* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Understanding Sanctions in Social Dilemmas: A Biopsychological
Belongingness wikipedia , lookup
Impression formation wikipedia , lookup
Social tuning wikipedia , lookup
Corporal punishment in the home wikipedia , lookup
Group dynamics wikipedia , lookup
Albert Bandura wikipedia , lookup
Vladimir J. Konečni wikipedia , lookup
Understanding Sanctions in Social Dilemmas: A Biopsychological Perspective on Costly Punishment in Public Goods Situations Dissertation zur Erlangung des Doktorgrades Dr.phil. der Fakultät für Ingenieurwissenschaften und Informatik der Universität Ulm vorgelegt von Stefan Pfattheicher aus Malsch (Kreis Karlsruhe) 2014 Amtierende Dekanin: Prof. Dr. Tina Seufert Gutachter: Prof. Dr. Johannes Keller Gutachter: Prof. Dr. Thomas Kessler Gutachter: Prof. Dr. Arnd Florack Tag der mündlichen Qualifikation: 06. Juni 2014 Contents Preface ....................................................................................................................................... v 1 Introduction ........................................................................................................................... 1 1.1 The importance of investigating social dilemma situations ............................................ 3 1.2 Solving social dilemmas .................................................................................................. 5 1.3 The value of a biopsychological perspective on social dilemmas ................................... 8 1.4 Paradigms from game theory......................................................................................... 11 2 Why and under which conditions individuals costly punish ........................................... 16 2.1 Different perspectives on how to investigate costly punishment .................................. 16 2.2 Costly punishment from a biopsychological perspective .............................................. 17 2.2.1 Fairness and justice.............................................................................................. 17 2.2.2 Impulsivity........................................................................................................... 21 2.2.3 Anticipated reward .............................................................................................. 25 2.2.4 Reputation............................................................................................................ 28 2.3 Summary........................................................................................................................ 29 3 Empirical papers ................................................................................................................. 31 3.1 Towards a biopsychological understanding of costly punishment: The role of basal cortisol (Pfattheicher & Keller, in press, Appendix A) ................................................ 31 3.1.1 Discussion............................................................................................................ 34 3.2 The eye cue manipulation as subtle induction of a sense of being watched: Empirical validation and theoretical integration (Pfattheicher & Keller, 2014, Appendix B) ................................................................................................................. 37 3.2.1 Discussion............................................................................................................ 40 3.2.2 Methodological remarks ...................................................................................... 43 3.3 Punishing for the sake of reputation? Effects of reputational concerns on costly punishment (Pfattheicher, Landhäußer, & Keller, 2014, Appendix C) ........................ 45 3.3.1 Discussion............................................................................................................ 50 3.3.2 Further remarks ................................................................................................... 52 3.3.3 Discussing costly signaling theory ...................................................................... 53 3.3.4 Explaining actor-observer discrepancies ............................................................. 56 3.4 Vigilant self-regulation and costly punishment in public goods situations (Pfattheicher & Keller, 2013, Appendix D) ................................................................. 61 3.4.1 Theories of motivation and regulatory focus theory ........................................... 62 3.4.2 The empirical paper ............................................................................................. 67 3.4.3 Integrating reputational concerns and oughts ...................................................... 69 3.4.4 Additional theoretical remarks ............................................................................ 70 3.4.5 Integrating findings on cortisol and prevention focus ......................................... 73 3.5 Individual differences in antisocial punishment in public goods situations: The interplay of cortisol with testosterone and dominance (Pfattheicher, Landhäußer, & Keller, in press, Appendix E) ....................................................................................... 74 3.5.1 Relations to other work ....................................................................................... 77 3.5.2 Proposals for future research ............................................................................... 78 4 General discussion ............................................................................................................... 81 4.1 Summarizing the findings .............................................................................................. 82 4.2 Discussion of the applied paradigm .............................................................................. 84 4.3 Discussion of the biopsychological perspective ............................................................ 85 4.4 The subjective construction of social dilemmas ............................................................ 87 4.5 Implications for behavior in “real life”.......................................................................... 89 4.6 The role of altruism in costly punishment ..................................................................... 92 References ............................................................................................................................... 96 Zusammenfassung ................................................................................................................ 136 Appendix ............................................................................................................................... 