* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Lesson 1
Fuzzy concept wikipedia , lookup
History of the function concept wikipedia , lookup
Analytic–synthetic distinction wikipedia , lookup
Abductive reasoning wikipedia , lookup
Axiom of reducibility wikipedia , lookup
Foundations of mathematics wikipedia , lookup
Truth-bearer wikipedia , lookup
Fuzzy logic wikipedia , lookup
Willard Van Orman Quine wikipedia , lookup
First-order logic wikipedia , lookup
Lorenzo Peña wikipedia , lookup
Interpretation (logic) wikipedia , lookup
Jesús Mosterín wikipedia , lookup
Propositional calculus wikipedia , lookup
Mathematical logic wikipedia , lookup
Modal logic wikipedia , lookup
Curry–Howard correspondence wikipedia , lookup
Quantum logic wikipedia , lookup
Combinatory logic wikipedia , lookup
History of logic wikipedia , lookup
Laws of Form wikipedia , lookup
Natural deduction wikipedia , lookup
Law of thought wikipedia , lookup
Introduction to Logic Marie Duží [email protected] 1 Introduction to Logic Texts to study: http://www.cs.vsb.cz/duzi Courses Introduction to Logic: Information for students Chapters: 1. Introduction 2. propositional Logic 2.1. Semantic exposition 2.2. Resolution method 3. Predicate Logic 3.1. Semantic exposition 3.2. General resolution method Presentation of lectures Book: Gamut L.T.F., Logic, Language and Meaning, Chicago Press 1991, Vol. 1. Chapter 1, Chapter 2 (except of 2.7), Chapter 3, and Chapter 4 – Sections: 4.1, 4.2, 4.4. Introduction to Logic 2 Requirements to pass the course • Accreditation: • Two written tests – Propositional logic - max. 15 grades, min. 5 grades. – Predicate logic - max. 15 grades, min. 5 grades. – No repetitions for the tests! + 5 grades for being active • Requirement: obtaining at least 15 grades. • Exam: Written test (max. 65 grades, min. 30 grades) • Total: – at least 51 grades – good (3), – at least 66 grades – very good (2), – at least 86 grades – excellent (1) Introduction to Logic 3 1. Introduction What is logic about? What is the subject of logic? Logic is the science of correct, valid reasoning, or, in other words, the art of a valid argumentation What is an argument? Argument: On the assumption of true premises P1,...,Pn it is possible to reason that the conclusion Z is true as well: P1, ..., Pn Z Example: On the assumption that it is Thursday I belief that today a lecture on Introduction to logic takes place: Thursday Lecture on Logic Introduction to Logic 4 Introduction: valid arguments In this course we deal only with deductively valid arguments. Notation: P1,...,Pn |= Z The conclusion Z logically follows from the premises P1,..., Pn. Definition 1: The conclusion Z logically follows from the premises P1,...,Pn , notation: P1,...,Pn |= Z, iff under no circumstances it might happen that the premises were true and the conclusion false. Introduction to Logic 5 Introduction: valid arguments Example: Because it is Thursday today I believe that the lecture “Introduction to Logic” takes place: It is Thursday Lecture on Logic takes place invalid Is it a deductively valid argument? No, it is not: It might happen that Duzi were sick and the lecture does not take place though it is Thursday (a premise is missing, for instance that Each Thursday the lecture takes place). Each Thursday the lecture on Logic takes place. It is Thursday today valid Today the lecture on Logic takes place. Introduction to Logic 6 (Deductively) invalid arguments: generalization (induction), abduction We will not deal with arguments that are not deductively valid, like: generalization (induction), abduction, and other –ductions a subject of Artificial Intelligence (non-monotonic reasoning) Examples: Till now logic always took place on Thursday. induction, invalid (Therefore) Logic will take place also this Thursday All swans that I have seen till now are white. (Therefore) All swans are white Introduction to Logic induction, invalid 7 Deductively invalid arguments: generalization (induction), abduction Examples: All rabbits in the hat are white. These rabbits are from the hat. These rabbits are white. Deduction, valid