* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download The Importance of Ethics to the Practice of Public Relations
Consequentialism wikipedia , lookup
Ethical intuitionism wikipedia , lookup
Cosmopolitanism wikipedia , lookup
Morality and religion wikipedia , lookup
Kantian ethics wikipedia , lookup
Virtue ethics wikipedia , lookup
Alasdair MacIntyre wikipedia , lookup
J. Baird Callicott wikipedia , lookup
Secular morality wikipedia , lookup
Sexual ethics wikipedia , lookup
Ethics of technology wikipedia , lookup
Aristotelian ethics wikipedia , lookup
Thomas Hill Green wikipedia , lookup
Primary care ethics wikipedia , lookup
Marketing ethics wikipedia , lookup
Motion Picture Production Code wikipedia , lookup
Ethics of artificial intelligence wikipedia , lookup
Compliance and ethics program wikipedia , lookup
New Testament household code wikipedia , lookup
Arthur Schafer wikipedia , lookup
Medical ethics wikipedia , lookup
Accounting ethics wikipedia , lookup
Clare Palmer wikipedia , lookup
Business ethics wikipedia , lookup
The Importance of a Code of Ethics to the Practice of Public Relations In 1996, the Center for the Study of Ethics in the Professions (CSEP) at the Illinois Institute of Technology (2009a) received a grant to place its collection of codes of ethics on the Web. More than 850 codes of professions, corporations, government agencies, and academic institutions can now be found online at http://ethics.iit.edu. The center was established in 1976 “to promote research and teaching on practical moral problems in the professions” (CSEP, 2009b) and was the “first interdisciplinary center to focus on ethics in the professions” (CSEP, 2009b). CSEP acknowledges that “some writers have suggested that codes of professional ethics are pointless and unnecessary. Many others believe that codes are useful and important, but disagree about why” (CSEP, 2009c). At the outer edges of the first camp is John Ladd (1991), who maintains that to rely on a code of ethics is “to confuse ethics with law” (CSEP, 2009c). Ladd (1991) contends that there is no special ethics for professionals that is somehow separate from the ethics of ordinary human beings. Professionals “have no special rights or duties separate from their rights and duties as moral persons” (CSEP, 2009c). Heinz Luegenbiehl (1991) mounts a different attack against codes of ethics: “The adoption of a code is significant for the professionalization of an occupational group, because it is one of the external hallmarks testifying to the claim that the group recognizes an obligation to society that transcends mere economic self-interest” (p. 138); however, “ultimately codes of ethics create moral problems rather than helping to resolve them” (CSEP, 2009c). He remarks that professionals do not often consult their codes of ethics for guidance on ethical matters and that the guidelines presented in the codes are sometimes inconsistent (Luegenbiehl, 1991). Harris et al. (1995) argue that though practicing professionals do not frequently consult their codes, that does not necessarily mean that they do not know about or care about the their contents. “Further, the fact that codes of ethics sometimes seem internally inconsistent can be addressed by understanding codes of ethics not as recipes for decision-making, but as expressions of ethical considerations to bear in mind. We should view them as an ethical framework rather than as specific solutions to problems” (CSEP, 2009c). One of the most compelling cases for the value of a code of ethics comes from Michael Davis (1991), who argues that codes of ethics are to be understood as conventions between professionals: The code is to protect each professional from certain pressures (for example, the pressure to cut corners to save money) by making it reasonably likely...that most other members of the profession will not take advantage of her good conduct. A code protects members of a profession from certain consequences of competition. A code is a solution to a coordination problem. (p. 154) Davis (1991) gives the example of an engineer who can use his profession’s code of ethics to object to pressure to produce substandard work, not merely as an ordinary moral agent, but as a professional. Engineers or doctors or clergy or public relations professionals can say, "As a professional, I cannot ethically put business concerns ahead of professional ethics." Making such a statement and taking such a stand would allow a public relations professional to avoid deceiving the public or misrepresenting an issue or withholding pertinent information by telling a client, politely but firmly, that such behavior is prohibited by his or her code of ethics. Davis (1991) gives four reasons why professionals should support their profession’s code of ethics: 1. Upholding the code will help protect them from being injured by what others in their profession do. 2. Upholding the code will help ensure a working environment in which it will be easier than it would otherwise be to resist pressure to do what the professional would rather not do. 3. Upholding the code helps make the profession one in which practitioners need not feel embarrassment, shame, or guilt about what they do. 4. Upholding the code reinforces the individual professional’s obligation to do his or her part in fostering benefits for all those within the profession (p. 166). Harris et al. (1995) make the point that a code indicates to others that the profession is seriously concerned with responsible, professional conduct (p. 35). This is especially important in the practice of public relations, which often is seen by the public as the realm of spin doctors and fabricators. A code of ethics that is upheld by its members can foster consistency and build trust (see Appendices E-H). Ethics: Though “morality” and “ethics” are often used interchangeably, the two actually concern different areas of social conduct. The former is primarily concerned with behavior that either adheres to or is in opposition to spiritual or religious teachings, whereas the latter concerns standards of behavior set by a profession, an organization, or an individual (Lattimore et. al, 2009, p. 74). Ethics concerns what is good and bad, fair and unfair, professional and unprofessional, proper and improper behavior for an individual, a profession, a company, or an organization. Code of ethics: A set of principles that all members of an organization, an institution, a company, or a profession swear to uphold. For the most part, codes of ethics have little or no enforcement provisions. To be in good standing, a member is supposed to adhere to the code’s principles, but if he or she does not, he or she may not suffer any consequences (Wilcox et. al, 2007, p. 81).