* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Questioning the Individual under Capitalism: Alienation and
History of the social sciences wikipedia , lookup
World-systems theory wikipedia , lookup
Postdevelopment theory wikipedia , lookup
Collectivist anarchism wikipedia , lookup
Development economics wikipedia , lookup
Development theory wikipedia , lookup
Frankfurt School wikipedia , lookup
Depleted community wikipedia , lookup
Character mask wikipedia , lookup
Anthropology of development wikipedia , lookup
Marx's theory of human nature wikipedia , lookup
Creative destruction wikipedia , lookup
Criticisms of the labour theory of value wikipedia , lookup
Marxist philosophy wikipedia , lookup
Historical materialism wikipedia , lookup
Political economy in anthropology wikipedia , lookup
Reproduction (economics) wikipedia , lookup
Questioning the Individual under Capitalism: Alienation and the Iron Cage Derya Güler Aydın* Abstract: The capitalist system is inherently unstable and open to change, and most of the destructive tendencies of the system depend on its internal variables. Capitalism commodifies labor, which is the basic element of production as Marx put forward in his analysis, and it imprisons the individual in the iron cage of rational bureaucracy as Weber argues. Such a case can be regarded as unexpected consequences of rational behavior. In this study, Marx’s theory of crisis will be analyzed taking the instability of the capitalist system as the basis on the one hand, and the fact that capitalism is a system that mostly leads to unintended consequences and can dehumanize the individual within the process of capitalist development, will be scrutinized on the other hand. Key Words: Marx, alienation, Weber, iron cage, dynamic instability. INTRODUCTION The capitalist system is inherently unstable and the source of its instability is its internal dynamics. These internal dynamics and changes, which involve economic and non-economic elements, may produce consequences that will prepare the end of the system in the capitalist development process. As the economic sphere is an element of the social field, problems in the economic sphere should be investigated without being isolated from the social sphere. Although the thought that the development and dynamic change process of the capitalist system may bring its own end has so far been approached from very different aspects, this paper will attempt to analyze and discuss Marx and Weber’s studies. The capitalist development process will be discussed not only from the economic aspect, but also in terms of society as a whole for both philosophers. The study argues that the capitalist system has laid the foundation for an adverse consequence that ‘dehumanizes’ the individual. What should be deducted from this situation, which is expressed as unintended consequences of rational behavior, is: In the essence of the * Dr., Lecturer, Hacettepe University, FEAS, Department of Economics. TODAĐE’s Review of Public Administration, Volume 4 No 2 June 2010, p .21-38. 22 TODAĐE’s Review of Public Administration rational individual model lays the idea that self-interested individuals ensure the best consequences for society. The loss of human values by individuals, who act by themselves with self-seeking and hedonistic motivation, i.e. their dehumanization, can be described as the unintended consequence of rationality, which is the prerequisite of the capitalist development process. In other words, in Marx and Weber, the unintended consequences of rationality are the emphasis laid on the fact that the absolute goal should not be the institutions, but the humans themselves. The study has no intention of bringing these two philosophers closer or, reducing one of them to the other. The study, taking as the starting point Marx and Weber, who had quite different views at epistemological and ontological level, intends to lay emphasis on the ‘dehumanization of the individual’, the basic fact about capitalism. As the process of dehumanization of the individual is a product of capitalist development, the study will discuss the capital accumulation process and the crises caused by this process as well. The process of dehumanization, which is conceptualized as ‘alienation” by Marx and ‘iron cage’ by Weber, can be defined as not only the dissolution of the functioning of capitalism in the economic sphere, but also the dissolution of its social fabric and institutional structure. Though Marx and Weber represent two different ways of thinking, their fields of study are modern economics and the capitalist organization of society. The analysis of the capitalist economy and the form of society bases itself on the active individual in an economic sense. In brief, the theme of Marx and Weber’s scientific research is “capitalism”. The problem of capitalism and contemporary man raises the question ‘what makes human a human?’ The obvious intention of the Communist Manifesto is practical-political, while the intention of Weber’s studies in the sociology of religion is theoretical-historical (Löwith, 1982: 20). Reserving this important distinction, this study overemphasizes “the theme of the dehumanization” of the individual taking Marx and Weber as the starting point. With regard to capitalism, Marx directly and Weber indirectly present the nature of ‘economy’ that prevails humans. This situation necessitates a critical analysis of modern man in the bourgeois society. The human, who is the key actor of the capital accumulation process and the development of capitalism, is prevailed over by his own products and this becomes the major problem of the capitalist development process. Marx argues that this problem can be solved when a Questioning the Individual under Capitalism: Alienation and the Iron Cage 23 human becomes conscious of his/her power of action, while Weber only defines it. Therefore, it can be said that Marx proposes a therapy, while Weber only offers a diagnosis (Löwith, 1982: 20). Capitalism, in its essence, is a dynamic system open to change that leads to instabilities. Therefore, this study attempts to reveal the connection of the instability of the capitalist system in the