* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Justice Criminology and Criminal
History of social work wikipedia , lookup
Anthropology of development wikipedia , lookup
Postdevelopment theory wikipedia , lookup
Anti-intellectualism wikipedia , lookup
Unilineal evolution wikipedia , lookup
Public engagement wikipedia , lookup
Social theory wikipedia , lookup
Community development wikipedia , lookup
Sociology of culture wikipedia , lookup
Sociological theory wikipedia , lookup
Social history wikipedia , lookup
Public sociology wikipedia , lookup
Index of sociology articles wikipedia , lookup
History of sociology wikipedia , lookup
Criminology and Criminal Justice http://crj.sagepub.com/ Wacquant and civic sociology: 'Formative intentions' and formative experiences Ian Loader and Richard Sparks Criminology and Criminal Justice 2010 10: 405 DOI: 10.1177/1748895810382366 The online version of this article can be found at: http://crj.sagepub.com/content/10/4/405 Published by: http://www.sagepublications.com On behalf of: British Society of Criminology Additional services and information for Criminology and Criminal Justice can be found at: Email Alerts: http://crj.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts Subscriptions: http://crj.sagepub.com/subscriptions Reprints: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.nav Permissions: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav Citations: http://crj.sagepub.com/content/10/4/405.refs.html >> Version of Record - Nov 26, 2010 What is This? Downloaded from crj.sagepub.com at Moray House Inst of Education on October 31, 2012 Article Wacquant and civic sociology: ‘Formative intentions’ and formative experiences1 Criminology & Criminal Justice 10(4) 405–415 © The Author(s) 2010 Reprints and permission: sagepub. co.uk/journalsPermissions.nav DOI: 10.1177/1748895810382366 crj.sagepub.com Ian Loader University of Oxford, UK Richard Sparks University of Edinburgh, UK Our contribution to the now rather expansive activity of welcoming, critiquing, and otherwise discussing Loïc Wacquant’s new books is devoted to exploring the conception of sociology’s ‘civic’ roles that he says animates and underpins them. For this reason, we will focus here in particular on the afterword to Prisons of Poverty (which itself is called ‘A civic sociology of neo-liberal penality’) (Wacquant, 2009b). Given that this is the argument with which we primarily wish to engage, we will shortly devote a moment or two to summarising the position. Like many people, we think there is reason to be grateful that a sociologist of Wacquant’s stature has chosen to devote a substantial portion of his career to analysing the new penal politics. We believe that this has contributed significantly to our understanding of the issues and to the seriousness with which wider social scientific and public discourse now have to treat ‘criminological’ questions. As far as space permits here, we will go on to say a few words about what this means for sociological and criminological work as agents of democratic deliberation and reflection. This happens to be the very problem that has occupied our attention recently (Loader and Sparks, 2010), just as it does, in one way or another, most people who think seriously about these issues at all. We will then go on to argue in favour of a certain conception of the civic roles of social science. This emphasises the connections between what we call an ‘academic formative intention’, on the one hand, and a commitment to the enhancement of democratic deliberation on matters of common concern, on the other. Our argument, in brief, is that the public value of sociology or criminology, in this case as applied to questions of punishment and social control, is most coherently and convincingly described as that of contributing to a better politics of crime and its regulation – or what we call ‘democratic under-labouring’ (we say a little more about this curious term below; for a fuller exposition, see Loader and Sparks, 2010: Ch. 5). We think this is in many respects very Corresponding author: Richard Sparks Email: [email protected] Downloaded from crj.sagepub.com at Moray House Inst of Education on October 31, 2012 406 Criminology & Criminal Justice 10(4) close to, perhaps even entirely compatible with, Wacquant’s view of the matter, notwithstanding some differences in vocabulary and style. However, it is also designedly inclusive and is by no means restricted to, and certainly does not automatically prefer, one way of engagement over all others. We suggest that Wacquant has discovered – in a way that is partly given by prior aspects of his intellectual orientation and theoretical convictions (his ‘approach’, or more technically his ‘formative intention’), and partly worked out in response to some striking aspects of the acclaim, and no doubt opprobrium, that greeted the publication of his work in various parts of the world (what we call here his ‘formative experiences’) – one important way of doing something that looks very like what we mean by democratic under-labouring. We are aware that this sounds curious: Loïc Wacquant as under-labourer, surely some mistake? We borrow the term ‘formative intention’ from the work of Collins and Evans (2007: 116–7) in the sociology of