Download The lattice structure of quantum logics

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts

Renormalization group wikipedia , lookup

Bohr–Einstein debates wikipedia , lookup

Bohr model wikipedia , lookup

Coherent states wikipedia , lookup

Quantum decoherence wikipedia , lookup

Lattice Boltzmann methods wikipedia , lookup

Quantum field theory wikipedia , lookup

Tight binding wikipedia , lookup

Quantum dot wikipedia , lookup

Path integral formulation wikipedia , lookup

Density matrix wikipedia , lookup

Atomic theory wikipedia , lookup

Measurement in quantum mechanics wikipedia , lookup

Copenhagen interpretation wikipedia , lookup

Quantum entanglement wikipedia , lookup

Quantum fiction wikipedia , lookup

Quantum computing wikipedia , lookup

Many-worlds interpretation wikipedia , lookup

Bell's theorem wikipedia , lookup

Orchestrated objective reduction wikipedia , lookup

History of quantum field theory wikipedia , lookup

Quantum machine learning wikipedia , lookup

Symmetry in quantum mechanics wikipedia , lookup

Quantum teleportation wikipedia , lookup

Hydrogen atom wikipedia , lookup

Quantum key distribution wikipedia , lookup

Max Born wikipedia , lookup

EPR paradox wikipedia , lookup

Quantum group wikipedia , lookup

Quantum state wikipedia , lookup

Canonical quantization wikipedia , lookup

Interpretations of quantum mechanics wikipedia , lookup

T-symmetry wikipedia , lookup

Hidden variable theory wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
A NNALES DE L’I. H. P., SECTION A
K RYSTYNA B UGAJSKA
S LAWOMIR B UGAJSKI
The lattice structure of quantum logics
Annales de l’I. H. P., section A, tome 19, no 4 (1973), p. 333-340
<http://www.numdam.org/item?id=AIHPA_1973__19_4_333_0>
© Gauthier-Villars, 1973, tous droits réservés.
L’accès aux archives de la revue « Annales de l’I. H. P., section A » implique
l’accord avec les conditions générales d’utilisation (http://www.numdam.
org/legal.php). Toute utilisation commerciale ou impression systématique
est constitutive d’une infraction pénale. Toute copie ou impression de ce
fichier doit contenir la présente mention de copyright.
Article numérisé dans le cadre du programme
Numérisation de documents anciens mathématiques
http://www.numdam.org/
Ann. Inst. Henri
Vol. XIX,
Section A :
Poincaré,
n° 4, 1973,
Physique théorique.
p. 333
The lattice structure of quantum
Krystyna BUGAJSKA
logics
Slawomir BUGAJSKI
Katowice, Poland
ABSTRACT. - A solution of the question of the lattice structure for quanlogics is proposed. It is achieved by a construction of a natural embeddof
ing the logic into a complete lattice, preserving all essential features of
the logic. Special cases of classical mechanics and the standard form of
quantum mechanics are investigated.
tum
1. INTRODUCTION
The lattice property for quantum logics is one of puzzling questions
of the logical approach. Usually we assume the logic to be an orthomodular,
complete ortholattice without any further substantiations. However,
a deeper analysis suggest, that this property is neither obvious nor natural. The problem is important, because of the basic role played by the
lattice property in the logical approach. Two possible ways out arises:
(i) to give a clear phenomenological interpretation to the lattice joins
and meets in quantum logics, or (ii) to derive the lattice property from
others, more plausible assumptions.
Concerning the first possibility, it is probable, that the property in
question has no satisfactory interpretation in terms of experimental operations (see Mac Laren’s discussion in [9], p. 11-12); the recent attempt
of Jauch and Piron [7] in this direction is not entirely conclusive [11].
The second way is preferred by some authors (for example [2], [9], [6], [12].
Newertheless, usually assumed postulates to imply the desired structure
seem to be not more convincing than the derived property itself.
In this paper we propose a solution of the problem in question not by