economic sphere with the social sphere based on the studies of Marx and Weber, who make a dynamic change analysis with a historical approach and focuses on how and in which way capitalism dehumanizes the individual. The first section of the study will investigate the process that leads to the dehumanization of an individual in the context of Marx’s theory of alienation. Alienation is nourished by internal dynamics that appear in the capital accumulation process and increase the instability tendency in capitalism. In this context, the issue of alienation that emerges in the capital accumulation process or the dehumanization of an individual in the capitalist development process seems to be too extensive and important to be restricted to the economic sphere. In the second section of the study, rational bureaucratic capitalism and Weber’s metaphor of the iron cage caused by rational bureaucratic capitalism will be analyzed. CAPITALISM AND ALIENATION Marx’s purpose is to set forth the laws of motion of the capitalist system. The most distinctive characteristic of Marx’s analysis is that it approaches production relations in the context of the conflicting and struggling relationship between labor and capital (the generator of surplus value and appropriator of surplus value). Another important feature of Marx’s analysis is its historicity. Marx explains the fundamental dynamics of social change by taking the forces and means of production and the conflict between them as the starting point. “In the social production of their existence, men inevitably enter into definite relations, which are independent of their will, namely relations of production appropriate to a given stage in the development of their material forces of production. The totality of these relations of production constitutes the economic structure of society, the real foundation, on which arises a legal and political superstructure and to which correspond definite forms of social consciousness. The mode of production of material life conditions the general process of social, political and intellectual life. It is not the consciousness of men that determines their existence, but their social existence that determines their consciousness. At a certain stage of development, the material productive forces of society come into conflict with the existing relations of production or – this 24 TODAĐE’s Review of Public Administration merely expresses the same thing in legal terms – with the property relations within the framework of which they have operated hitherto. From forms of development of the productive forces these relations turn into their fetters. Then begins an era of social revolution. The changes in the economic foundation lead sooner or later to the transformation of the whole immense superstructure” (Marx, 1970: 20-21). The mode of production of societies (base structure) determines their conscious (superstructure) (Marx, 1970). It can be asserted in view of these expressions that in Marx’s analysis productive forces and production relations constitute the basis of historical change. According to Marx’s understanding of history, capital determines its historical preconditions, while his analyses on capitalism put forward the dehumanization process of an individual and the alienation process. The essence of man can remain the same in different historical periods, but its existence is determined by material conditions. In this sense, it can be said that in his work ‘Capital’, Marx discovers the conflict between the existence and essence of man under capitalism (Özel, 2009: 197-198). Under capitalism, man not only alienates himself from the product of his labor, but also from his potential power of action and thus, is dehumanized. According to Marx, the capitalist system can be described by four institutional and behavioral factors. The first of these elements is that production is undertaken for the purpose of market sales; the second is the existence of private ownership of the means of production; the third is the majority of individuals that are forced to sell their labor in the market to survive and the fourth is economic decision-making agents’ efforts towards rational behavior. The primary characteristic of capitalism is that production is done for market sales. This means that under the capitalist system the individual does not know who will consume the product of his labor and therefore, the relation between the producer and consumer is established by the market. As a result, under capitalism, the economic and social relations between individuals transform into inter-product relations via the market and thus, individual requirements become dependent on the impersonal forces of the market. The second characteristic of capitalism is the existence of private ownership of the means of production. In capitalist society, while a specific class of society owns the raw materials needed for production and has the right to use the means and tools of production, other classes have no rights to them. Under such a structure, the owners of the means of production, instead of directly participating in the pro- Questioning the Individual under Capitalism: Alienation and the Iron Cage 25 duction process, take control of the management of production and the surplus value produced, while those lacking ownership are given the status of producer. That is to say, while the capitalist becomes the sovereign power as a result of ownership relations, he has no direct role in the control and management of the production of labor (Hunt, 1992: 5-6). As the laborer, who actually realizes the production does not possess the means of production, he can only get a part of the products of his labor. The surplus value of labor, which is the basic source of the capital accumulation process, is utilized by the capital owners. In this context, under capitalism, labor turns into a commodity bought and sold in the market place and can utilize only a certain part of it. Therefore, in the analysis, production relations deepen in such a way so as to cover the struggle between classes, and with this aspect they gain a social dimension. Another characteristic of capitalism is that