natural science. Collins and Evans use this term to analyse what is distinctive about particular sorts of knowledge production and claims to expertise – what counts, for example, as properly conducted and reported science within the conventions of what Merton termed ‘organised scepticism’ that structure a scientific community? How does this differ from the intentions and expectations of art, or law, or ordinary discussion? We find this diction helpful in developing our own conception of the mission and tasks of the democratic under-labourer. In our view, the special contribution that the under-labourer as a social scientist can make to democracy presupposes a commitment to the values of clarity, coherence, non-contradiction, evidence, and so on, that define her activities as academic ones. She holds, that is to say, that when sociology, criminology, and other disciplines intervene in public life, they need to do so in ways that remain embedded in academic formative intentions and processes, and retain an overriding interest in the production of knowledge. Yet this is not, as we hope to make clearer below, in any sense an argument that scholarship stands above debate, or flourishes an expertise that can trump other positions and bring an end to discussion, still less that it should absent itself from public controversy (see also Edwards and Sheptycki, 2009). How, then, does all this bear upon Wacquant’s objectives in writing these books? No doubt there will be readers for whom Wacquant’s very eloquence, the vigour of his judgements and opinions, and the intensity of his objections to what he sees as the destructive march of neoliberalism through the institutions and ways of life of many countries, casts suspicion on his scientific credibility from the outset. Yet, at the same time, the vehemence of his disapproval of what he sees as the evangelising and propagandist activities of many of the neoliberal think-tankers, policy consultants, commentators, and others implicated in this process, seems to us to result not just from disagreement, but from a sense that these people are seeing the world through ideological blinkers, playing fast and loose with evidence and so on. That is to say, he does not see them simply as mistaken, but also as somewhat fraudulent; as being so convinced of the correctness of the cause that they have become indifferent to the quality of the evidence that supports it. The problems of their politics, and the inadequacy of their social science, are for him bound up together. Thus, although Wacquant may be seen from a certain point of view as an inveterate side-taker, he does not see himself as inhabiting an epistemologically flat universe. He thinks, in other words, that he has a better argument, not just a morally superior vantage point. Yet at the same time, whilst no alert reader of Wacquant can generally be left in much doubt as to what he is against, and despite his well-known taste for pugilism in all its Downloaded from crj.sagepub.com at Moray House Inst of Education on October 31, 2012 Loader and Sparks 407 forms, we see his outline of civic sociology as an accommodating, moderate, and quite capacious one. Perhaps this seems surprising. We are certainly not suggesting that Wacquant has ceased to express himself in a trenchant and on occasion combative manner. Certainly he intends us to be in no doubt as to where he stands on the big issues that his books address. For him, the effects of the neoliberal ascendancy on the penal realm have been disastrous, perhaps especially in their exported forms. The apologists and ideologues involved in this movement (its ‘missionaries’, as he calls them) have in his depiction characteristically been over-zealous, always highly instrumental, and often downright unscrupulous. At the same time, he has some fairly unflattering things to say even about those whom one might suppose to be closer to him, politically and intellectually. Certain other notable recent contributions in the sociology of punishment receive a somewhat peremptory – and not always fair – dismissal. The entire debate on ‘public sociology’ is cuffed aside in one rather disdainful footnote – even if the casual observer might have some difficulty in grasping what is really at stake in the distinction between ‘public’ and ‘civic’ sociology (we return to each of these engagements in due course). Yet, curiously, the appealing (to many readers) ebullience of Wacquant’s writing in Prisons of Poverty (2009b) and elsewhere could easily lead one to suppose that civic sociology here means something bigger and less intellectually modest than turns out to be the case on closer examination. What then is civic sociology? What does it require and preclude? Does it matter, and if so why? We will seek briefly to locate both Wacquant’s conception of the civic role of social science and ours in relation to certain current controversies and debates below. We have in mind here not just those debates concerning the recent transformations of law and order politics that are the substantive topic of his recent work, and as it happens of much of ours, but also, and for present purposes more particularly, those that address questions about the relations between social scientific work and public issues more generally. Let