* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Moral Reasoning
Lawrence Kohlberg wikipedia , lookup
Business ethics wikipedia , lookup
Individualism wikipedia , lookup
Moral disengagement wikipedia , lookup
Alasdair MacIntyre wikipedia , lookup
Moral development wikipedia , lookup
Golden Rule wikipedia , lookup
Bernard Williams wikipedia , lookup
The Morals of Chess wikipedia , lookup
Ethics in religion wikipedia , lookup
Kantian ethics wikipedia , lookup
Moral relativism wikipedia , lookup
Morality and religion wikipedia , lookup
Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals wikipedia , lookup
Lawrence Kohlberg's stages of moral development wikipedia , lookup
Morality throughout the Life Span wikipedia , lookup
Ethical intuitionism wikipedia , lookup
Moral responsibility wikipedia , lookup
Secular morality wikipedia , lookup
Thomas Hill Green wikipedia , lookup
Moral Reasoning Ethical dilemmas in management are not simple choices between “right” and “wrong”.They are complex judgments on the balance between economic performance and social performance, complicated by the multiple alternatives, extended consequence, uncertain probabilities and career implications that are an inherent part of the decisions. Formal Rules (Laws) and Ethics You may ask why it is necessary for professionals to have the ability to critically analyze [ethical ]situations. After all, if the rules are there, then it just seems a matter of following them. It is extremely important to realize, however, that acting ethically in the professions is not so simple. Adopting a simplistic approach will not be helpful and is likely to be damaging. Even with certain rules in place, the ability to rationally analyze situations is crucial. How do we decide when face such issues. How do we determine what is “just”, “right” and “proper” in these and other instances? Choosing between right vs. right is not easy like choosing between right and wrong for business manager. On many occasion managers also choose between two wrongs . Managerial decision (or dilemmas) simply does not depend on "do the right thing", or "always tell the truth". On the surface one can argue that there is another right thing which is not done but in complex business situations the action is morally justified. . Mangers analyze the situation and find solution which is win-win for both the parties and most practical. Application of ethical theories help them to justify their action. Moral dilemmas Many times we feel stuck when confronting a moral problem. Only a few options come to mind, none of them very appealing. In fact, our most immediate association with the word “moral” seems to be the word “dilemma”, Moral dilemmas. We are supposed to have two and only two choices or any way only a few and often neither choice is much good. We can only pick the “lesser of two evils.” But, hey, that’s life. Or so we’re told. Is it? In all seriousness: is it? How many alleged dilemmas are actually only what logicians call “false dilemmas”? How many times, when we seem stuck, do we just need a little more imagination? For one thing, mightn’t there be some ready ways of multiplying options; of simply thinking up other possibilities, options we might not have considered? And how about rethinking the problem itself, so that it might be headed off in the future, or transformed into something more easily resolved? How much farther might we be able to go in ethics if we approached it with a little more creativity? Teleology The term teleology is derived from the Greek word “telos” which means, “end” or “purpose”. According to this theory the concept of right, wrong and duty are subordinated to the concept of end or purpose of the action. This is also called consequentialist theory. Which suggest that ethical reasoning concentrate on the consequence of human action, and all actions are evaluated in terms of the extent to which they achieve desirable results. Deontology The term deontology comes from the Greek Word “deon” means “duty”. According to the deontologist the rules and principles are crucial for guiding human action.They believe that ethical reasoning should concern activities that are rationally motivated and apply universally to all human action. Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) attempted to discover the rational principle that would stand as a categorical imperative grounding all other ethical judgments. The imperative would have to be categorical rather than hypothetical, or conditional, since true morality should not depend on our individual likings and disliking or on our abilities and opportunities. These are historical “accidents”; any ultimate principle of ethics must transcend them . Among the various formulations of the categorical imperative, two are particularly worth noting. 1)Always act in such a way that you can also will that the maxim of your action should become a universal law. 2)Or act so that you treat humanity, both in your own person and in that of another, always as an end and never merely as a means. Thus morality is seen as being an objective requirement, independent of what anyone may want. Although ultimately these are formally equivalent, the first illustrates the need for moral principles to be universalizable. The second points to the radical distinction to be made between things and persons, and emphasizes the necessity of respect for persons. Kant’s theory is an example of a deontological or duty-based ethics. It judges morality by examining the nature of actions and the will of agents rather than goals achieved. (Roughly, a deontological theory looks at inputs rather than outcomes). One reason for the shift away from consequences to duties is that, in spite of our best efforts, we cannot control the future. We are praised or blamed for actions within our control, and that includes our willing, not our achieving. This is not to say that Kant did not care about the outcomes of our actions-we all wish for good things. Rather Kant insisted that as far as the moral evaluation of our actions was concerned, consequences