137 PREFACE v Preface In 2006 I participated in a seminar on “Theories of Political Decisions” held at my former university (at Mannheim). At that time I was interested in learning about how people in our society make decisions when they vote, particularly because I was convinced that many of these decisions were not founded on reasonable considerations. In short, the seminar did not answer my questions. Instead, I found myself in a seminar on game theory in the political decision context. I was immediately fascinated by the possibility of using simple game theory paradigms to model human decisions and social situations. Almost two years later the story continued when I joined a seminar on “Social Interaction”. What bothered me in the political seminar on game theory was that the ultimate focus was on human behavior from a rational choice perspective with basal human needs, motivations, and social situations being neglected. Happily, these issues were addressed in the seminar on “Social Interaction”. In fact, this seminar was a tasty antithesis to the rational choice perspective primarily taught at my university (cf. Kroneberg & Kalter, 2012). When it came to deciding where to write my thesis for my diploma I recalled the inspiring seminar on “Social Interaction” and contacted my former lecturer. In a nutshell, this begun my work with Johannes Keller on social dilemma situations and the notion of costly punishment. While writing my diploma thesis, I was very happy when Johannes offered me the possibility to become a PhD student at his department and to continue working on this topic (I remember that I possessed a promotion-focus that day). Becoming a doctoral candidate was appealing given the possibility it offered to gain a deeper understanding of human behavior. For instance, I found it interesting how humans’ behavior can be shaped by simple social cues (cf. Pfattheicher & Keller, 2014, Appendix B) as a function of basal motivational orientations (Keller & Pfattheicher, 2011, Appendix F). However, the understanding of why humans behave as they do was not easily served. Specifically, the understanding, crystallized in this dissertation, of why individuals engage in costly punishment in public goods situations is the result of a long PREFACE vi (and still ongoing) process. My thinking began with the conceptualization of costly punishment as a socially desirable behavior, mainly deliberatively executed to uphold social norms and moral principles (Batson, Ahmad, Powell, & Stocks, 2008; Batson, Ahmad, & Tsang, 2002; Kurzban, DeScioloi, O’Brien, 2007). I ended up at a very different point in what constitutes this thesis. I would not be where I am now without the help and encouragement I received from my colleagues in academia and my friends. I am deeply grateful to Johannes for being such an outstanding supervisor. You not only established a pleasant working atmosphere but always had time for me and were willing to listen and to support me. Thanks to you, I believe I now recognize the importance of a theory and what it means to conduct basic research. Although you may support another football team, our discussions about football (and other important issues) also contributed to my well-being during recent years. Thank you for the, literally, open door you offered. I am also deeply grateful to Toshi who has been an, almost, indefatigable and indestructible companion in our office. Thank you for the fun times we shared, although sometimes delicious food and a few drinks were necessary to make this happen. Thank you, Claudia and Svenja, for being there in our self-help group (and beyond). Thanks to all the research assistants who worked with me during the past couple of years, particularly Cia, Friedrich, and Silvi. Thank you, Simon, for our inspiring talks about existence. Thank you, Philipp, for our deep friendship and for introducing me to honeymustard salad dressing. Thank you, Cathrin, for your kindness and baking skills. Thank you, Sebastian, for sharing my ridiculous sense of humor. Thank you, Flo and Thomas, for sharing your devotedness to pasta and lively discussions. Thank you, Mum and Dad, for offering me the chance to do what I have. Thank you, Bro, for being there, always. Finally, and most importantly: Thank you, Katharina, for your love. INTRODUCTION 1 1 Introduction Imagine a single, lonely angler who knows from experience that she has a good chance of catching a considerable amount of fish at a small lake. Having caught two fish, the angler faces the possibility of catching a third, a fourth, and a fifth one. A rational angler whose benefits exceed the costs of catching more than two fish would go for a third fish (Esser, 2000). Indeed, individuals often strive to maximize their own benefit which fits the basic idea of an orthodox rational actor referred to as homo economicus (Becker, 1976).1 Given perfect information about the costs and benefits of several behavioral options, rational actors choose the option that yields the highest benefit. The situation involving the angler is a very specific situation because it is not a social situation in which the actions of several individuals relate to and influence each other. The behavior of the angler is moreover not a social action. An “action is ‘social’ if the acting individual takes account of the behavior of others and is thereby oriented in its course” (Weber, 1922/1972, p. 1). In the present ideal-typical example, the rational angler simply follows her own preferences (i.e., maximizing her benefit through catching fish) and she does not take (and does not need to take) the expectations or behaviors of other individuals, which may influence her preferences, into account. In social situations, however, individuals affect other individuals’ affect, cognitions, and behaviors, and an actor’s actions are, in turn, also affected by the affect, cognitions, and behaviors of other individuals. There are social situations in which the benefits to the individuals involved are remarkably construed. To follow the example above, let us now consider not only a single angler but three anglers sitting at the lake. Now the benefit of the angler is not only determined by her own actions but also by the actions of the other anglers. For instance, the other anglers could have more effective lures than the first angler which may influence the first angler’s success. That is to say, the success of an angler also depends on the actions of other anglers, which reflects the notion of mutual 1 When I refer to rational actors in the present work I mean actors that maximize material benefits; I do not include other possible benefits, for instance psychological benefits such as satisfaction. INTRODUCTION 2 interdependence. A second aspect of this social situation is worth noting. As mentioned above, a rational angler would benefit from catching a lot of fish because catching more fish results in more food and the possibility of gaining money through selling the fish at a local market. However, catching a lot of fish affects the fish stocks in that there are less fish for all of the anglers who angle at the lake. To emphasize this point, every rational angler benefits from catching a lot of fish. However, if every angler behaves in this way, the fish stocks are damaged so that the collective (i.e., all anglers) catch less fish. This reflects the notion of conflicting interests between the individual and the collective. The