These rabbits are from the hat. These rabbits are white. (Probably) All rabbits in the hat are white. Generalization, Induction, invalid All rabbits in the hat are white. These rabbits are white. (Probably because) These rabbits are from the hat. Abduction, invalid Seeking premises, causes of events, diagnosis of “malfunctions” Introduction to Logic 8 Examples of deductively valid arguments 1. He is at home or he has gone to a pub. If he is at home then he plays a piano. But he did not play a piano. ------------------------------------------------ Hence He has gone to the pub. Sometimes the arguments are so obvious that it seems as if we did not need any logic. Well: If he did not play a piano (3. premise), then he was not at home (2. premise), and according to the first premise he must have gone to the pub. But, we all use logic in our everyday life, we wouldn’t survive without logic: 2. All agarics (mushrooms) have a strong toxic effect. The mushroom I have picked up is an agaric. ---------------------------------------------------------------------The mushroom I have picked up has a strong toxic effect. Will you examine the mushroom by tasting it, or will you rely on logic? Introduction to Logic 9 Examples of deductively valid arguments All agarics (mushrooms) have a strong toxic effect. This apple is an agaric. ---------------------------------------------------------------------Hence This apple has a strong toxic effect. The argument is valid. But the conclusion is evidently not true (false). Hence, at least one premise is false (obviously the second). Circumstances according to Definition 1 are particular interpretations (depending on the expressive power of the logical system). Logical connectives (‘and’, ‘or’, ‘if …then …’) and quantifiers (‘all’, ‘some’, ‘every’, …) have a fixed interpretation; we interpret elementary propositions and/or their parts. In our example, if “this apple” and “agarics” were interpreted in such a way that the second premise were true, the truth of the conclusion is guaranteed. We also say that the argument has a valid logical form. Introduction to Logic 10 Deductively valid arguments Logic is a tool that helps us to discover the relation of logical entailment, to answer questions like „What follows from particular assumptions “?, etc. 1. 2. 3. If the course is good then it is useful. The lecturer is sharply demanding studiousness or the course is not useful. But the lecturer is not demanding. -------------------------------------------------------------------------- Hence 4. • The course is not good. It helps our intuition that can sometimes fail. – – – The assumptions can be complicated, “enmeshed in negations and other connectives”, so that the relation of entailment is not obvious at first sight. Similarly as all the mother-tongue speakers use intuitively rules of grammar without knowing the grammar explicitly (often not being able to formulate the rules). But sometimes it is useful to consult the grammar book or a dictionary (in particular when taking part in a TV competition). Introduction to Logic 11 Examples of valid arguments 1. All men like football and beer. 2. Some beer-lovers do not like football. 3. Xaver likes only those who like football and beer. –––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––– 4. Xaver does not like some women. Necessarily, if premises are true the conclusion has to be true as well. Is this argument valid? Certainly, if Xaver likes only those who like football and beer (premise 3), then he does not like some beer-lovers (namely those who do not like football – according to the premise 2). Hence, (according to 1) he does not like some “no-men”, i.e., women. But according to the Definition 1 the argument is not valid: the argument is valid if necessarily, i.e., in all the circumstances (under all interpretations) in which the premises are true the conclusion is true as well. But: in our case those individuals that are not men would not have to be interpreted as women. A premise is missing, viz. the premise “who is not a man is a woman”. Moreover, to be precise, we should also specify that “who is a lover of something he likes that”. Introduction to Logic 12 Examples of valid arguments Hence: We have to state all the premises necessary for deriving the conclusion. 