individuals behave as rational beings in the economic sphere. Rationality, which is argued to be essential for the successful functioning of capitalism, suggests that the basic drive of an individual is utilitarianism/hedonism. In this context, under the capitalist system, rather than the method used by the capital owner to increase his profit, the amount of his profit assumes importance. Therefore, the surplus value seized by the capital owner through the means of production he owns and the distribution that comes as a result of it, are considered the outcome of individuals who act rationally. According to Marx, who analyzed the laws of motion of capitalism, while it involves economic conflicts on distribution on the one hand, capitalism is open to change and industrial development on the other hand. Capitalism is a system in pursuit of increased profit margins, which is rendered legitimate by individual rationality. This is the outcome of production made for change in the “market’. The realization of production for the purpose of change turns labor into a commodity subject to sale and purchase in the market just like other products. In Marx’s view, the conflicts the capital accumulation process involves and production for the market leads to alienation both for capital and labor (Elliott, 1984: 385-386). Marx has two different approaches towards capitalism. According to Marx, the first of these is that compared to the former modes of production, capitalism is a stew towards the freedom of individuals in the history of humanity. “It is one of the civilising aspects of capital that it enforces this surplus-labour in a manner and under conditions which are more advanta- 26 TODAĐE’s Review of Public Administration geous to the development of the productive forces, social relations, and the creation of the elements for a new and higher form than under the preceding forms of slavery, serfdom, etc.” (Marx, 1991: 819). Nevertheless, the second point that should be underlined is that capitalism prepares its own end as a result of its own internal conflicts and dehumanizes the individual in the production process. At this point, it is possible to define the capital accumulation process as creator, while the consequences of this process as destructive. While the capitalist system undergoes economic depressions in the economic development process, it leads the individual to a social depression by commodifying his labor. The source of this social depression or alienation and the source of economic crises faced in the capitalist system are the consequences of the internal conflicts of capitalism. Therefore, while examining the functioning and instability of capitalism, the economic sphere and social sphere should be jointly considered. Before discussing the issue of alienation, which emerges in the capital accumulation process, and which will be investigated in this study as the first consequence of the development process of the capitalist system, it will be helpful to briefly touch on Marx’s crisis theories in order to set forth the economic aspect of the instability of capitalism. Marx’s theories of crisis that put forth the dynamic, unstable nature of the capitalist system can be gathered under two headings: real and monetary theories. Marx approaches crisis as an economic theory, a political issue (Jacoby, 1975: 3-4). One of the most important characteristics of Marx’s analysis is that the effects of monetary and financial circulation on crises are not overlooked. In Volume III of Capital, Marx discusses money circulation processes and describes how credit and financial institutions affect the real processes (Marx, 1991: 566-567). Nevertheless, Marx argues that the factor that determines the social existence of an individual is not his labor, but the market value of his labor. Money is the basic tool of the circulation relationship between the producer and consumer. When money buys labor power and turns it into monetary labor, it becomes the fundamental instrument of the relationship between labor and capital. Marx maintains that money circulation can occur without crises, but the emergence of crises without money circulation is impossible (Roberts – Stephenson, 1985: 58). Therefore, in Marx’s view, money is an instrument that influences real processes and that has to be to taken into accout in real processes (Schuklian, 1999). His view is apparent from his assertion in The Power of Money in Bourgeois Questioning the Individual under Capitalism: Alienation and the Iron Cage 27 Society section of his work ‘Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844’ that money is the procurer between man’s need and the object, between his life and his means of life (Marx, 1976: 206). In law of the tendency of the rate of profit to fall, one of Marx’s theories of real crisis1, which demonstrates the instability of capitalism, the social consequences of the analysis are at the forefront as much as its economic consequences. It is possible to say that in his theory of profit squeeze, the basic emphasis is laid on the conflict between labor and capital. The fundamental difference between these two theories is that in the theory of profit squeeze, the labor and capital emphasis of crisis is replaced by the tension between wages and profits and every factor that increases wages leads the system to crisis at the point where that it decreases the profit (Sweezy, 1968). Under the inter-sector inconsistency theory and the underconsumption theory, which are defined as realization crises that break out when the capital owner fails to sell his product at its real value, the basic problem is the halt in production by the capital owner due to the emergence of overproduction or underconsumption as a result of products made by various sectors in the right amounts (Shaikh, 1978). The point that should be taken into account in the monetary and real crisis theories is that the economic variables in the analyses, such as labor-capital, surplus value and profit margins, are at the same time variables of a social nature. Therefore, Marx’s analyses2 consider laborers and capitalists different social classes in qualitative terms and focus on