kind of social situation just described is termed a social dilemma situation, and the dilemma is reflected in the divergence of individual and collective interests (Dawes, 1980). If several individuals are involved in a social dilemma situation, two general types of situation can be distinguished by means of three criteria.2 The first type involves a common good and fits the example above. There are typically several anglers catching fish at a lake which is home to a limited amount of fish. The anglers can take fish out of the common good (i.e., catch a fish), they typically cannot exclude individuals who would also like to catch fish, and the benefits are subtractable because for every fish caught there is one less fish available for other anglers. So, taking, non-excludability, and subtractable benefits are the criteria for a common good. The second type, a social dilemma situation involving a public good, is characterized by the aspect of giving. Let us assume that anglers have to keep the lake and its surroundings clean, and that the anglers have to put (i.e., to give) a lot of effort into cleaning. Individuals cannot be excluded from using the public good (i.e., the lake and its surroundings). Using the public good is, moreover, non-rival because every angler can angle and use the lake no matter how the other anglers behave. So, giving, non- 2 The focus of the present dissertation is social dilemma situations involving more than two individuals. Therefore, social dilemma situations involving two individuals such as the “Prisoner’s Dilemma” (Diekmann, 2009) are neglected. INTRODUCTION 3 excludability, and non-rivalry are the criteria for a public good. Public goods are the focus of the present dissertation so only these are considered in detail below. In public goods situations, the benefit-maximizing strategy (i.e., not helping to keep the lake clean) of several rational actors results in a deficit Nash equilibrium (Nash, 1950). A Nash equilibrium is the state that results from the converging strategies of several, in this case, rational actors in which no actor benefits from changing their behavior (i.e., the equilibrium). In the example above, if every single angler pursues the benefitmaximizing strategy the result would be a ruined lake. An angler would gain almost no benefit from changing their behavior, that is, cleaning a ruined lake completely on their own. This situation is deficient in the sense that there actually is a collective optimum, that is, mutual cooperation (i.e., all anglers participate in cleaning the lake and its surroundings). These considerations emphasize why Hardin (1968) speaks of a “tragedy” when he describes social dilemma situations. Behaving selfishly is always the most beneficial strategy from a rational choice perspective. This results in a Nash equilibrium in which no one has any incentive to change their behavior. Thus, social dilemma situations are intractable, strong situations in which individuals benefit from acting against the collective (Esser, 2000). 1.1 The importance of investigating social dilemma situations Why is it important to be concerned about social dilemma situations? In the example above only very few individuals (anglers) take part in the dilemma situation and are potentially affected by uncooperative behavior. If social dilemma situations occurred rarely and affected only a very few individuals, investigating how to establish cooperation would surely be essential for these individuals but not much beyond that. However, this is undeniably not the case (van Lange, De Cremer, van Dijk, & van Vugt, 2007; van Lange, Joireman, Parks, & van Dijk, 2013). There is no individual on earth that is not affected by social dilemma situations. This is true because far-reaching social dilemma situations that affect all individuals do exist, for instance earth’s climate (Hansen et al., 2013; van Vugt, Griskevicius, & Schultz, 2014). Specifically, a rational INTRODUCTION 4 individual is best off if s/he does not devote resources (e.g., time, money) to protecting the environment. However, the collective suffers from environment-damaging behavior (i.e., uncooperative behavior) because the environment-damaging behavior of several individual leads to climate change (e.g., Irwin & Berigan, 2013). Another example: the fact that most individuals on earth are part of a nation state also creates numerous dilemma situations (Ostrom, 1990). For instance, individuals are better off when evading taxes but then the collective (i.e., the state) will suffer due to tax evasion because it will be more difficult to run the healthcare system, the education system and the legislature effectively. Smaller groups also face social dilemma situations, such as a student study group in which each individual has incentives not to prepare for a meeting but, nonetheless, benefits from the other (prepared) students. In sum, social dilemma situations are present in a huge variety of social situations (van Lange et al., 2007; van Lange et al., 2013). However, not only quantity counts when answering the question of why it is important to be concerned about social dilemma situations. The specific quality of social dilemma situations also makes them worth investigating (Camerer, 2003). Individuals’ behavior is more likely to be successfully predicted when benefits can be obtained on the individual micro-level and the collective macro-level (i.e., no social dilemma). Halevy, Chouc, and Murninghan (2012), for instance, showed that almost all of the individuals in their studies behaved cooperatively when the highest personal benefit for them and the others involved in the situation could be obtained through cooperation. However, because in social dilemma situations individuals’ interests are in contrast to the interests of the collective (cooperation is not the Nash equilibrium), it is often difficult to establish cooperation (see, e.g., Fehr & Gächter, 2002). By definition, cooperation between entities is a beneficial and valuable state for the collective. Given that selfish interests, however, are in contrast to the collective’s interest the question of how to establish cooperation between several individuals is of substantial value and worth investigating. This proposal is strengthened by manifold empirical work. In her seminal book, Ostrom (1990) documents the breakdown of cooperation in several real life situations, for INTRODUCTION 5 instance when observing systems for water irrigation where overusing water (i.e., damaging the collective) during a drought may save one’s harvest. Empirical work from the laboratory points in the same direction. Kelley and Grzelak (1972) were the first to empirically investigate cooperation between several individuals in public goods situations (referred to as an N-person prisoners’ dilemma). They observed a decreasing level of cooperation across multiple repeated interactions (the same pattern was later observed by Fehr and Gächter, 2002). To conclude, social dilemma situations are likely to emerge when several individuals interact to produce benefits and when mutual interdependence is provided in a way in which individuals’ personal interest is in contrast to the collective’s interest (Esser, 2000). These situations exist in a variety of contexts, that is, social dilemma situations frequently affect and guide humans’ behavior. Additionally, given the inherent suboptimal beneficiary structure, social dilemma situations have a special quality that essentially affects and guides humans’ behavior which is well-documented empirically (e.g., Balliet, Mulder, & van Lange, 2011; Fehr & Gächter, 2002; Ostrom, 1990; van Lange, Balliet, Parks, & van Vugt, 2014). These considerations constitute the rationale for why factors that foster cooperation in social dilemma situations should be investigated. These factors are outlined in the following section. 