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. All men like football and beer. Some beer-lovers do not like football. Xaver likes only those who like football and beer. Who is not a man is a woman. Who is a lover of something he likes it. –––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––– 6. Xaver does not like some women. Now the argument is valid, it has a valid logical form. The conclusion is logically entailed by (follows from) the premises. We also say that the conclusion is informationally (deductively) contained in the premises. Introduction to Logic 13 Valid arguments in mathematics Argument A: Argument B: No prime number is divisible by three. The number 9 is divisible by three. ––––––––––––––––––––––––––– The number 9 is not a prime. No prime number is divisible by six. The number eight is not a prime. ––––––––––––––––––––––––––– The number eight is not divisible by six. valid invalid Though in the second case B it can never happen that the premises were true and the conclusion false, the argument is invalid. The conclusion is not logically entailed by the premises. If the expression “eight” were interpreted as the number 12, the premises would be true and the conclusion false. (The conclusion is not deductively contained in the premises) Introduction to Logic 14 Theorem of deduction; semantic variant If the argument P1,...,Pn |= Z is valid, then the statement of the form “if P1 and ... and Pn then Z” P1 &...& Pn Z is analytically (necessarily) true. Notation: |= P1 ... Pn Z. Hence: P1,...,Pn |= Z (if and only if) P1,...,Pn-1 |= (Pn Z) P1,...,Pn-2 |= ((Pn-1 Pn) Z) P1,...,Pn-3 |= ((Pn-2 Pn-1 Pn) Z) … |= (P1 ... Pn) Z Introduction to Logic 15 Logical analysis of language Validness of an argument is determined by the meaning (interpretation) of particular statements that are analyzed (formalized) in a less or more fine-grained way according to the expressive power of a logical system: • • • • • Propositional logic: makes it possible to analyze only the way in which a complex statement is composed from elementary propositions. The composition of elementary propositions is not examined, they contribute only by its truth value: True – 1, False – 0 (an algebra of truth values) 1st-order Predicate logic: makes it possible to analyze moreover the composition of elementary propositions, namely the way in which properties and/or relations are ascribed to (tuples of) individuals. 2nd-order Predicate logic: makes it possible to analyze moreover properties of properties, propertied of functions and relations between them. Modal logics (analyze “necessary” and “possible”), epistemic logics (knowledge), doxastic logics (of hypotheses) deontic logics (of commands), ... Transparent intensional logic (perhaps the most powerful system) – see the course “Principles of logical analysis“. Introduction to Logic 16 Properties of valid arguments A valid argument may have a false conclusion: All primes are odd The number 2 is not odd The number 2 is not a prime But then at least one premise has to be false In such a case we also say that the argument is not sound. But a valid argument that is not sound may also be useful: a proof ad absurdum. If you want to show that your boss is not right, it is not diplomatic to say it in an open way. Instead, you may argue by way of the proof ad absurdum: “Well, you say P – interesting, but P entails Q, and Q entails R, which is obviously false.” (Hence, P must have been false as well.) Monotonicity: if an argument is valid then extending the set of assumptions by another premise does not change the validity of the argument. Introduction to Logic 17 Properties of valid arguments • From contradictory (inconsistent) assumptions (such that it can never happen that all of them were simultanously true) any conclusion follows. • If I study hard then I’ll pass the exam. • I haven’t passed the exam though I studied