the problem of distribution based on the existence of surplus value. In this context, the issue of alienation, which is the second pillar of Marxian theories maintaining that crisis originates from the conflict between the economic and social dimensions and, which is defined as the crisis of individual in the study. In the capital accumulation process, while the capitalist system goes through real and monetary crises, it also leads to the alienation of the individual to the product of his labor and himself. While 1 2 For detailed information on Marx’s theories of crisis, see:. Güler Aydın, 2008. As it is known, there is no qualitative difference between labor and capital under neoclassical tradition. As there is no surplus value left over in total production, distribution is not a problem. In their actions based on benefit maximization, each and every decision-making agent strives to achieve the best for themselves and society. In this context, the factors that may cause crises are external factors. Marx’s analysis that attributes crisis to internal variables makes the analysis dynamic on one hand and leads to more realistic analyses in terms of the individual and society. 28 TODAĐE’s Review of Public Administration exploring the issue of alienation, Marx focuses on the form of existence of the individual in the capitalist system and argues that labor turns into a commodity to become an object within capitalist property relations. This objectification process that can be described as the crisis of subject or the social dimension of the capitalist depression leads to the consideration of the social aspect of crisis undergone in economics as well. In the capitalist society, the individual is trapped in the inter-relations of goods produced for exchange as a result of market relations and is objectified. In this respect, Marx’s analysis of capitalism describes not only the ‘dehumanization3 process of the capitalist system, but also of the individual, who exists in this system, as the creator of the system. The concept of alienation, which is defined as the dehumanization of the individual, appears in its two forms in Marx’s Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844 (1976). The first one is the alienation of man, isolating him from nature and his creation of a new nature for himself in the cultural-social sphere. Such a form of alienation that refers to a break from nature can be considered positive alienation in terms of the existence and the development of man. The second form of alienation is the alienation inherent in the capitalist system, which is specific to this system. As a consequence, man alienates himself from his nature/labor/product. In other words, man alienates himself from, his labor, social relations, world and life. Even though the private property relations on the means of production lies behind alienation, this situation assumes more importance particularly under capitalism, where labor power turns into a commodity. Under the capitalist system, as the worker is broken off from the means of production, he turns into a commodity bought by the capital owner in the market place. At the end of the production process, the worker gets only a part of the products of his labor, just enough to reproduce himself and thus the surplus value produced is seized by the capital owner. The surplus value can be asserted to be the consequence of private ownership on the one hand and alienation and alienated labor on the other hand. In his sense, the relation of alienation and private ownership continuously reproduces itself, thus breaking off labor from human values and turning it into a commodity. 3 Holloway takes as his starting point what he terms the 'scream': that is the transformation of the 'power over' to the 'power to' and brings an interesting approach to the dehumanization of the individual and alienation. For detailed information, see: “Change the World Without Taking Power”, 2006. Questioning the Individual under Capitalism: Alienation and the Iron Cage 29 In his work Capital I, Marx attempts to explain the material basis of man’s alienation from his own nature by the concept of fetishism that emerges as an outcome of market relations. According to Marx, once an individual begins to work for others in any way, his labor takes a social form. As soon as labor acquires a social nature, that is to say, when products are produced for the market, the products enter a relation both with one another and labor itself. Marx calls this process the fetishism of commodities, which attaches itself to the products of labor, as soon as they are produced as commodities, and which is therefore inseparable from the production of commodities (Marx, 1990: 165). In fact, it should be borne in mind that commodity fetishism is the natural outcome of alienation. The reason is that under this system, the alienation of man not only from the products of his labor, but also from his own labor power, which represents his total physical and mental capacity, is the consequence of the transformation of his power into a ‘commodity’. In other words, the alienation process under capitalism leads to the ‘fetishism‘ and ‘reification‘4 processes. The individual in these processes is a dehumanized being deprived of his individual efficiency; in brief, he is a lost individual engulfed in rational rules. Therefore, in this study, alienation is presented as the initial state of dehumanization under rational capitalism. In this framework, ‘commodity fetishism’ comes first among Marx’s criticisms towards capitalism as a form of mode of production. As mentioned above, under the theory of commodity fetishism, the relation between the physical and social existence of man are reproduced via the relations between commodities and therefore, individuals begin to lose focus of their physical and social existence. According to Marx and Engels, “the production of ideas, of conceptions, of consciousness, is at first directly interwoven with the material activity and the material intercourse of men, the language of real life” (Marx Engels, 1970: 47). That is to say, under capitalism, which is a specific mode of production, the alienation process leads to reification and fetishism. Due to the reduction of relations between people to the relation between commodities, the social aspect of an individual is explained by the relation between commodities. Although private prop4 The commodification of the labor force describes a social relation, in which relations among individuals appear to be in the form of relations between objects, i.e. commodities. Under this fetishism, labor force, as an abstract category, becomes alienated from individuals who own it, and turns into a ‘thing’. (Lukacs, 1971: 83). In brief, this is a process, where social relationships between people are expressed as, mediated by and transformed into, objectified relationships between things (fethishism). 