1.2 Solving social dilemmas Kollock (1998) has proposed three general perspectives regarding how social dilemmas can be solved, that is, how cooperation can be established: a structural perspective, a strategic perspective, and a motivational (psychological) perspective. The structural perspective emphasizes changing the structure of a social dilemma situation in order to make cooperation more beneficial. Prominent instances of this are iterations of interactions (rather than one-shot interactions) especially when individuals can be identified (Fox & Guyer, 1978; Jerdee & Rosen, 1974) and when they can communicate (Caporael, Dawes, Orbell, & van de Kragt, 1989). When these structural conditions are given, higher levels of cooperation could be observed (cf. Shinada & Yamagishi, 2007). One can also change the payoff structure to a situation where cooperation is rewarded by INTRODUCTION 6 a higher personal return (Isaac & Walker, 1988; Kelley & Grzelak, 1972), and where one’s contribution to a public good has a noticeable effect (e.g., in small groups) and is crucial to the provision of the public good (Kerr & Kaufman-Gilliland, 1994; note, however, that the literature on group size produced mixed results; see Shinada & Yamagishi, 2007). The strategic perspective emphasizes the notion that actors try to strategically adapt their own behavior and shape the behavior of others in order to gain personal benefits. The most prominent and one of the most successful strategies of this is the tit-for-tat strategy (Axelrod & Hamilton, 1981). The tit-for-tat strategy states that an actor cooperates at first and then responds to an action by a second actor by replicating the second actor’s action (also known as direct reciprocity; Trivers, 1971). Thus, if a second actor cooperates, then the first actor using the tit-for-tat strategy will cooperate as well. However, if a second actor does not behave cooperatively, the uncooperative behavior is responded to with equally uncooperative behavior. Another useful strategy is choosing partners that have behaved cooperatively in the past because these types of individuals are more likely to behave cooperatively in the future (Nowak & Sigmund, 1998; Wedekind & Braithwaite, 2002). Halevy et al. (2012) have shown that individuals do behave in accordance with a strategic approach. For instance, it was found that when individuals faced a competitive situation in which cooperation provides a higher benefit than defection if the other defects, individuals are more likely to cooperate the higher the likelihood was that the other individual would defect. Accordingly, one can argue that individuals strategically adapt their behavior in order to gain personal benefits. The core of the structural and strategic perspectives is the fundamental goal to maximize benefits (Kollock, 1998). However, there is wide agreement that these approaches do not capture the entire spectrum of possibilities of how to establish cooperation (e.g., Camerer, 2003; Kollock, 1998; Shinada & Yamagishi, 2007; van Lange et al., 2007; van Lange et al., 2013). The third approach proposed by Kollock (1998), the motivational perspective, captures this point. This perspective emphasizes that individuals not only take their own benefit into account but also that of the other individuals involved in the INTRODUCTION 7 situation. Batson and colleagues (Batson et al., 2008; Batson et al., 2002) specified the motivational perspective and put forward three general non-egoistic motivations to explain why people act for the public good. These are: collectivism (to increase the benefit of a group), principlism (to uphold moral principles), and altruism (to increase the benefits of others). Strengthening these basal motivational orientations should increase cooperation (Batson et al., 2008; Batson et al., 2002). In sum, research completed over decades has identified several tools for avoiding freeriding and establishing cooperation (for a compelling review see van Lange et al., 2013). In her seminal book Governing the Commons (1990), Nobel Prize winner Elinor Ostrom has systematically offered several principles for how to promote cooperation and prevent free-riding. First, clearly defined boundary conditions have to be set up in terms of who is allowed to benefit from the common or public good. Taking the example given at the beginning of the present work, the anglers could, for instance, unionize and restrict access to the lake. Second, rules that regulate the use of the common or public goods should be adapted to local conditions. For example, the anglers could restrict the amount of fish that is allowed to be caught. Third, Ostrom argued that it is important that individuals involved in the dilemma situation are able to participate in modifying operational rules. Fourth, external authorities (such as a federal government or religious institution) must recognize the rules adopted by the local individuals directly involved in the dilemma. Fifth, boundary conditions and rules for how the goods are to be used need to be monitored. Sixth, if a conflict emerges a low-cost local institution must be in place to resolve the conflict. Seventh, Ostrom proposed that appropriate sanctions for breaking the rules are necessary in order to prevent uncooperative behavior and to foster cooperative behavior. Proposing a sanction system is indeed a worthwhile approach given the remarkable amount of empirical evidence (cf. the meta-analysis of Balliet et al., 2011) that has convincingly shown that (a) negatively sanctioning (i.e., punishing) uncooperative others leads to an increase in cooperative behavior of the punished individuals in future interactions, and (b) there is a higher cooperation level in situations in which an option to punish is available as compared with situations in which no such option is available. In this regard, Gürerk, Irlenbusch, and Rockenbach (2006) showed that individuals also INTRODUCTION 8 recognize the importance of a sanction system and adapt their behavior accordingly. They offered participants the choice between a social dilemma situation in which negative sanctions (i.e., punishing other individuals involved in the social dilemma) were possible and the same social dilemma situation but without the possibility to negatively sanction others. Individuals could change their choice after each interaction. At the beginning, about 60% of the participants chose the social dilemma situation in which negative sanctions were possible. After thirty interactions, more than 90% had chosen the situation in which negative sanctions were possible. It is the central feature of the present work to examine the sanction systems that Ostrom (1990) and others have proposed (e.g., Olson, 1968; Yamagishi, 1986). This is a worthwhile approach given that a sanction system is of substantial value when cooperation needs to be established (Balliet et al., 2011; Fehr & Gächter, 2002; Gürerk et al., 2006). Specifically, the main theme in the present dissertation is the question of why and under which conditions individuals engage in the negative sanctioning of individuals involved in social dilemma situations. That is, it is the aim of the present work to understand negative sanctions in the context of social dilemma situations. 