did not matter. Note that universalizability is not the same as universality. Kant’s point is not that we would all agree on some rule if it is moral. Instead, we must be able to will that it be made universal; the idea is very much like the golden rule – “Do unto others, as you would have them do unto you.” If you cannot will that everyone follow the same rule, your rule is not a moral one. The principle of universalizability and reversibility. Utilitarianism Utilitarianism was first formulated by Jeremy Bentham(1748-1832) and it’s foremost proponent was a student of Bentham’s John Stuart Mill(1806-1873). Bentham and J.S. Mill both criticized Kant. They asked “do we really care what a persons intentions are if we get hurt or benefit?” Bentham said, for the most part, we focus on the utility of actions. Utility: an act or thing has utility for a person if it makes them happy or brings pleasure or decreases pain. Bentham addressed this problem by proposing a “hedonistic calculus” in which the good ness or badness of an action would be calculated based on a sophisticated analysis of each potential pleasure’s (and pain’s) “intensity, duration, certainty or uncertainty, propinquity or remoteness, fecundity, and the purity of the value in question”. When these variables were figured in, Bentham said, reasonable people would with some accuracy be able to distinguish between low-yield and high-yield pleasures, to assess the relative (if not absolute) preferability of actions based on the ‘units” of pleasure and pain. If you could count, you could tell right from wrong. As a straightforward, materialistic approach to moral questions, utilitarianism has proved remarkably durable, largely because as Bentham and his followers pointed out the hedonistic calculus, with all its imprecision, is a fairly accurate metaphor for the way the nonphilosopher compares choices anyway, all the time. “Utilitarianism”, De George says, “is simply the result of making explicit the ways we ordinarily argue about policies, laws, and actions”. To the business professional this should be obvious. When you use any type of cost-benefit analysis, you are employing utilitarian thinking. And this is appropriate. If you want to know whether a given decision is ethical or not, it makes sense to ask how much good (pleasure) and how much bad (pain) it will bring, and then compare the two. It’s done all the time, and it works. But there are problems with this ledger approach to ethics. Let us address the two most serious ones: the likelihood that subjective bias will distort the calculation, and the utilitarian’s incomplete explanation of how a balance sheet on morals serves justice. Subjective bias. Critics of utilitarianism say that in calculating the net sum of good and bad in a potential action, I am not likely to be dispassionate and impartial, but to weight my own happiness more heavily than that of others. The injunction to promote the general good may be ignored, consequently, if it conflicts with what I see as my own pleasure. Moreover, I am likely to make my own case special, to make myself an exception to every utilitarian rule. That this is no idle apprehension we see in business every day. It’s a generally moral action, or that the distributiors of defective merchandise see the greatest good for the greatest number in the crapshoot they play with their products. To every manager faced with the choice of honoring the general good or of honoring his own good by increasing profits, the temptation is strong to weight the scales. To Bentham and his chief apologist, the philosopher John Stuart Mill, this was a manageable problem. Yes, they admitted, the hedonistic calculus could be perverted. But so could every other system. “Is utility the only creed,” Mill asked in his 1863 tract Utilitarianism, “which is able to furnish us with excuses for evil doing, and means of cheating our own conscience?” …………….. With the proper education, the early utilitarians were convinced, rational individuals would understand the ultimate conjunction between their personal happiness and that of the greatest number. With the proper education, they would see thing impartially and act well. Hedonism “How do we measure pleasure?” Bentham proposed we start by naming our units of measure: Hedons: Units of pleasure Dolors: units of pain Analogy with determining which of two rooms is the largest – we need a unit of measure or a yardstick, and a method of calculating the total space in each room in order to determine the largest room) . 1.Anticipation/Certainty 2. Intensity, 3.Duration 4.Remoteness (doing for others) (all the above provide a means of measuring immediate pleasure/pain). 5.Secondary effects – some pains produce pleasure and vice versa 6.Extent: how far reaching (how many people does it affect). So, 1-5 measure the aspects of pleasure for an individual, while 6 accounts for the group (society, all sentient beings) Hedonistic Calculus: 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. Start with the individual most affected Quantify the immediate pleasure Quantify the immediate pain Quantify the secondary pleasure/pain. Grand total for that individual Repeat steps 1-5 for all affected Repeat for every possible alternative act Principle of Utility: Utilitarianism focus on the consequences of actions – with an eye toward maximizing happiness/utility. Act Utilitarianism and Rule Utilitarianism: Act Utilitarianism: “Do those acts which will result in the greatest good for the greatest number of people”. The Rule Utilitarianism: “Follow those rules, the following of which will result in the greatest good for the greatest number”….(You do the calculus once on a proposed rule, and then follow the rule). ` The Act Utilitarian may allow rules to be used; but conceives of a rule like “Tell the Truth” as follows Telling the truth is generally for the greatest general good” But the Rule Utilitarian conceive of this as : Our always telling the truth is for the greatest general good” Or “It is for the greatest good if one always tell the truth”