forcing the logic to possess a complete lattice structure, but by constructing
Annales de l’Institut Henri Poincaré - Section A - Vol.
XIX,
n° 4 - 1973.
334
K. BUGAJSKA AND S. BUGAJSKI
natural extension of the logic into complete lattice. Such extended logic
appears to be a good substitute for original one and possesses all its essential features. Our « critical » assumption if any, is the von Neumann’s
projection postulate-unquestionable in the common opinion, but criticized by some prominent philosophers and theorists (e. g. [5]). The somewhat similar extension was previously discussed by the authors [3] on a
quite different axiomatic basis.
In the next section we collect our assumptions. They are formulated
in the technical language of the logical approach. Definitions of the used
terms one can find in some other papers (e. g. [10], [12]).
a
2. ASSUMPTIONS
Let J5f denote the logic of given physical system. The fundamental
of j~f are discussed in many papers; the reader is referred to
the book of Mackey [8] for a justification of the first postulate:
properties
is an orthomodutar 03C3-ortho-poset.
This hypothesis has a good tradition in the quantum logic approach
and is not questioned.
The next assumption states a connection between the set of atoms d
of J~f and the set of pure states of the system.
POSTULATE 1.
a set g of probability measures on L (the
such
that:
(i) g is separating; (ii) for any b ~ L there
of pure states),
such that a(b)
exists
1; (iii) there exists an one-to-one mapping car :
~ -~ d with property: a(b)
1,
implies car (a) ~ b.
The following supposition looks very natural: every state is a mixture
(countable or not) of pure states. The first assertion of postulate 2 may
be treated as a consequence of this not precise, but plausible statement.
As regards (iii), this property essentially states, that one can unambiguously
identify the pure state in a single yes-no measurement.
Observe, that postulate 2 implies the atomicity of J~f and the existence,
car (a).
of one and only one pure state a, such that a
for any a
the
usual
Our next assumption is essentially
projection postulate of
mechanics
:
quantum
POSTULATE 2. - There exists
set
=
=
=
0 then there exists one
POSTULATE 3. - Let bE J5f and a E ~. If
1 and a(b)
a [car (/?)].
and only one pure state f3 such that f3(b)
The projection postulate (in many, seemingly non-related formulations)
is one of the most popular axioms in the quantum logics approach, see [4]
for further remarks and examples.
Postulate 3 completes our list of needed assumptions.
=
=
Annales de l’Institut Henri Poincaré - Section A
LATTICE STRUCTURE OF
335
QUANTUM LOGICS
3. THE EMBEDDING
Let
us
introduce
some
notations. If M is
a
subset of
orthocomplement of a E 2. In the sequel
simple properties of operations~, ~’ collected in
with a’-the
The application of the
of closure operation the
we
then
shall
use some
afte the operationv gives a kind
of H. C. Moore [1]. It is the content of
operation D.
one
We define the extended logic Ef as the set of all « closed » (in the sense
of above closure operation) subsets of 2. It is easy to see (the reader is
referred to [1] for the general theorem), that Ei is a complete lattice under
the partial ordering by inclusion, with lattice joins and meets defined
(M, N e F) as (M u N)B7~ and M n N resp.
One can introduce a natural orthocomplementation in J~. Indeed, the
possesses needed properties:
operation M - M’~ for
not exist any element a of 2 such that
Thus
e-the
greatest element of
except
Proof: (i) Obviously, there does
a E
and
a E
MV,
Is a consequence of lemma 1. (iii) (M’~)’6
We summarize the obtained results in
(ii)
= (M")V~ = M~ =
M.
D
COROLLARY 1. - The extended logic ~ is a complete, atomic ortholattice.
The relation between 2 and !P is clear. Namely, the set a° for a E 2
is a close subset of
hence is a member of 2. The mapping of 2 into J~:
Vol. XIX, n° 4 - 1973.
336
K. BUGAJSKA AND S. BUGAJSKI