30 TODAĐE’s Review of Public Administration erty is a phenomenon seen in different periods, the factor that differentiates private property under capitalism is the alienation it causes. In summary, according to Marx, labor is severed from its human traits under the circumstances of the capitalist system and is transformed into an object. Man’s estrangement from his human values by the capitalist society denotes the capitalist society’s transformation of man in the context of the capitalist values of the society. In fact, this transformation, i.e. the fetishism process, leads to instability in the social fabric as well. Such a ‘dehumanization’ process leads to conflicts in the capitalist society’s reproduction process itself as well. In other words, capitalism’s tendency to go through periodical crises does not stem only from the economic sphere. Alienation is also an important factor that increases the instability of capitalism in the social sphere. Therefore, crises faced by capitalism from time to time should not be considered merely a consequence of economic depression, but also the depression of the individual and society. RATIONAL DEMOCRACY AND IRON CAGE The impacts of the economic development process on the individual or the effects of individual actions or motivations on economic actions bring integrity to economic and social activities. In his economic views and his studies conducted in the field of sociology, Weber took account of this integrity and with his ‘iron cage’ metaphor, he investigated the adverse effects of capitalism on the individual in such a way so as to overlap with Marx’s arguments on alienation. This section of the study will first focus on Weber’s views and then analyze the fundamental concepts that are believed to be related to the instability of capitalism. Weber’s ‘concept of ideal type’, “rationality and forms of rationality’, ‘bureaucracy and Ascetic Protestant Ethic’ and ‘iron cage’ come first among these concepts. There exist two Max Webers; the first is the one who is a liberal individualist and the basic issue that weighs on his mind is the trapping of the individual’s future in an iron cage in a predestined manner. This iron cage appears as a result of the irresistible power of products over the individual as a consequence of mechanization. That is to say, the iron cage, which Weber describes as the individual’s bleak destiny, emerges with mechanized petrification. The said petrification further deepens by bureaucratization, which is an outcome of rationalism. The other Weber is described as a man who never envisages any other world than his own, which is largely characterized by the rivalry Questioning the Individual under Capitalism: Alienation and the Iron Cage 31 of nation states (Löwith, 1982: 15). Considering such a difference, it should be noted that this study focuses on the first Weber. According to Weber, who is interested in the sociological aspect of economic facts, it will be appropriate to access the knowledge of economics and sociology via the interaction of these two fields. In his works, Weber maintained that while exploring the interaction of economic and social variables, economic theory should be examined in respect of not only economic facts, but also economic sociology and sociological facts. Recalling that the interaction of economic and non-economic factors are also taken into consideration in Marx’s crisis theories, it is possible to assert that while analyzing the capitalist system, both theorists adopted a viewpoint that went beyond the boundaries of pure theoretical analysis and built their analyses on a broader base. 5 While the interaction of economic and social events expands the framework of the analysis on the one hand, it makes analysis difficult on the other hand. For that reason, in his analysis, Weber asserted that what was important was to choose events and to establish a connection of meaning between the chosen events, and he described the instrument that would establish this connection as the “ideal type” (Sen, 1985: 7). According to Weber, capitalism was a historical concept of ideal type6 in the context of a few centuries of meaning connection. In this framework, Weber saw capitalism as a product of the rationalization process in Western countries from the Enlightenment Era up to the present and attempted to describe capitalism as a historical process based on accumulation and motive of profit. 5 6 Weber’s aim is to reveal the factors that ensure the continuation and motivation of capitalism. In his work The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism (1997), Weber, rather than detecting a causal relationship between protestantism and capitalism, investigated the effects of certain religious and ethical forms of thought on the economic system (Sen, 1985: 5). According to Weber, instead of a scientific system based on the same causal factors and effects, a study where the researcher describes the mutual effects of certain factors produces more efficient results in terms of economic facts. According to Löwith, Weber misunderstands himself, when he insists on the purely “methodological” significance of his “individualistic” and “rational” definition and denies its substantive character [i.e. its historical specificity] as well as its valuerelatedness. The value which sustains this definition (and the many others like it in Weber’s sociology) is basically that of freedom and autonomy. ‘The ideal-typical “construct” is based upon a human being who is specifically “free of illusions”, thrown back upon itself by a world which has become objectively meaningless (Löwith, 1982: 13). 