1.3 The value of a biopsychological perspective on social dilemmas In the present work, I will propose several explanations for why and under which conditions individuals engage in negative sanctions and punish others. This approach is in line with recent theorizing emphasizing that several routes can lead to specific behavior (cf. Bullock, Green, & Ha, 2010; Fiedler, Schott, & Meiser, 2011; Hayes, 2013). When explaining punishment in public goods situations I take the position that individuals’ decisions are driven by factors of the person and by factors of the situation as well as the interaction between these two types of factors (Ross & Nisbett, 1991). This dissertation focuses on specific factors of the individual, that is, endocrinological and psychological factors, which constitutes a biopsychological perspective. Specifically, I propose that one has to take endocrinological and psychological factors as well as the present situation into account when aiming to comprehensively understand social behavior. A good example that emphasizes the importance of this perspective is INTRODUCTION 9 the study by Josephs, Sellers, Newman, and Mehta (2006). These scholars have documented that in specific social situations the testosterone levels of individuals is relevant in terms of how they experience emotions. Specifically, when individuals with a relatively low level of testosterone were placed in a high status position they reported greater emotional arousal and worse cognitive functioning as compared with when they were placed in a low status position. The reverse was the case for individuals with a relatively high level of testosterone. That is to say, it was not the testosterone levels itself and also not the social situation itself (i.e., holding a low or high status position) that predicted how the individuals reacted. The interaction of testosterone and the social situation predicted behavior. Also in line with a biopsychological perspective, Carré, Putnam, and McCormick (2009) found that the testosterone levels of men who have won (vs. lost) a previous competition increased, and this increase was positively related to aggression after a provocation. However, this relation only holds true for those with a relatively high dispositional level of dominance. A study by Klinesmith, Kasser, and McAndrew (2006) also impressively shows the importance of a biopsychological perspective. These authors reported that interacting with a gun (vs. a toy) increased proactive aggression (i.e., aggression without a prior provocation) which could be explained by an increase in testosterone when participants interacted with a gun. It should have become apparent that when aiming to comprehensively understand social behavior one has to take endocrinological factors and their interaction with situational and other personal variables into account. Thus, a biopsychological perspective offers the possibility to reach a better understanding of social behavior, which is the principal objective of the present dissertation – to understand negative sanctions in public goods situations. Investigating social behavior from a biopsychological perspective has several additional advantages. First, specific endocrinological factors are related to specific motives and psychological processes. For instance, testosterone regulates dominant and destructive behavior in status-relevant situations (Josephs et al., 2006; Mehta, Jones, & Josephs, INTRODUCTION 10 2008; van den Bos, Golka, Effelsberg, & McClure, 2013). Basal levels of the steroid hormone cortisol are negatively related to impulsivity (Schmidt, Mussel, & Hewig, 2013, and Raine et al., 2006) and positively related to behavioral withdrawal (Blair, Peters, & Granger, 2004; Brown et al., 1996; Montoya, Terburg, Bos, & van Honk, 2012; Nava, Caldiroli, Premi, & Lucchini, 2006; Tops & Boksem, 2011; van Honk, Harmon-Jones, Morgan, & Schutter, 2010; Windle, 1994). Thus, by relating behavior in social dilemma situations to endocrinological factors (e.g., cortisol and testosterone) one can shed light on underlying motives and processes. This is even more remarkable as individuals themselves often have difficulty in and a restricted ability to correctly report the motives and processes underlying their behavior (Nisbett & Wilson, 1977). Second, neglecting endocrinological factors can lead to either false conclusions or no conclusions. If Klinesmith et al. (2006) had not assessed testosterone levels they could not have explained why interacting with a gun increased proactive aggression (i.e., no conclusion). Furthermore, if Carré et al. (2009) had not assessed changes in testosterone in their test subjects they could have concluded that the dispositional level of dominance is not related to reactive aggression (i.e., a false conclusion). Thus, a biopsychological perspective not only has the potential that conclusions can be drawn but also to prevent false conclusions or no conclusion. Third, endocrinological factors are unbiased in terms of socially desirable responding. This is important given that social desirability may play a role in the domain of prosocial behavior (such as cooperation) and antisocial behavior (such as the punishment of cooperative individuals, cf. Chapter 3.5). Thus, by assessing endocrinological (e.g., testosterone) and psychological factors (e.g., a concern for dominance) in social dilemma situations one can accommodate concerns regarding socially desirable responding. In sum, a biopsychological perspective on behavior in social dilemma situations seems to be a valuable approach: a better understanding can be reached, false or no conclusions can be avoided, and social desirability concerns can be addressed. Generally, the framework of the present dissertation follows the perception of other models, such as the General Aggression Model (Anderson & Bushman, 2002; Bushman & Anderson, 2002; DeWall, Anderson, & Bushman, 2011), emphasizing not only traits, sex, values, goals, INTRODUCTION 11 and behavioral scripts of a person that influence aggression but also individuals’ endocrinology. The following section (Chapter 2) outlines why and under which conditions individuals punish others, taking the biopsychological perspective just proposed. Before elaborating on this central goal of the present dissertation, I provide an overview of how negative sanctions can be investigated in the laboratory. 