a ~ a° preserves all essential features of
extension of 2.
LEMMA 4.
-
Let a,
b,
a~ E
2,
i
E
2, thus that is the mentioned
I, I-some
set
of indices. Then:
(provided left hand side exists) .
Proof - The first assertion as well
. regards (iii), b6 = bV6 for any bE 2.
the second
The equality
as
one
is obvious. As
is easy to prove. Thus
So the above constructed embedding 2 -+ ,;l preserves the partial
ordering, the orthocomplementation and all existing joins (it also preserves all meets, of course, as a result of this). The extended logic would
be therefore a good substitute for the original one if only it were orthomodular. The orthomodularity is commonly accepted as a basic feature
of quantum logics and an eventual lack of it makes our construction unuseful. The next section is devoted to a demonstration of the orthomodularity
of J~.
4. THE
Before
QUESTION OF ORTHOMODULARITY
we come near
LEMMA 5.
Proof -
-
The
to the
problem,
we
examine
some
If a ~ A and b~L then there exists a
projection postulate implies the existence
properties
of 2.
V b E 2.
of the atom al ,
sucn mai
Moreover,
Let c a a, b. We would like to demonstrate
V ai. Indeed, by the
orthomodularity, there is in 2 an element, say b1 , such that bi1 1 b and
c
bl V b. If one. applies the projection postulate to a and b, then one
can find the atom a 1 with the properties:
=
Annales de l’Institut Henri Poincaré - Section A
337
LATTICE STRUCTURE OF QUANTUM LOGICS
Thus 311
al and c ~ ai, b. It means, that b
in the set {a, b ~~ , i. e. b V a 1
b V a. D
=
is the least element
V al
=
If c e (b~ n
then two following
Obviously, b e (b~ n
c°
b~
c~
or
n
~
~
b° n d. Let us
possible:
consider the first one. By the projection postulate, there exist, for given
a
[(x(&#x26;) 5~ 0,
0], atoms ci and bl such that a(ci) a(c),
But a(b) ~ a(c 1 ) a(c) and a(c) ~
a(b). Thus a(b) a(c) for all a E f!jJ,
and the separating property of g assures b = c. If
b0394 n A,
Proof
cases
-
are
=
=
=
=
then c &#x3E; b by lemma 5. Thus
n
=
~)° implies c,&#x3E; b, i. e. b
a.
0
terms of
[9]).
=
aeb n.r~
The
proved lemma states, that
~ is atomistic
(atomic in
Moreover,
COROLLARY 2.
Proof
atomistic too.
-
- It suffices to note, that if M
then b E M is
equivalent
to
Let BM denote a maximal set of pairwise orthogonal atoms, contained
in M E
orthobasis of M). We demonstrate M to be determined by BM,
namely.
If M ~ and BM is an orthobasis of M, then B~0394M = M.
Proof - BM M, then B~6 MV6 = M. Let a be an atom belonging
to M B B~, and let a
car (a). One can prove, that if b E BM then x(b) ~ 0
LEMMA 7.
-
c
c
=
only for some countable subset of
there is an atom c, such that
BM, say {bl, b2
Atom a is orthogonal to all b E
b2
whole BM. Hence, it is no atom in M ’
to
COROLLARY 3.
Proof
Bi
-
extend
Let
-
M1
to some
Vol. XIX, n° 4 - 1973.
5i is
c
...
},
...
thus
}. By
c
is
lemma 1
orthogonal
and, by the atomicity
orthomodular.
M2
and
orthobasis
Bi be an orthobasis of MI. One
B2 of M2. Obviously,
B2.
can
Let
338
B3
i.
K. BUGAJSKA AND S. BUGAJSKI
All elements
B2" Bl and M3
B3 c B1° , By applying lemmas 1 and
=
e.
thus
=
M3
is
orthogonal
to
of B3 are orthogonal to
2 we obtain
B1,
Mi. Moreover,
This proves the orthomodularity
0
The above corollary solves the question of
orthomodularity
for
J~.
5. CONCLUSION
Thus
we
have
proved the following.
THEOREM 1.
satisfy postulates 1-3, then there exists an orthoand a natural embedding of L
modular, complete, atomic ortholattice
into fl, preserving the partial ordering, the orthocomplementation and all
joins of ~.
One can treat !i as a new, extended logic of the system, satisfying all
The described extension
regularity conditions usually assumed for
procedure takes, however, into considerations some new elements, with
no counterparts in « experimental questions »
concerning the system.
It is the usual price paid for an application of a regular mathematical
structure to a description of some features of reality. Theoretical physics
provide numerous examples of that.
