Znaniecki introduces the notion of the "social circle," that is, the
audience or public to which a thinker addresses himself. He thus links the sociology of
knowledge with research on publics and audiences that was pioneered by the Chicago school
of sociology' (for example, see Park 1904). Znaniecki shows that thinkers - at least in
differentiated societies - are not likely to address their total society but rather only selected
segments or publics. The thinker is related to a social circle: and this circle expects him to live
up to certain of its demands, in exchange for which it grants him recognition and support.
9
Men of knowledge anticipate the demands of their public; and they tend to form self-images,
select data, and seize upon problems in terms of their actual or anticipated audiences. Men of
knowledge may thus be classified in regard to their social roles and their publics. Hence it
becomes possible to understand the emergence of such special roles as that of sage,
technologist, and scholar in terms of the differentiated publics to which they address
themselves. [See INTELLECTUALS.]
It is impossible to discuss or even enumerate within the confines of this article the recent
American studies which either directly or indirectly contribute to the further development of
the sociology of knowledge. This state of affairs may itself be an indicator of the continued
strength of this research orientation. A few references will have to suffice.
Research in the field of social role, the sociology of science, the professions and
occupations, and the sociology of communications and public opinion has already been
mentioned. In other areas can be listed the studies exploring the relations between minority
status and originality of intellectual perspective, to which Veblen (1919) made significant
contributions, and of which the recent work by Melvin Seeman (1956) seems an excellent
example; the studies in the history of sociological or philosophical theories, in which
conceptualizations derived from the sociology of knowledge have been utilized - for example,
the works of C. Wright Mills on pragmatism (1964); the studies that relate thought styles of
American academic men to the structure and functioning of the American academy - such as
Logan Wilson's Academic Man (1942), Lazarsfeld and Thielens' Academic Mind (1958), an
analysis of social scientists' reactions to the threats posed by the McCarthy era, and Caplow
and McGee's Academic Marketplace (1958); general studies of the settings and contexts in
which intellectuals play their peculiar roles, such as Lewis Coser's Men of Ideas (1965); and
Fritz Machlup's large-scale study, The Production and Distribution of Knowledge in the
United States (1962). More detailed studies - such as Peter Berger's recent attempt to account
for the popularity of psychoanalysis in America (1965) and John Bennett's study of divergent
interpretations of the same culture by different social scientists in terms of their divergent
backgrounds and social perspectives (1946)—have also been very much in evidence in recent
years.
The sociology of knowledge was marked in its early history by a tendency to set up
grandiose hypothetical schemes. These contributed a number of extremely suggestive leads.
Recently its practitioners have tended to withdraw from such ambitious undertakings and to
restrict themselves to somewhat more manageable investigations. Although this tendency has
been an antidote to earlier types of premature generalizations, it also carries with it the danger
10
of trivialization. Perhaps the sociology of knowledge of the future will return to the more
daring concerns of its founders, thus building upon the accumulation of careful and detailed
investigations by preceding generations of researchers.
[Directly related are the entries
STRUCTURAL ANALYSIS.
MARXIST SOCIOLOGY; SOCIAL STRUCTURE,
Other relevant material may be found in
SOCIOLOGY OF LITERATURE; SCIENCE;
and in the biographies of
article on
LITERATURE,
SOCIAL
article on
THE
BACON; DEWEY; DURKHEIM;
HALBWACIIS; JAMES; MANNHEIM; MARX; PEIRCE; SCHELER; SOROKIN; VEBLEN; WEBER, MAX;
ZNANIECKI.]
BIBLIOGRAPHY
For extensive bibliographies on the sociology of knowledge, see Merton 1949; Mannheim
1929-1931; Maquet 1949; and Wolff 1959.
BACON, FRANCIS
(1605) 1958 The Advancement of Learning. Edited with an introduction by G.
W. Kitchin. London: Dent; New York: Dutton.
BARBER, BERNARD 1952
BENNETT, JOHN
Science and the Social Order. Glencoe, 111.: Free Press.
W. (1946) 1956 The Interpretation of Pueblo Culture: A Question of Values.
Pages 203-216 in Douglas G. Haring (editor), Personal Character and Cultural Milieu: A
Collection of Readings. 3d ed., rev. Syracuse Univ. Press - First published in Volume 2 of the
Southwestern Journal of Anthropology.