1.4 Paradigms from game theory It is possible to model social dilemma situations and negative sanctions in a laboratory setting, allowing the investigation of cooperation and negative sanctions in a reduced situation in which external influences can be controlled and causal analytic approaches applied. A public goods game including the option to negatively sanction other individuals involved in the dilemma (i.e., to punish others) is often used to investigate the emergence of cooperation. The public goods game is also extensively applied in the empirical studies presented below, so it is described in the following paragraph.3 In a typical public goods game, four players constitute one group (cf. Fehr & Gächter, 2002). Each player is endowed with 20 money units (MUs; the MUs are converted to real money and paid out at the end of a study) and are free to choose how many of these to keep and how many to contribute to a common group project (i.e., the public good). Each MU contributed is multiplied by 1.6. Next, each player receives one fourth of the public good, independent of their contribution. Accordingly, it is always in the material self-interest of every individual to keep all of their MUs irrespective of how much the other three subjects contribute: If every group member invested 20 MUs, each subject would earn 0.4 × 80 = 32 MUs. If one group member engages in free-riding (e.g., s/he contributes 0 MUs) and the other three group members still invest their 20 MUs, the free-rider earns 44 MUs (20 MUs already owned plus one fourth of the public good, that is, 24 MUs) and each of the other three group members earns 24 MUs. 3 To establish transparency, I want to mention that the following paragraph includes sentences taken from Pfattheicher, Landhäußer, and Keller (in press, Appendix E). INTRODUCTION 12 Given the equal division of the public good irrespective of an individual’s contribution, individuals benefit from selfish behavior regardless of the actions made by other individuals involved in the situation. However, and this again is the tragedy Hardin (1968) referred to, all individuals gain lower benefits if all behave selfishly than if all individuals behave cooperatively (Dawes, 1980). That is, if all of the individuals behave selfishly and contribute 0 MUs they will all end with their original endowment of 20 MUs. In contrast, if all of the individuals behave cooperatively and contribute 20 MUs, they will all end up with 32 MUs. Following this stage, each player is given accurate information on the contributions of the other three players and is then given the option to punish them by investing their own MUs (between 0 and 10 for each player) which reduces the selected other player’s payoff by the factor of three (e.g., the investment of 2 MUs decreases the payoff of another by 6 MUs). The investment of own MUs reflects the negative sanctions Ostrom (1990) referred to and is also known as costly punishment (e.g., Henrich et al., 2006).4 As far back as the 1970s, Caldwell (1976) investigated the effectiveness of a sanction system in a public goods game. He let participants play repeated public goods games in groups of five members. The study included three conditions. In the first condition, the group members were not allowed to communicate. Communication was possible in the second condition. The third condition was an extension of the second; Caldwell added a (costless) option to reduce another individual’s payoff. If at least two group members voted to punish another individual, the income of the other individual was reduced. As with Fehr and Gächter (2002), Caldwell (1976) was able to document a substantially higher level of cooperation when a sanction system was available (vs. not available). In the field of negative sanctions, another game theory paradigm is often used to assess costly punishment: the ultimatum game (Güth, Schmittberger, & Schwarze, 1982).5 The 4 Fehr and Gächter (2002) termed costly punishment of uncooperative interaction partners altruistic punishment. This term is discussed in the general discussion of this dissertation. 5 Costly punishment can also be assessed when an individual simply observes uncooperative behavior. For instance, Kurzban et al. (2007) included an option for observers to costly punish uncooperative actors of a INTRODUCTION 13 ultimatum game consists of two players, the first player can offer a split of a specific amount of money and the second player decides whether to accept the split or not. If the offer is accepted, both players earn the money according to the offer. If the offer is rejected, both players earn nothing. The rejection is often considered to reflect costly punishment (e.g., Henrich et al., 2006; Marlowe et al., 2008) because the rejection reflects punishment “at a cost to […] sanction unfair behavior” (Fehr & Fischbacher, 2003, p. 785). It is not proposed here that costly punishment in a public goods game and costly punishment in an ultimatum game reflect exactly the same behavior based on the same motives. For instance, uncooperative behavior in a public goods game affects the benefit of several individuals whereas in an ultimatum game only one individual is affected. Accordingly, punishment in order to increase group cohesion (Horne, 2001) cannot be a possible motive of costly punishment in the ultimatum game. Also, (interdependent) collectivistic orientations are likely to emerge in groups (Markus & Kitayama, 1991) whereas the group context does not exist in ultimatum games (although interdependence is not precluded in ultimatum games). Additionally, if one is punished in an ultimatum game, the punishment definitely comes from the second player whereas in a typical public goods game one does not know from which group member the punishment comes. So, in a public goods game, costly punishment may be executed in a less (subjectively perceived) identifiable way (although in both games individuals typically act under conditions of anonymity). Moreover, regarding costly punishment in a public goods game, one has to invest resources taken from one’s own endowment to punish whereas in the ultimatum game one rejects a benefit that was not owned before. Research on the endowment effect (Kahneman, Knetsch, & Thaler, 1991; Knetsch, 1989) shows that individuals assign a higher value to things they possess than things they do not possess. Accordingly, assuming all other things being equal, one could expect that individuals are trust game and a prisoner’s dilemma game. This kind of punishment is termed third party punishment (Fehr & Fischbacher, 2004). The present work focuses on punishment that occurs when individuals are directly affected by uncooperative behavior, so third party punishment is neglected in the remainder of the text. INTRODUCTION 14 less likely to punish in a public goods game (vs. in an ultimatum