An application of the obtained results to the problem of linear representation of quantum logic will be a subject of subsequent paper of the
authors.
6. T W O SPECIAL CASES
The problem of lattice structure for 2 becomes remarkably simpler
in two special cases of interest: (i) any two elements of 2 split (the case
of classical mechanics); (ii) 2 is separable, i. e. any set of pairwise orthogonal elements of 2 is countable (the case of the standard quantum
mechanics).
In the first case, 2 appears to be a Boole’an algebra, hence it is a lattice.
If 2 is assumed to be not complete, then the described extension is not
trivial. Our embedding theorem holds in this case with weaker assumptions :
THEOREM 1 (i).
any two elements of
If
2 split, then
-
an
atomic, orthomodular orthoposet and
the thesis
of theorem I holds.
Annales de l’Institut Henri Poincaré - Section A
339
LATTICE STRUCTURE OF QUANTUM LOGICS
of ~ and the embedding are quite analogous
above ones. We must prove the orthomodularity of !l only. Any
of J~f,
b, c E 2 split, i. e. there exist pairwise orthogonal elements b 1 ,
then bi = 0 and b c.
such that b = bl V d, c
ci V d. Let c E (b~ n
Thus 2 is atomistic. Now the orthomodularity of 4 readily follows. D
In the second case we also do not need the set
Observe, that the
without
formulated
making any reference to
projection postulate may be
transition probabilities:
Proof The construction
to the
=
then there exist unique atoms
and a
POSTULATE 3’.
a2
such that
and
a
b’,
al V a2 .
This is the Varadarajan’s version [13]; for further discussion see [4].
The embedding theorem takes now the form :
THEOREM 1 (ii). - If 2 is separable, orthomodular, atomic
and the projection postulate 3’ holds in 2, then 2 is isomorphic
is in itself a complete lattice.
03C3-orthoposet
to
2, i. e. ~
Proof One can prove, in an analogous manner as for lemma 5, that if a
exists in
Moreover, let { cl, c2 ... ~
atom, then a V b with any b E
If
be an orthobasis of
By the orthomodularity, c=Ci1 V c2 V
is
an
....
and !e is atomistic. Now
a2 ... ~ be an orthobasis of M E 2.
The existence of such ao E M that
a2 V ...)ð. is contrary to
M
Hence
demonstrated
the just
(at V a2 V ...)~. D
properties
=
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
The authors express their
kind interest in this work.
[1]
[2]
[3]
[4]
[5]
[6]
gratitude
for Professor A. Trautman for his
G. BIRKHOFF, Lattice Theory, New York, 1948.
K. BUGAJSKA and S. BUGAJSKI, On the axioms of quantum mechanics (Bull. Acad.
Pol. Sc., Série des sc. math. astr. et phys., vol. 20, 1972, p. 231-234).
K. BUGAJSKA and S. BUGAJSKI, Description of physical systems (Reports on Math.
Phys., vol. 4, 1973, p. 1-20).
K. BUGAJSKA and S. BUGAJSKI, The projection postulate in quantum logics (Bull. Acad.
Pol. Sc., Série des sc. math., astr. et phys., vol. 21, 1973, p. 873-877).
M. BUNGE, Foundations of Physics, Springer Verlag, Berlin-Heibelberg-New York,
1967.
S. GUDDER, A superposition principle in physics (J. Math. Phys., vol. 11, 1970, p. 1037-
1040).
Vol. XIX, n° 4 - 1973.
340
[7]
[8]
[9]
[10]
[11]
[12]
[13]
K. BUGAJSKA AND S. BUGAJSKI
J. M. JAUCH and C. PIRON, On the structure of quantal proposition systems (Helv. Phys.
Acta, vol. 42, 1969, p. 848-849).
G. W. MACKEY, The mathematical foundations of quantum mechanics, W. A. Benjamin
Inc. New York, Amsterdam, 1963.
M. D. MACLAREN, Notes on axiom for quantum mechanics, Argonne National Laboratory Report ANL-7065, 1965.
M. J. MACZY0143SKI, Hilber space formalism of quantum mechanics without the Hilbert
space axiom (Reports on Math. Phys., vol. 3, 1972, p. 209-219).
W. OCHS, On the foundations of quantal proposition systems (Z. Naturforsch., vol. 27a,
1972, p. 893-900).
J. C. T. POOL, Baer-semigroups and the logic of quantum mechanics (Commun. math.
Phys., vol. 9, 1968, p. 118-141).
V. S. VARADARAJAN, Geometry of quantum theory, vol. I, Van Nostrand Co, Princeton, N. J., 1968.
(Manuscrit
reçu le 3
mars
1973) .
Annales de l’Institut Henri Poincaré - Section A