us first remind ourselves of the essential features of the case. Doing the Civic Sociology of Neoliberal Penality Wacquant holds that the punitive turn in penal policy and the ‘glorification of the penal wing of the state’ is not an adjunct or mere by-product of neoliberalism, but rather an inherent component of a ‘larger revamping of public authority’ and a ‘re-engineering of the state to promote and respond to the economic and sociomoral conditions ... of hegemonic neoliberalism’. For him, the growth and intensification of penal controls (the ‘right hand’ of the state) are not responses to ‘the evolution of crime’ (indeed, crime rather drops out of Wacquant’s story altogether). Rather, they are ‘core political capacities through which Leviathan produces and manages inequality, marginality and identity’. The famous ‘rolling back’ of the state that is one of neoliberalism’s proudest claims, is accompanied by a rolling out of ‘a new government of poverty wedding restrictive “workfare” and expansive “prisonfare”, which ensnares the precarious fractions of the post-industrial proletariat in a carceral-assistential net designed to steer them towards deregulated employment or to contain them in their dispossessed neighbourhoods and in the booming prisons that have become their satellites’ (Wacquant, 2008: 9). Thus, Wacquant claims, whereas a number of influential readings of recent penal change understand it as one of the manifestations of a deep-seated cultural shift, it is Downloaded from crj.sagepub.com at Moray House Inst of Education on October 31, 2012 408 Criminology & Criminal Justice 10(4) more appropriate to depict it rather as something purposefully pursued to consolidate the dominance of neoliberal rule. In the face of that dominance, he argues, punitive policies become more or less compulsory, thus acquiring a breadth of political support such that ‘penal severity is now presented virtually everywhere and by everyone as a healthy necessity, a vital reflex of self-defence by a social body threatened by the gangrene of criminality, no matter how petty’ (Wacquant, 2008: 11). In Wacquant’s vision, the new penal state is one designed to deal with ‘castaway categories’ of unassimilated, unwanted, and unnecessary people. The historic interest of the social state in inclusion or reintegration, however problematic and attenuated these may have been in reality, now wanes to a residual level: as the welfare state retreats so the penal state grows. Mass imprisonment is a key dimension, on this view, of the new government of poverty, with obvious correlative consequences for both indigenous and immigrant minorities. ‘Logically’, Wacquant argues, ‘the prison returns to the forefront of the societal stage, when only 30 years ago the most eminent specialists of the penal question were unanimous in predicting its waning, if not its disappearance’ (2008: 15). Wacquant insists that social policy and penal policy are not ‘separated and isolated domains of public action’. Rather, ‘in reality they already function in tandem at the bottom of the structure of classes and places’. This has a bearing on the relations between penal politics and, to mention but two, migration and public health. In that they are, in Wacquant’s view, part and parcel of the neoliberal ‘rolling back’ of the social state, these new institutional arrangements are also actively exported, for example to Europe and to Latin America. Thus, the new gadgets and devices – and the think-tank pamphlets and consultancy opportunities facilitated by the requirements of the expansion of the penal field – impel the international circulation of expert discourse and academic apology, and hence the phenomenon of ‘policy transfer’ (Jones and Newburn, 2007) to a new level of intensity. What follows is that these phenomena cannot be adequately named, tracked, analysed, or criticised so as to speak internally to a specialist discipline or activity of penology or criminology – they require the intellectual resources of a wider sociology of politics and of state theory, or else they simply escape proper understanding. They also demand rigorous comparative and trans-national or translational study in order to track their global reach and diffusion in its variety and unevenness, and to apprehend the complexities of their local appropriations and resistances. It is for these reasons that Wacquant is so critical of accounts of these transformations that seem to him to depend on notions of evolution or succession. This is not, he insists, a question of transition to a new societal ‘stage’. What Wacquant calls ‘hazy disquisitions on late modernity’ do not meet the need. What is required is a much more expressly political reading of recent events. The issue concerns which vision of economic and social futures is winning, where, by whose agency, with what effects and at whose expense. What Do ‘Civic’ Sociologists Do Then? How, then, is this a civic project and what is entailed in so naming it? At various points in the afterword (2009b) Wacquant says that civic sociology is for him ‘an effort to deploy the tools of social science to engage in, and bear upon, a current debate of frontline Downloaded from crj.sagepub.com at Moray House Inst of Education on October 31, 2012 Loader and