32 TODAĐE’s Review of Public Administration Weber argues in the framework of economic actions that the analysis should move beyond the boundaries of theoretical economics to also include non-economic factors along with economic ones. To Weber, the type of individual, who acts rationally and is defined as homo economicus is specific to modern Western societies. He criticizes homo economicus for being an abstract individual, rather than a real life person. Weber defines economic action as ‘any peaceful exercise of an actor's control over resources, which is in its main impulse oriented toward economic ends,’ (Weber, 1995: 98). Rational economic action is a purposive, rationally planned economic action. Rationally planned economic action is the purposive and methodical use of instruments elevated to the peak of rationality under scientific assessments (Weber, 1995: 101). At this point, economics differ from sociology and other fields in terms of its boundaries of actions and economic action is restricted to the actions of rationally acting decision-making agents. However, a tradesman is not only influenced by the actions of potential consumers, but also legal, political and even ethical values (Weber, 1995). Such a unity of motivation of action, i.e. economic or non-economic, all actions based on action motivation, falls in the scope of ‘economic sociology’.7 Weber's work on economic behavior with rational action divides into two: individuals’ concrete rational action and rational behavior within abstract values. The concrete rationality of the individual refers to their rational choice among instruments, purposes and consequences. As abstract values are generally considered irrational, the rationality of individuals in terms of abstract values is used in the meaning of their attempt to act in a rational manner within the irrational values system. Throughout his studies, Weber focused on the nature, reasons and consequences of rationality. Kalberg (1980) proposes four different definitions of rationality based on Weber’s studies. The first of these is practical rationality, Practical rationality (is every way of life that views and judges worldly activity in relation to the individual's 7 Economic sociology is a field that attracts the interest of economists and sociologists in terms of the emergence and analysis of economic institutions. Although economic sociology is the field of sociologists, it includes the studies of many economists. In this sense, the first name that comes to mind is the economist Schumpeter. In his work ‘History of Economic Analysis’ (1954), Schumpeter puts forth that economic sociology should be attached importance to as much as economic history (Schumpeter, 1954: 9). The book, which consists of four chapters, investigates the institutional structure in the analyses of schools of economics from Ancient Greek times up to the present. For more information about economic sociology, see: Swedberg, 1991: 253-254. Questioning the Individual under Capitalism: Alienation and the Iron Cage 33 purely pragmatic and egoistic nature. The second type of rationality is theoretical rationality. Theoretical rationality involves a cognitive effort to master reality through increasingly abstract concepts rather than through action. Substantive rationality directly orders action into patterns through clusters of values. Substantive rationality makes calculation not only by rational instruments, but also taking into consideration traditional, political and class factors. These are, in a sense, irrational instruments of value and, substantive rationality has numerous criteria. The fourth type of rationality is formal rationality. Formal rationality involves the rational calculation of means to ends based on universally applied rules, regulations, and laws. Although practical, theoretical and substantive types of rationality have so far been observed in different societies; formal rationality was experienced only in the industrialization process in the West. In Weber’s studies, formal rationality is given more prominence, as it is compatible with the essence of Western capitalism and it defines maximum efficiency. In a formal rational system, almost all decisions and actions are built on a rational foundation (Weber, 1995: 130132). Weber, inspired by Nietzsche, sees the rational world as a disenchanted world. In this magical world, the rationalization process sometimes works in the opposite direction. To Weber, rationality refers to the action of abandoning a worldview based on values and ideals and purifying the world of its magic/spirit. Therefore, in rational thought, the only way to understand the world is the rationalistic way of thinking (Swatos, 1981: 120). Bureaucracies are organizations formed under the principle of formal rationality. The more official affairs become independent from love, hate and all incalculable personal feelings, the more bureaucracy gets closer to its intended nature. Weber lays down the relationship between capitalism and rationality as follows: capitalism refers to curbing irrational motives or balancing them in a rational manner. As bureaucratic tendencies increase, the framework of rational rules becomes more robust and, bureaucratization and rationality appear before us as factors that nourish each other. The rational entrepreneur, rational calculation, rational technology and rational law come first among factors that contributes to the development of capitalism. To Weber, none of these factors alone can be considered the factor that develops capitalism. Along with these, other factors that complete each and every factor, such as the rational spirit, agreements that ensure the rationalization of society and rational economic ethics, are needed (Weber, 2003: 352-354). In We- 34 TODAĐE’s Review of Public Administration ber’s view, the spirit of capitalism is nourished by the rational understanding of work. Weber characterizes the rational understanding of work by the ascetic spirit; he