game) where individuals have to punish using their own endowment. Empirical research on the endowment effect and costly punishment is, however, lacking. In the end it is a (still uninvestigated) empirical question whether those who punish in a public goods game will also punish in an ultimatum game. Despite the differences between the two games, both modes of punishment reflect an impulsive response to the perceived unfair behavior of another individual (cf. Chapter 2 “Why and under which conditions individuals punish”). That is, both modes of punishment have the same core. Therefore, in the remainder of the current text and when referring to literature regarding costly punishment, costly punishment in a public goods game will not be distinguished from costly punishment in an ultimatum game if the decisive factor for why a specific study is mentioned (e.g., punishment as a response to unfair behavior) is relevant in both games. In the studies reported on below, the paradigm by Fehr and Gächter (2002) is used to investigate costly punishment in public goods situations. In this paradigm, individuals typically behave under conditions of anonymity, that is, individuals’ behavior cannot be traced back to them. Additionally, one-shot games were applied, that is, individuals interacted only once with another individual. Thus, strategic considerations, such as personal reputation building, mutual reciprocity, and shaping other individuals’ behavior to gain personal benefits, were minimized (cf. Fehr & Gächter, 2002). This represents a much reduced situation and it is questionable whether these kinds of situations emerge outside the laboratory raising fundamental external validity concerns (cf. Feinberg, Cheng, & Willer, 2012; Guala, 2012; Guney & Newell, 2013). However, the benefits of investigating costly punishment in a reduced situation are manifold from the perspective of basic research. Specifically, a causal analytic approach can be applied; moreover, variables can be controlled, for instance when minimizing strategic considerations of individuals that may interfere or interact with the central research question. This is particularly important given that we investigated whether costly punishment is strategically executed in order to gain a valuable reputation (see below and Pfattheicher, Landhäußer, & Keller, 2014, Appendix C). If costly punishment INTRODUCTION 15 had already been strategically executed (i.e., if strategic considerations had not been minimized), the likelihood that we would have been able to have observed an effect in terms of reputation on top of already strategically executed punishment would have been fairly low. In other words, it would have been difficult to investigate the central research question of whether costly punishment is executed to strategically gain a valuable reputation. I do not deny that it is worthwhile investigating costly punishment in situations in which it can be used as a strategy (e.g., when repeated interactions are possible). In fact, individuals strategically adapt their behavior in accordance with a maximizing benefit account (Halevy et al., 2012). However, before we add this additional factor that will likely change the nature of costly punishment we need to understand the basic notion of costly punishment. These thoughts also fit the aim of using parsimonious paradigms to investigate basic human behavior (van Lange et al., 2014). These considerations are also central for the three other papers focusing on costly punishment presented below. The aim of these articles was to understand the basic notion of costly punishment by linking it to cortisol and reactive aggression (Pfattheicher & Keller, in press, Appendix A) and by investigating the basal motivational orientations that may underlie costly punishment (Pfattheicher & Keller, 2013, Appendix D). The same applies to the analysis of antisocial punishment (Pfattheicher et al., in press, Appendix E). The goal here was to understand the basal motives and endocrinological factors of costly punishment beyond strategic considerations. In sum, the present dissertation contributes to the understanding of costly punishment in public goods situations while focusing on the essence of costly punishment. Following this central aim it was methodologically necessary to apply parsimonious paradigms such as the public goods game of Fehr and Gächter (2002). WHY AND UNDER WHICH CONDITIONS INDIVIDUALS COSTLY PUNISH 16 2 Why and under which conditions individuals costly punish The present dissertation aims to understand costly punishment from a biopsychological perspective. Accordingly, this chapter deals with the question of why and under which conditions individuals punish. This chapter will endeavor to build the conceptual framework for the empirical papers presented below. Let me begin by reviewing different possible perspectives to investigate costly punishment. 2.1 Different perspectives on how to investigate costly punishment When solving social dilemma situations one can apply the three general perspectives proposed by Kollock (1998), that is, the structural perspective, the strategic perspective, and the motivational (psychological) perspective. These three general perspectives can also be applied when examining costly punishment. The structural perspective refers to the possibility of costly punishment changing the structure of a social dilemma situation. Specifically, by implementing the option to costly punish uncooperative group members one can increase the cost of uncooperative behavior (because uncooperative behavior is likely to be punished; see Fehr & Gächter, 2002). As a consequence, cooperation levels are substantially higher when an option to costly punish is implemented (vs. not implemented; Fehr & Gächter, 2002) because individuals are motivated to avoid the costs of being punished (Berg, Dickhaut, & McCabe, 1995). Thus, costly punishment can represent a structural approach to increasing cooperation. The strategic perspective refers to the notion that actors try to (strategically) adapt their own behavior and shape the behavior of others in order to gain personal benefits (Halevy et al., 2012). Costly punishment can be used as an individual strategy to gain benefits in several respects, for instance through increased cooperative behavior of a punished individual in the future, given repeated and mutual interactions. Costly punishment may also be used as a strategy to acquire a good reputation which may benefit the costly punisher in future interactions (Barclay, 2006; Nelissen, 2008; but see Chapter 3.3 below regarding this issue). The core of the structural and strategic perspective is the fundamental goal to maximize benefits (Kollock, 1998). It is true that individuals’ behavior can be shaped by structural WHY AND UNDER WHICH CONDITIONS INDIVIDUALS COSTLY PUNISH 17 approaches (Camerer, 2003), for instance through costly punishment (Fehr & Gächter, 2002). It is also true that individuals can strategically and deliberately shape another individual’s behavior which is, in principle, possible through costly punishment (Boyd & Richerson, 1992). However, one has to ask the question whether costly punishment is actually used as a strategy by individuals. That is, do individuals engage in costly punishment to maximize benefits (e.g., to gain a valuable reputation)? Obviously, there is a difference in describing a behavioral tendency as having the potential to be used as a strategy and the notion that a behavioral tendency is actually used as a strategy. These considerations refer to the question of why individuals punish and to the motives and psychological motivations that drive costly punishment (i.e., the motivational perspective). The next chapter outlines in more detail the underlying motives and boundary conditions of costly punishment. 