Sparks 409 societal significance’, and that this involves ‘circumventing’ dominant policy and media discourse and ‘alerting’ citizens and decision-makers to the dire consequences of current trends. In other words, just as the ‘glorification’ of penality is not an adjunct or add-on of neoliberalism, but rather something intrinsic to it, so ‘engagement’ (in debate) and ‘alerting’ are not, on this view, supplements to or optional extras of the sociological enterprise but constitutive of its basic character, and intrinsic features of the disposition of its practitioners. These involvements do not belong only to some distinct activity of polemic or prophecy – they are, for Wacquant, central to the academic formative intention of the sociologist. We must take it that the words ‘deploying the tools of social science’ are no less important than any other terms in this statement of intention. The scientific aspiration and the civic mission both go, to paraphrase Richard Rorty, ‘all the way down’. What follows? First of all, Wacquant naturally does not claim to be originating anything wholly new. The notion of sociology as a civic enterprise refers directly to the Durkheimian notion of ‘Professional Ethics and Civic Morals’ (1900/1957). Civic Sociology is also, as it happens, the title of a book by E.A. Ross (1925).2 Of course, for Wacquant the most direct antecedent and primary influence is Pierre Bourdieu. As Bourdieu and Wacquant had already elsewhere reminded us, the element of engagement in sociological work does not mean that such work is just about partisanship or side-taking in the ordinary sense, but rather that it seeks to offer greater opportunities for ‘knowing what game we play’. We may thus ‘minimis[e] the extent to which we are manipulated by the forces of the field in which we evolve’, and ‘discern the sites in which we do indeed enjoy a degree of freedom’ to develop our own dispositions and just possibly to engage actively as political subjects (Bourdieu and Wacquant, 1992: 198–9). On this view, the sociological contribution in civic deliberation is not about the advocacy of already-defined positions (becoming a policy adviser or counsellor, still less the kind of well-resourced think-tank operative, trader in policy ‘solutions’, or ‘guru’ to whom Wacquant refers as a ‘missionary’), as it is an attitude of empirically informed scepticism towards dogmas, slogans, and prescriptions, and an atmosphere of imposed consensus, and thus about carving our particular kind of space for rational reappraisal and democratic discussion. Wacquant’s account of the civic purposes of his work and in particular the fervid reception of Prisons of Poverty3(2009b) in Latin America and elsewhere is an illuminating, and in certain respects exemplary, story. The intense and often fevered atmosphere into which he stumbled on his many travels to discuss his work will be for many readers amongst the most fascinating aspects of Prisons of Poverty. Wacquant insists that this history stands not so much as a validation of the academic merits of the work, but as an index of the reach and penetration of the issues with which it deals. His conclusion is that just as small armies of consultants and sales-people were energetically working to import the vocabulary and techniques of neoliberal crime control into Latin America and Central Europe, others there (many of them state officials, including criminal justice officials) were avidly seeking ‘civic firebreakers’ and ‘shields’. Thus: The point of this recapitulation is emphatically not to suggest that the foreign reception of Prisons of Poverty provides an apt measure of its analytic merits, but to give an idea of the wide diffusion and fiery fever that the phenomenon it tracks evinces in the political, journalistic and intellectual fields of First- and Second-World societies. A firestorm of ‘law and order’ has Downloaded from crj.sagepub.com at Moray House Inst of Education on October 31, 2012 410 Criminology & Criminal Justice 10(4) indeed been raging across the globe, which has transformed public debate and policy on crime and punishment in ways that no observer of the penal scene could have foreseen a dozen years before. The reason behind the unusual international engouement for the book was the same as in France: in all these countries, the mantras of ‘zero tolerance’ policing and ‘prison works’, lionised by US officials and showcased by the Giuliani-Bratton duet as the cause for the seemingly miraculous crime drop in New York, were being hailed by local officials. Everywhere politicians, of the Right and more significantly of the Left, were vying to import the latest American methods of law enforcement presented as the panacea for curing urban violence and assorted dislocations, while skeptics and critics of these methods were scouring for theoretical arguments, empirical data, and civic firebreakers with which to thwart the adoption of punitive containment as a generalised technique for managing rampant social insecurity. (Wacquant, 2009b: 166–7; original emphasis) Yet, although this is a vivid story, energetically told, about an academic succès fou, it is emphatically not a template or recipe or how-to manual. This is why we have emphasised the superficially paradoxical modesty of Wacquant’s