integrates the ambition to work and accumulate wealth for earthly things with protestant ethics. This spirit nourished by rationality is exposed to a danger. Weber lays emphasis on his danger, saying that material goods ‘should be worn like a light coat that can be easily cast aside’ (Weber, 1997: 159) and it can turn into ‘an iron cage’ over time. In other words, the capitalist spirit nourished by rationality will lead to the removal of all an individual’ personality in the course of time. At the point of evolution of the capitalist spirit, Weber’s concept of charisma should be touched on. Weber says the concept of charisma dates back to the past and there are numerous charismatic leaders in history. In Weber’s view, the origin of charisma differs from person to person. An individual, who is considered charismatic by a specific group of people, can be rejected by other groups of people. In general, charisma is said to come out in certain people as a consequence of a particular social movement. Charismatic leadership leads to irrational actions. In fact, charismatic authority is needed for the functioning of rationality and bureaucratic organization. A certain routinization and the disturbance felt because of it may cause irrational actions and after some time, it can be re-routinized. That is to say, it is the fate of charisma, whenever it comes into the permanent institutions of a community, to give way to powers of tradition or of rational socialization. This waning of charisma generally indicates the diminishing importance of individual action. And of all those powers that lessen the importance of individual action, the most irresistible is rational discipline (Weber, 1996: 98-99). One of the unintended consequences of rationality that takes place at the core of modernization is the routinization of charisma. Weber defines the routinization of charisma that improves in line with the increased rationality in the modernization process as the ‘disenchantment of the world". While, on the one hand, modernization, which is shaped on a rational bureaucratic basis, brings about wealth accumulation (an economically favorable effect), on the other hand, it leads to the withering of all manners of personality and personal capability (socially adverse effect) (Özel, 2007). Weber describes this state, which is considered a kind of mechanization, and, which is reinforced by the routinization of charisma, as the ‘iron cage’. Being trapped in the iron cage refers to the mechanization of an individual by being stripped of his every personal trait. It should be noted that Questioning the Individual under Capitalism: Alienation and the Iron Cage 35 the mechanization of the individual and commodification of labor means the same in terms of the dehumanization of the individual (Löwith, 1982). At his point, the following words by Weber are impressive: “No one knows who will live in this cage in the future, or whether at the end of this tremendous development entirely new prophets will arise, or there will be a great rebirth of old ideas and ideals, or, if neither, mechanized petrification, embellished with a sort of convulsive selfimportance. For the last stage of this cultural development, it might well be truly said: "Specialists without spirit, sensualists without heart; this nullity imagines that it has attained a level of civilization never before achieved” (Weber, 1997: 160). According to Ashley and Micheal (1990), Weber’s analysis points to a bleak destiny for individuals in modern society. Modern societies are enslaved by the bureaucratic organization founded on the formal rationality in the long-term, i.e. of capitalism itself. Weber argues that there is no escape from the iron cage metaphor in modern societies. Capitalism is a chaos, in which individuals strive to exist. This chaos can be said to have an ironic consequence, in respect of the fact that it leads to the loss of the individual’s human values over time. That is to say, under the capitalist system, individuals become involved in the relations determined by the market and individual behaviors are shaped according to the principles of capitalism. These behaviors, which are formed in accordance with the rules of the market or the rationality, lay the foundations for the dehumanization of the individual and in Weber’s analysis, breaking the individual from his human values is one of the inevitable consequences of modern capitalism. While capitalism rises above the principles of rationality, the individual gets trapped in an iron cage under bureaucratic rules. One of its most concrete signs is that under the capitalist system, the individual’s choices and abilities are most of the time suppressed due to the formal rational rules in his work life. In brief, under capitalism, individual relations are replaced by relations between commodities, as Marx maintains. Therefore, in modern societies, individuals seem to be bound by the chains of bureaucracy. In this regard, Weber attributes the bleak destiny of the individual determined by the capitalist system to the individual’s breaking from his values and human feelings, thus turning him into a cold, insensitive creature. The individual’s waning of personality and the charismatic leader becoming nonfunctional under capitalism that has emerged as a product of a historical process are important, as these are the products of formal ra- 36 TODAĐE’s Review of Public Administration tionality and in this sense, both situations can be considered unintended consequences of rationality (Weber, 1996: 97). That is to say, rational actions that constitute the basis of the capitalist development process have unintended consequences such as the dehumanization of the individual. In brief, Marx’s commodity fetishism and Weber’s iron cage metaphor discussed above are important in respect of their emphasis on the fact that the individual delegates his power of action to the market mechanism as an inevitable consequence of the capitalist development process. CONCLUSION According to Löwith (1982), Marx and Weber’s critical approaches towards capitalism can be discussed in the context of the concepts of alienation and rational