BERGER, PETER
L. 1965 Toward a Sociological Understanding of Psychoanalysis. Social
Research 32:26-41.
CAPLOW, THEODORE 1954
CAPLOW, THEODORE;
The Sociology of Work. Minneapolis: Univ. of Minnesota Press.
and McGEE,
REECE
J. 1958 The Academic Marketplace. New York: Basic
BooJcs. - A paperback edition was published in 1961 by Wiley.
CORNFORD. FRANCIS
M. 1912 From Religion to Philosophy: A Study in the Origins of Western
Speculations. New York: Longmans. - A paperback edition was published in 1957 by Harper.
COSER. LEWIS A.
DAHLKE,
1965 Men of Ideas: A Sociologist's View. New York: Free Press.
H. OTTO 1940 The Sociology of Knowledge. Pages 64-89 in Harry E. Barnes, Howard
Becker, and Frances B. Becker (editors), Contemporary Social Theory. New York: Appieton
DtGRE.
GERALD
L. 1943 Society and Ideoiogit: An Inquiry Into the Sociology of Knowledge.
New York: Columbia Univ. Press.
DURKHEIM, EMILE
(1912) 1954 The Elementary Forms of the Religious Life. London: Allen &
Unwin; New York: Macmillan. - First published as Les formes elementaires de la vie
religieuse, le systeme totemique en Australie. A paperback edition was published in 1961 by
11
Collier.
DURKHEIM, EMILE:
and
MAUSS, MARCEL
(1903) 1963 Primitive Classification. Translated and
edited by Rodney Needham. Univ. of Chicago Press. - First published as "De quelques formes
primitives de classification" in L'annee sociologique.
GRANET, MARCEL (1934)
1950 Le pensee chinoise. Paris: Michel.
HALBWACHS, MAURICE 1925
HALL, OSWALD 1948
Les cadres sociaux de la memoire. Paris: Alcan.
Stages of a Medical Career. American Journal of Sociology 53:327-336.
HARRISON, JANE ELLEN (1912)
1927 Themis.- A Study of the Social Origins of Greek Religion. 2d
ed. rev. Cambridge Univ. Press.
HUGHES, EVERETT C.
LAZARSFELD, PAUL
1958 Men and Their Work. Glencoe, 111.: Free Press.
F.; and THIELENS, WAGNER JR. 1958 The Academic Mind: Social Scientists in
a Time of Crisis. A report of the Bureau of Applied Social Research, Columbia University.
Glencoe, III.: Free Press.
LEVI-STRAUSS, CLAUDE 1945
French Sociology. Pages 503-537 in Georges Gurvitch and Wilbert
E. Moore (editors), Twentieth Century Sociology. New York Philosophical Library.
MACHLUP, FRITZ
1962 The Production and Distribution of Knowledge in the United States.
Princeton Univ. Press.
MANNHEIM, KARL (1922-1940)1953
Essays on Sociology and Social Psychology. Edited by Paul
Kecskemeti London: Routledge. - See especially pages 77-164 in "Conservative Thought.
MANNHEIM, KARL
(1923-1929) 1952 Essays on the Sociology of Knowledge. Edited by Paul
Kecskemeti. New York: Oxford Univ. Press. -* See especially pages 191-229 on
"Competition as a Cultural Phenomenon"
MANNHEIM, KARL
(1929-1931) 1954 Ideology and Utopia: An Introduction to the Sociology of
Knowledge. New York: Harcourt; London: Routledge. - First published in German. A
paperback edition was published in 1955 by Harcourt.
MAQUET, JACQUES
J. (1949) 1951 The Sociology Of Knowledge, Its Structure and Its Relation to
the Philosophy of Knowledge: A Critical Analysis of the Systems of Karl Mannheim and
Pitirim A. Sorokin. Translated by John F. Locke. Boston: Beacon. - First published in French.
MARSHALL,
T. H. (1934-1949) 1950 Citizenship and SocraZ Class, and Other Essays.
Cambridge Univ. Press.
MARX. KARL
(1859) 1913 A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy. Chicago: Kerr. -
First published as Zur Kritik der politischen Okonomie.
MARX. KARL;
and
ENGELS, FRIEDRICH
(1845-1846) 1939 The German Ideology. Parts 1 and 3.
With an introduction by R. Pascal. New York: International Publishers. — Written in 184512
1846, the full text was first published in 1932 as Die deutsche Ideologic and republished by
Dietz Verlag in 1953.