conception of the civic contribution of sociology. Despite the intercontinental scale of the phenomenon to which it attends, the assertiveness and confidence of its writing, and the certainty of many of its judgements, what matters practically in this story are the local appropriations of the analysis by those involved in situ. And overwhelmingly, those uses and appropriations concern, it seems, not an alternative blueprint, a sort of counter-‘panacea’ to the mantras of the ‘zero tolerance’ lobby, but rather a ‘firebreak’, a way of moderating or holding back for a time an otherwise seemingly unstoppable conflagration.4 Presumably these experiences are amongst the reasons why Wacquant rejects as inadequate the distinction drawn by his Berkeley colleague Michael Burawoy (2005a, 2005b) between ‘public’ and ‘professional’ (not to mention ‘policy’ and ‘critical’) forms of sociology.5 On this point, Wacquant comments with characteristic trenchancy: I prefer the term civic to public sociology (which has recently come into fashion among American sociologists), since such sociology seeks to bridge the divide between instrumental and reflexive knowledge and to speak simultaneously to both academic and general audiences – albeit in different harmonics. The dichotomous opposition between ‘public’ and ‘professional’ sociology is a peculiarity of the US intellectual field, expressive of the political isolation and social impotence of American academics, that does not travel well outside of the Anglo-American sphere and does not adequately capture the positional predicament of university sociologists in America either. (Wacquant, 2009b: 204; emphasis added) This seems a somewhat harsh evaluation, and one that makes too much of a minor difference. Nevertheless, it matters from Wacquant’s perspective that, for civic sociology, no division of labour of quite the kind that Burawoy’s (2005a, 2005b) typology of sociologies appears to propose is really feasible. For example, picking up an instance mentioned by Wacquant in the final chapter of Punishing the Poor (2009a), it is the richly empirical, largely quantitative work by Tom Tyler and colleagues (1990, 2004, 2007) on procedural justice, legitimacy, and law-abidingness that gives us rational grounds for suspicion that evermore assertive styles of policing and prosecution (as proposed by advocates of zero Downloaded from crj.sagepub.com at Moray House Inst of Education on October 31, 2012 Loader and Sparks 411 tolerance) may be self-confounding (and hence why the current doctrines of neoliberal crime control are likely to turn out to be self-limiting, whatever their ascendancy now). The implicit message may be that Tyler’s work exercises the influence it now does in large part because it is judged by so many readers to stand up as professional social science, as well as carrying vital implications for a field of policy and practice. So where does it stand on this public–professional–critical–policy matrix? Is it perhaps something like ‘professional social science undertaken for public purposes’? From Wacquant’s perspective, one could play such parlour games all day, but the outcome would still not matter very much. Similarly, sociologists may well very often be people with a sense of mission, but never missionaries in the sense intended by Wacquant in describing the new profession of security and crime control ‘experts’. Civic sociology is not a special sort of sociology, it is just sociology that remains true to its disciplinary moorings and sources of insight, and declines to be excluded from public discourse by people with something to sell. Civic Social Science as ‘Under-labouring’?6 In our current work, we raise a number of questions about the ways in which social science (criminology in our case) participates in public life – which criminologies are taken up and used? What are the filters that structure certain contexts of reception? What are the ‘formative intentions’ of various participants in these conversations? If we begin from an understanding that crime and its control partake of the basic stuff of politics (and thus raise questions of order, authority, legitimacy, justice, freedom, power), what then is the special contribution of systematic scholarship on those practices? It matters a good deal, we suggest (unoriginally but not trivially), not only that crime risks are regulated and controlled, but also how they are regulated and controlled, and which instruments of government are used in doing this. How we contrive to get the results of research and reflection to have any purchase on what practically happens in a policy environment that has become volatile and unstable, one in which it becomes evermore difficult to make reason and evidence the drivers of what is said and done (which seems to be how many scholars experience it), is to say the least of it a hard question. We argue (and we call the position, ruthlessly updating and ripping from its original context a term borrowed from Locke (1690/1975))7 that the social scientist may aspire to something like the role of an under-labourer for democracy. To pose this issue in these terms is to try to think afresh about criminology’s relation to the present pathologies and unrealised promise of modern politics. In the former