capitalism. Particularly Marx’s analysis attempts to lay down the dynamics of bourgeois capitalism through a historical analysis. To Marx, the basic contradiction of the capitalist system is the conflict between labor and capital and the breaking of production and the labor force, the source of surplus value, from the product it produces and the alienation that emerges thereof, in other words, the transformation of the individual into an object bought and purchased in the market place in the production process. Every single economic variable used in Marx’s monetary and real crisis theories (laborcapital, surplus value, profit margins, realization, et.) is the internal and at the same time social variable of the systems. Marx attributes the problems of the capitalist system to its own dynamics; considers labor and capital as different social classes in qualitative terms and focuses on the distribution analysis based on the existence of surplus value. In this sense, Marx’s theories of crisis argue that crisis stems from the tension between the economic and social dimensions of the system and dehumanizes the individual with the alienation. This contradiction caused by the economic development process or this result that can be said to be the unintented consequences of rational intentions is highly important in respect of the fact that it portrays the individual’s state in the capitalist system. On the other hand, Weber, who puts forth the contradictions of modern rationality, argues that formal rationality, which is the spirit of modern capitalism, leads to the bureaucratization of human behavior via intense technical calculations and thus, to the petrification of indi- Questioning the Individual under Capitalism: Alienation and the Iron Cage 37 vidual actions. According to Weber, capitalist rationality also incorporates irrationality. That is to say, capitalist development, which is based on formal rationality, causes the loss of charismatic values, such as individual happiness, individual activity and decisiveness. In Weber’s expression, individuals get trapped in an iron cage in the capitalist development process in the course of time. The individual, who loses all his personality as result of rational bureaucracy, dehumanizes with modern capitalism. A rational purpose defined as the fulfillment of man’s needs leads to an unintended consequence, the dehumanization of the individual or his deprivation from his human values. It should be noted that the analyses on the causes and consequences of crises facing the capitalist system at certain times reveal that the crisis is not just economic; it may cause the crisis of the individual too. In this framework, the findings of the analyses of both Marx and Weber that point to the dehumanization of the individual as a consequence of the capitalist system is an issue that should be emphasized significantly. REFERENCES Ashley, D. - Micheal D. (1990), Sociological Theory: Classical Statements, Boston, Bacon, 1990. Elliot, J. E. (1984), “Karl Marx’s Theory of Socio-Institutional Transformation in Late- Stage Capitalism”, Journal of Economic Issues, Vol. 18, No: 2, p. 383-391. Güler Aydın, Derya (2008), “Kapitalizmin Đstikrarsız Doğası: K. Marx ve J. A. Schumpeter”, Hacettepe Üniversitesi Sosyal Bilimler Enstitüsü, Yayınlanmamış Doktora Tezi, 2008. Holloway, John (2006), Đktidar Olmadan Dünyayı Değiştirmek, (Çev. Pelin Sirol), Đletişim Yayınları, Đstanbul. Hunt E. K. (1992), History of Economic Thought: A Critical Perspective, Harper Collins Publisher. Jacoby, R. (1975), “The Politics of Crisis Theory: Toward A Critique Of Automatic Marxism II”, Telos, Vol. 23, p. 3-52. Kalberg, S. (1980), “Max Weber’s Types of Rationality: Cornerstones for the Analysis of Rationalization Process in History”, American Journal of Sociology, Vol. 85, p. 1145-1179. Lukacs, G. (1971), History and Class Consciousness: Studies in Marxist Dialectics, (Tr. R. Livingstone), Cambridge, Mass., The MIT Press. Löwith, Karl (1982), Max Weber and Karl Marx, London: George Allen & Unwin. Marx, Karl (1844), 1844 El Yazmaları, Sol Yayınları, Ankara, 1976. 38 TODAĐE’s Review of Public Administration Marx, Karl (1867), Capital, Volume I, Penguin Books, London, 1990. Marx, Karl (1894), Capital, Volume III, Penguin Books, London, 1991. Marx, Karl (1970), A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy, Maurice Dobb. (yay.), New York: International Publishers. Marx, Karl - F. Engels (1970), The German Ideology, C. J. Arthur (Yay.), New York International Publishers. Mommsen, W. J. (1989), “Capitalism and Socialism: Weber’s Dialogue with Marx”, The Political and Social Theory of Max Weber (Ed.), Basil Blackwell Ltd., p. 53-73. Özel, Hüseyin (2007), “Four Horsemen of the Apocalypse: Marx, Weber, Schumpeter, and Polanyi”, Economic Pluralism for the 21st Century adlı konferans tebliği, Utah, USA. Özel, Hüseyin (2009), Piyasa Ütopyası, BilgeSu Yayıncılık, Ankara. Roberts, C. P. - A. M. Stephenson (1985), Marx’s Theory of Exchange Alienation and Crisis, Hoover Institution Press, Standford University, California. Shaikh, Anwar (1978), “An Introduction to the History of Crisis Theories”, U.S. Capitalism in Crisis, New York: U.R.P.E, p. 219-241. Schumpeter, Joseph. A. (1954), History of Economic Analysis, London Allen and Unvin. Shuklian, S. (1999), “Karl Marx on the Foundations of Monetary Theory”, Working Paper, p.1-13. Sen, A. (1985), “Weber, Gramsci and Capitalism”, Social Scientist, Vol.13, No: 1, p. 3-22. Swatos, W. H. (1981), “The Disenchantment of Carisma: A Weberian Assesment of Revolution in a Rationalized Word”, Sociological Analysis, p. 119-136. Swedberg R. (1991), “Major Traditions of Economic Sociology”, Annual Review of Sociology, Vol.17, p. 251-276. Sweezy, Paul (1968), The Theory of Capitalist Development, Modern Reader Paperbacks, New York and London. Weber, Max (1995), Toplumsal ve Ekonomik Örgütlenme Kuramı, (Çev. Özer Ozankaya), Đmge Kitabevi Yayınları. Weber, Max (1996), Sosyoloji Yazıları, (Çev. Taha Parla), Đletişim Yayınları. Weber, Max (1997), Protestan Ahlakı ve Kapitalizmin Ruhu, (Çev. Zeynep Aruoba), Hil Yayın. Weber, Max (2003), General Economic History, (Tr. Frank Knight), Dover Publications.