hard. -------------------------------------------------------------------• (e.g.) My dog plays a piano right now • Reflexivity: If A is one of the assumptions P1,...,Pn, then P1,...,Pn |= A. • Transitivity: If P1, …, Pn |= Z and Q1, …, Qm, Z |= Z’, then P1, …, Pn, Q1, …, Qm |= Z’ . Break Introduction to Logic 18 Naïve theory of sets What is it a set? A set is a collection of elements, and it is determined just by its elements; a set consisting of elements a, b, c is denoted: {a, b, c} An element of a set can be again a set, a set may consist of no elements, it may be empty (denoted by ) ! Examples: , {a, b}, {b, a}, {a, b, a}, {{a, b}}, {a, {b, a}}, {, {}, {{}}} Sets are identical if and only if (iff) they have exactly the same elements (the principle of extensionality) Notation: x M – „x is an element of M“ a {a, b}, a {{a, b}}, {a, b} {{a, b}}, {, {}, {{}}}, {, {}}, but: x for any (i.e., all) x. {a, b} = {b, a} = {a, b, a}, but: {a, b} {{a, b}} {a, {b, a}} Introduction to Logic 19 Set-theoretical operations (create new sets from sets) Union: A B = {x | x A or x B} read: „The set of all x such that x is an element of A or x is an element of B.“ b, c} {a, d} = {a, b, c, d} {odd numbers} {even numbers} = {natural numbers} – denoted Nat {a, UiI Ai = {x | x Ai for some i I} Ai = {x | x = 2.i for some i Nat} UiNat Ai = the set of all even numbers Let Introduction to Logic 20 Set-theoretical operations (create new sets from sets) Intersection: A B = {x | x A and x B} read: „The set of all x such that x is an element of A and x is an element of B as well.“ b, c} {a, d} = {a} {even numbers} {odd numbers} = {a, iI Ai = {x | x Ai for all i I} Let Ai = {x | x Nat, x i} Then iNat Ai = Introduction to Logic 21 Relations between sets A set A is a subset of a set B, denoted A B, iff each element of A is also an element of B. A set A is a proper subset of a set B, denoted A B, iff each element of A is also an element of B but not vice versa. {a} {a} {a, b} {{a, b}} !!! It holds: A B, iff A B and A B It holds: A B, iff A B = B, iff A B = A Introduction to Logic 22 Some other set-theoretical operations Difference: A \ B = {x | x A and x B} {a, b, c} \ {a, b} = {c} Complement: Let A M. The complement of A with respect to M is the set A’ = M \ A Cartesian product: A B = {a,b | aA, bB} where a,b je an ordered couple (the ordering is important: a is the first, b is the second) It holds: a,b = c,d iff a = c, b = d But: a,b b,a, though {a,b} = {b,a} !!! generalization: A … A the set of n-tuples, denoted also by An Introduction to Logic 23 Some other set-theoretical operations Potential set: 2A = {B | B A}, denoted also by P(A) 2{a,b} = {, {a}, {b}, {a,b}} 2{a,b,c} = {, {a}, {b}, {c}, {a,b}, {a,c}, {b,c}, {a,b,c}} How many elements are there in 2A ? If |A| is the number of elements (cardinality) of a set A, then 2A has 2|A| elements (hence the notation: 2A) 2{a,b} {a} = {, {a,a}, {b,a}, {a,a, b,a}} Introduction to Logic 24 Grafical picturing (in a universe U): A: S\(PM) = (S\P)(S\M) S(x) (P(x) M(x)) S(x) P(x) M(x) S B: P\(SM) = (P\S)(P\M) P(x) (S(x) M(x)) P(x) S(x) M(x) A C: (S P) \ M S(x) P(x) M(x) E C D: S P M D B F S(x) P(x) M(x) G E: (S M) \ P S(x) M(x) P(x) F: P M (P M) \ S P(x) M(x) S(x) G: M\(PS) = (M\P)(M\S) H M(x) (P(x) S(x)) M(x) P(x) S(x) H: U \ (S P M) = (U \ S U \ P U \ S) (S(x) P(x) M(x)) S(x) P(x) M(x) Introduction to Logic 25 Russell’s paradox Is it true that any collection of elements (i.e., a collection defined in an arbitrary way) can be considered to be a set? It is normal that a set and its elements are entities of different types. Hence a “normal set” is not an element of itself. Let N is a set of all normal sets: N = {M | M M}. Question: Is N N ? In other words, is N itself normal? Yes? But then according to the definition of N it holds that N is normal, i.e., NN. No? But then NN, hence N is normal, and therefore it belongs to N, i.e., NN. Both the answers lead to a contradiction. N is not well defined. The definition does not determine a collection of elements that could be considered to be a set. Introduction to Logic 26 The end of lesson 1 Introduction to Logic 27