case, this means trying to make good on the rather remote and thin understanding that some social science disciplines such as the one that has lately preoccupied us, namely criminology, too often have of the world of practical affairs by fostering a better appreciation of the forces that shape the treatment of crime in the contemporary public sphere and the reasons why (social) scientific knowledge about crime does or does not get taken up and used in political debate and governmental action. This, in turn, means acquiring the will, and the necessary tools, to develop understanding of the ‘circumstances of politics’ (Waldron, 1999: 106) and cultivating a ‘qualified tolerance’ towards those who practise politics as a vocation (Swift and White, 2008: 64). This does not, however, mean reconciling oneself to the status quo. Downloaded from crj.sagepub.com at Moray House Inst of Education on October 31, 2012 412 Criminology & Criminal Justice 10(4) In the latter case, re-appraisal means re-connecting with and developing those strands of thought which have insisted that crime is ‘political’ (Taylor et al., 1973), and making explicit the connections that exist – that cannot but exist – between crime and its control and the repertoire of ideas (order, justice, authority, legitimacy, freedom, rights, etc.) and traditions (liberalism, but also conservatism, socialism, social democracy, feminism, republicanism, environmentalism, etc.) that comprise modern political thought. It involves folding into our understanding of criminological research and public engagement the fact that any discussion of the criminal question encodes in miniature a set of claims about the nature of the good society, and any attempt to answer it – however apparently ‘dry’, technical, or limited in scope – carries and projects a possible world, a desirable state of affairs that a political or criminological actor wishes to usher into existence. To think again and in these ways about the intersections between criminology (or socio logy, human geography, or whatever) and politics does not dispose of, or render secondary, the question of knowledge and its uses. Having indicated why criminologists might better understand the pathologies of modern politics and be clearer about the relationship of their work to its ideals and possibilities, another set of questions shuffles into view. One presumes that most individuals who spend their time, or in many instances the greater part of their working lives, practising criminology or an allied craft, do so because they believe that acquiring knowledge about crime, or justice, or punishment has some value. It also seems safe to suppose that they think the knowledge they produce and disseminate has a quality – a methodological rigour, respect for evidence, or theoretical acuity, which enables it to unearth things about the world or see that world in a revised light – that sets it apart from other claims about crime and its control, such as those circulated by politicians, journalists, bloggers, victim groups, offenders, police officers, campaigners, or simply citizens engaged in daily conversation. But what exactly is this ‘expertise’ and what value and place does it have? Here the following questions begin to emerge: what contribution can criminological knowledge make to shaping responses to crime in a polity which acknowledges crime and punishment to be properly political issues? What in a democracy is the public value of criminology, or any other social science? What modes of intervention – and what institutional arrangements – can best realise that good? To be a democratic under-labourer is to be committed, first and foremost, to the generation of knowledge, rather than (first and foremost) to scoring a point or winning a battle: if the distinction between sociologist and missionary is to mean anything, it must entail something of this kind. What, then, of the question of public intervention in disputes about crime? We have three points to make on this. The first is that engaging in public life – being ‘political’ in some broad sense – does not mean reducing the question of crime to one of political preference, nor positing criminologists as quasi-politicians, nor celebrating folk wisdom over professional judgement and hard-won knowledge. Our task is to be bearers and interpreters of that knowledge and to bring it to bear on matters of public concern and dispute, hence our insistence on the question of the scholarly ‘formative intention’. However, this does not – secondly – reduce what social scientists can bring to public debate to matters of evidence narrowly construed. It seems clear that the social scientist enjoys a degree of freedom that many participants in political and professional struggles over crime and justice lack. They have a certain liberty to refuse Downloaded from crj.sagepub.com at Moray House Inst of Education on October 31, 2012 Loader and Sparks 413 to take the social world for granted or accept received political ‘imperatives’, to provoke and unsettle, and pose questions about our responses to crime that neoliberal political cultures increasingly seem to have forgotten how to ask. Being critical in this sense properly forms part of the social scientist’s DNA (see further Ericson, 2005). In