MARX, KARL:
and
ENGZLS. FRIEDRICH
(1848) 1963 The Communist Manifesto. New York:
Russell. - A paperback edition was published in 1964 by Washington Square Press.
MEAD, GEORGE
H. 1934 Mind, Self and Society From the Standpoint of a Social Behaviorist.
Edited by Charles W. Morris. Univ. of Chicago Press. - Published posthumously
MERTON, ROBERT
K. (1949) 1957 Social Theory and Social Structure. Rev. & enl. ed. Glencoe,
III.: Free Press. - See especially Part 3 on 'The Sociology of Knowledge" and Part 4 on "The
Sociology of Science."
MILLS.
C.
WRIGHT
1963 Power, Politics and People: The Collected Essays of C. Wright Mills.
Edited and introduced by Irving Louis Horowitz. New York: Oxford Univ. Press. - See
especially pages. 423-438 on "Language, Logic and Culture," pages 439-452 on "Situated
Actions and Vocabularies of Motive," and pages 453-456 on "Methodological Consequences
of the Sociology of Knowledge."
MILLS,
C.
WRIGHT
1964 Sociology and Pragmatism: The Higher Learning in America. Edited
with an introduction by Irving Louis Horowitz. New York: Paine-Whitman. - A revision of
Mills's unpublished doctoral dissertation.
PARK. ROBERT
E. 1904 Masse und Publikum: Eine methodologische und soziologische
Untersuchung. Bern: Lack & Grunau.
PARSONS, TALCOTT
Free Press.
(1938-1953) 1963
RANULF,
SVEND
(1938)
Essays in Sociological Theory. Rev. ed. Glencoe, III.:
1964
MoraJ
Indignation and Middle Class
Psychology: A Sociological Study. New York: Schocken. - The appendix contains a welldocumented attack on Scheler's theory of resentment.
SCHELER, MAX (1926)
1960 Die Wissensformen und die Gesellschaft. 2d ed., rev. Bern: Francke.
SEEMAN, MELVIN 1956
Intellectual Perspective and Adjustment to Minority Group Status. Social
Problems 3:142-153.
SOROKIN, PITIRIM
A. 1928 Contemporary Sociological Theories. New York: Harper. --> A
paperback edition was published in 1964 by Harper as Contemporary Sociological Theories
Through the First Quarter of the Twentieth Century.
SOROKIN, PITIRIM A.
(1937-1941) 1962 Social and Cultural Dynamics. 4 vols. Englewood Cliffs.
N.J.: Bed-minster Press. - Volume 1: Fluctuation of Forms of Art. Volume 2: Fluctuation of
Systems of Truth, Ethics, and Law. Volume 3: Fluctuation of Social Relationships, War, and
Revolution. Volume 4: Basic Problems, Principles, and Methods.
SOROKIN, PITIRIM
A. (1943) 1964 Sociocultural Causality, Space, Time: A Study of Referential
13
Principles of Sociology and Social Science. New York: Russell.
SPEIER, HANS
(1938) 1952 The Social Determination of Ideas. Pages 95-111 in Hans Speier.
Social Order and the Risks of War: Papers in Political Sociology. New York: Stewart.
STARK, WERNER 1958
The Sociology of Knowledge: An Essay in Aid of a Deeper Understanding
of the History of Ideas. London: Routledge; Glencoe. III.: Free Press.
VEBLEN, THORSTEIN
(1891-1913) 1961 The Place of Science in Modern Civilisation, and Other
Essays. New York: Russell.
VEBLEN, THORSTEIN
(1918)1957 The Higher Learning in America: A Memorandum on the
Conduct of Universities by Business Men. New York: Sagamore.
VEBLEN, THORSTEIN (1919)
1948 The Intellectual Preeminence of Jews in Modern Europe. Pages
467-479 in Thorstein Veblen, The Portable Vtblen. Edited with an introduction by Max
Lerner. New York: Viking.
WILSON, LOGAN (1942)
1964 The Academic Man: A Study in the Sociology of a Profession. New
York: Octagon.
WOLFF, KURT H.
1959 The Sociology of Knowledge and Sociological Theory. Pages 567-602 in
Llewellyn Gross (editor), Symposium on Sociological Theory New York: Harper.
ZNANIECKI, FLORIAN
1940 The Social Role of the Man of Knowledge. New York: Columbia
Univ. Press.
14