other words, we can and should bring to public discussion a scepticism that refuses to treat at face value the categories, assumptions, and self-understandings that make up prevailing ‘common sense’ about crime and its control. We may, however, thirdly, have to give up an illusion of mastery in which we somehow expect our knowledge to engineer outcomes, end political discussion, and trump the ill-informed concerns and perspectives of others. The public role of criminology involves generating controversy, opening up and extending debate, and challenging and provoking received public ‘opinion’ and political postures, not closing such discourse down. So (to cut a much longer story very short indeed) it is a disposition and a practice whose formative intention is the production of rigorous knowledge, but which understands itself as engaging with a field in which applications of that knowledge never reduce to simple and transparent calculations. Instead, the question always arises: ‘what is the collective good that we want enquiry to promote?’ (Kitcher, 2001), and there are not only ever ‘matters of fact’, but also always disputed ‘matters of concern’ (Latour, 2004). The social scientist as a democratic under-labourer thus has a commitment both to rigour in knowledge production and to a more deliberative politics of big public questions like the future of punishment and crime control. She is necessarily implicated in what Hoppe (1999) calls the ‘argumentative turn’ in public policy. The under-labouring conception of social science is committed both to participating within, and to facilitating and extending, institutional spaces that supplement representative politics with inclusive public deliberation about crime and justice matters, whether locally, nationally, or in emergent transnational spaces. In this regard, the public value of democratic under-labouring lies not primarily in ‘cooling’ down controversies about crime and social responses to it, notwithstanding Wacquant’s terminology of ‘fire-breakers’ and the like,8 so much as in playing its part in figuring out ways to bring their ‘heat’ within practices of democratic governance (Krause, 2008). Hence the seemingly paradoxical nature of our suggestion in this short article. Although it seems odd to do so in the case of an undoubted academic ‘star’, and doughty controversialist, such as Wacquant, nevertheless his ethnographer’s feel for the local uses and appropriations of his work, and the often unexpected ways in which such work actually inserts itself into public consciousness or practical decision-making, allows us to claim him for the side of the under-labourers, not so distant indeed from the various sites in which the rest of us also toil. Notes 1. Like other contributions to the present collection, this article is developed from remarks prepared for the ‘Symposium on Neoliberal Penality’, which took place at Queen Mary, University of London, on 7 October 2009. We would like to thank Leonidas Cheliotis for having instigated and organised that occasion and created the platform for this discussion, and for his comments on an earlier draft. 2. The full title of Ross’s (1925) book is Civic Sociology: A Textbook in Social and Civic Problems for Young Americans. Ross’s book was an early attempt at publicising academic Downloaded from crj.sagepub.com at Moray House Inst of Education on October 31, 2012 414 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. Criminology & Criminal Justice 10(4) sociology for a wider readership, and was consistent with the distinctive views of theorists of the Progressive period on the role of education in sustaining democracy in mass society (Urbiel, 1998). There is little enough new under the sun. At one stage, colleagues (Sparks included) in Scotland took it that in nominating ‘civic criminology’ as the defining mission for the Scottish Centre for Crime and Justice Research (www.sccjr.ac.uk), we were doing something novel and distinctively Scottish. In one sense, we were – yet avid discussion of the civic missions of the social sciences has recurred at intervals ever since Durkheim. Wacquant is punctilious in using the local title of the book – originally Les Prisons de la Misère and subsequently Prisões da Miseria and so on – when describing its reception in various parts of the world. This seems quite appropriate, but detailing the contextual features of these narratives is not our main concern here, important as they clearly are, so we will stick with the English translation for present purposes. It is at this point worth posing the not insignificant sociological question of whether Wacquant’s preferred vocabulary and style – the aforementioned assertiveness and certainty that his writing displays – tends to attract and enchant those actors who are already on the lookout for resources to hold back the punitive upsurge, while doing less to persuade – and maybe even alienating – those who are still to be ‘awakened’ to the social costs of the neoliberal penal experiment. We have no way of knowing for certain the answer to this question – and it may even vary from place to place – but the suspicion that this may be so at least in part explains the differences in vocabulary and style between Wacquant’s project and ours that we alluded to at the outset. There is now a very extensive literature on the topic of ‘public sociology’. Burawoy’s original statements of the position (Burawoy, 2005a, 2005b) stand amongst the most highly cited papers in the field in recent times. For a good conspectus of the issues and the arguments ranged around the public sociology thesis, see Clawson et al. (2006) and Nichols (2007). As we point out elsewhere (Loader and Sparks, 2010: Ch. 2), these issues have been keenly felt in criminology (e.g. Chancer and McLaughlin, 2007), as in other neighbouring subjects, and several of the more intriguing contributions have come from those whose work concentrates upon crime and punishment issues, e.g. Braithwaite (2005) and Ericson (2005). The following section largely condenses aspects of the argument of Loader and Sparks (2010: Ch. 5). Those who wish to get the full story should go there. For Locke, the task of under-labourers – roughly meaning here all who are concerned to discover valid knowledge – consists in ‘clearing the ground a little, and removing some of the Rubbish’ (Locke, 1690/1975: 10). Our position is that ‘the Rubbish’ is to be construed as that which stands in the way of whatever one labours in the service of – in Locke’s case ‘Knowledge’, in the present case a better-informed democratic politics of crime control. This is not to say that we see this terminology as necessarily misplaced in his account. Wacquant sees his interlocutors as confronting a ‘conflagration’, not as engaging in a fire-side chat. References Bourdieu, P. and L. Wacquant (1992) An Invitation to Reflexive Sociology. Cambridge: Polity. Braithwaite, J. (2005) ‘For Public Social Science’, British Journal of Sociology 56(3): 345–54. Burawoy, M. (2005a) ‘For Public Sociology’, American Sociological Review 70(1): 4–28. Burawoy, M. (2005b) ‘Public Sociology: Populist Fad or Path to Renewal?’, British Journal of Sociology 56(3): 417–32. Chancer, L. and E. McLaughlin (2007) ‘Pubic criminologies: Diverse perspectives on academia and policy’, Theoretical Criminology 11(2): 155–73. Downloaded from crj.sagepub.com at Moray House Inst of Education on October 31, 2012 Loader and Sparks 415 Clawson, D., R. Zussman, J. Misra, N. Gerstel, R. Stokes, D.L. Anderton and M. Burawoy (eds) (2006) Public Sociology. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Collins, H. and R. Evans (2007) Rethinking Expertise. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Durkheim, E. (1900/1957) Professional Ethics and Civic Morals. London: Routledge. Edwards, A. and J. Sheptycki (2009) ‘Third Wave Criminology: Guns, Crime and Social Order’, Criminology and Criminal Justice 9(3): 379–97. Ericson, R. (2005) ‘Publicizing Sociology’, British Journal of Sociology 56(3): 365–72. Hoppe, R. (1999) ‘Policy Analysis, Science and Politics: From “Speaking Truth to Power” to “Making Sense Together”, Science and Public Policy 26(3): 201–10. Jones, T. and Newburn, T. (2007) Policy Transfer and Criminal Justice. Maidenhead: Open University Press. Kitcher, P. (2001) Science, Truth and Democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Krause, S. (2008) Civil Passions: Moral Sentiment and Democratic Deliberation. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Latour, B. (2004) Politics of Nature: How to Bring the Sciences into Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Loader, I. and R. Sparks (2010) Public Criminology? London: Routledge. Locke, J. (1690/1975) An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Nichols, L. (ed.) (2007) Public Sociology: The Contemporary Debate. Edison, NJ: Transaction. Ross, E.A. (1925) Civic Sociology: A Textbook in Social and Civic Problems for Young Americans. New York: World Book Co. Swift, A. and White, S. (2008) ‘Political Theory, Social Science, and Real Politics’, in D. Leopold and M. Stears (eds) Political Theory: Methods and Approaches. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Taylor, I., P. Walton and J. Young (1973) The New Criminology. London: RKP. Tyler, T. (1990) Why People Obey the Law. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Tyler, T. (2004) ‘Enhancing Police Legitimacy’, The ANNALS of the American Academy of Political and Social Science 593(1): 84–99. Tyler, T. (ed.) (2007) Legitimacy and Criminal Justice: International Perspectives. New York: Russell Sage Foundation. Urbiel, A. (1998) ‘Civic Education in Indianapolis During the Progressive Era’, in W. Reese (ed.) Hoosier Schools: Past and Present. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press. Wacquant, L. (2008) ‘Ordering Insecurity: Social Polarization and the Punitive Upsurge’, Radical Philosophy Review 11(1): 9– 27. Wacquant, L. (2009a) Punishing the Poor. Durham, NC: Duke University Press. Wacquant, L. (2009b) Prisons of Poverty. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press. Waldron, J. (1999) Law and Disagreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Biographies Ian Loader is Professor of Criminology and Director of the Centre for Criminology at the University of Oxford. Richard Sparks is Professor of Criminology at the University of Edinburgh and CoDirector of the Scottish Centre for Crime and Justice Research. Downloaded from crj.sagepub.com at Moray House Inst of Education on October 31, 2012