2.2 Costly punishment from a biopsychological perspective 2.2.1 Fairness and justice As outlined above, individuals have incentives for behaving selfishly in public goods situations (i.e., contributing very little or nothing) which damages the collective benefit of the other individuals involved in the situation. A low contribution is often considered unfair (e.g., Crockett, Clark, Lieberman, Tabibnia, & Robbins, 2010; Fehr & Rockenbach, 2003) or a violation of a fairness norm based on fundamental human justice concerns (e.g., Crockett, 2009; Fehr & Fischbacher, 2003, 2004). A low contribution violates distributive justice in that the principle of equal outcomes and equal contributions is violated which results in the perception of unfairness (Fowler, Johnson, & Smirnov, 2005; van Dijk & Wilke, 2000). When fundamental moral principles are violated, moral emotions emerge in individuals (Haidt, 2003). The moral emotion of anger (but not other basic emotions such as sadness; Srivastava, Espinoza, & Fedorikhin, 2009) is consistently reported as the emotion that drives costly punishment in ultimatum games (Pillutla & Murnighan, 1996; Rotemberg, 2008; van’t Wout, Kahn, Sanfey, & Aleman, 2006) and in public goods games (Dawes, Fowler, Johnson, McElreath, & Smirnov, 2007; Fehr & Gächter, 2002; Small & Loewenstein, 2005). WHY AND UNDER WHICH CONDITIONS INDIVIDUALS COSTLY PUNISH 18 Haidt (2003) and others (e.g., Nisbett & Cohen, 1996) have pointed out that anger often elicits the motivation to take revenge. On this basis one can assume that uncooperative behavior that is considered to be unfair elicits anger which in turn results in the motivation to take revenge. Evaluating these considerations, one could deduce that given the striking evidence that costly punishment results from anger about unfair behavior, costly punishment reflects a desire to seek revenge (e.g., de Quervain et al., 2004; Gollwitzer & Bushman, 2012; McCullough, 2008). However, anger can also elicit the motivation to reduce injustice (Haidt, 2003), so it is also possible that costly punishment reflects a strategy to reinstall justice. The issue of whether costly punishment is driven by the motivation to take revenge and/or the motivation to reinstall justice (be it consciously or unconsciously) is still a neglected issue in the field of costly punishment. What can be said at this point is that uncooperative behavior is typically considered to be a violation of a fairness norm. This perception elicits anger which in turn results in costly punishment. Although it is proposed that the concern for fairness and justice is deeply rooted in humans (McCullough, 2008; Sober & Wilson, 1998), individuals differ in their construal of fairness and justice. One central axiom in social psychology captures this point: the subjective construction of reality (Smith & Mackie, 2007). This notion corresponds to the Thomas-Theorem “if men define situations as real, they are real in their consequences” (Thomas & Thomas, 1928) and the notion of “the [subjective] definition of the situation” (Esser, 2000). Applied to the present context, this means that a relatively low contribution to the public good is not per se unfair; it must be considered to be unfair, that is, another’s behavior must be subjectively construed to be an unfair action. Having subjectively construed an action to be unfair, the subsequent cognitive, affective, and physiological consequences are real for this individual. As stated, reality is a subjective construction and individuals differ in its construal. For instance, research on aggression has shown that individuals differ in their subjective hostile interpretations of especially ambiguous behavior of others (i.e., the hostile interpretation bias; Crick & Dodge, 1996; Matthews & Norris, 2002). Likewise, one can WHY AND UNDER WHICH CONDITIONS INDIVIDUALS COSTLY PUNISH 19 assume that individuals differ in their interpretation of a relatively low contribution with respect to unfairness (Srivastava et al., 2009). Indeed, research on fairness has shown that individuals possessing a special sensitivity to unfairness show more anger when an event occurs that can be considered unfair (Schmitt, Baumert, Fetchenhauer, Gollwitzer, Rothmund, & Schlösser, 2009; Schmitt, Neumann, & Montada, 1995). These findings are in line with work by Fetchenhauer and Huang (2004) who documented that individual differences in sensitivity to unfairness were positively related to costly punishment in an ultimatum game. A perspective of individual differences reflecting equity and fairness considerations is also present in two frequently cited articles in the field of behavioral economics (i.e., Bolton & Ockenfels, 2000, and Fehr & Schmidt, 1999). These articles represent cornerstones in this field of research because they are said to deviate from standard economic theory which relies on homo economicus. According to Fehr and Schmidt (1999; Bolton and Ockenfels, 2000, made almost similar assumptions), those individuals who are especially prone to punish possess a so-called “self-centered inequity aversion”. It is self-centered in the way that these “people do not care per se about inequity that exists among people but are only interested in the fairness of their own material payoff relative to the payoff of others” (Fehr & Schmidt, 1999, p. 819). The Fehr and Schmidt (1999) model does not actually strongly deviate from standard economic models but shifts the perspective from maximizing one’s own material benefits (standard economic model) to maximizing one’s own material benefits and costly punishing those who have jeopardized one’s own material benefits relative to others (i.e., the principle of equity). This also holds true for the model proposed by Bolton and Ockenfels (2000).6 One can conclude that in the field of behavioral economics also individual differences in equity and fairness considerations are acknowledged to predict costly punishment. 6 Selten (1998) emphasized that it is not the objective deviation that counts but the subjectively perceived “inequity aversion”. This point was not included in the Fehr and Schmidt (1999) model. It is also unclear why they restricted their model to “self-centered inequality aversion” given that it is well documented that individuals also react to inequality when they are not directly affected (e.g., Bendor & Mookherjee, 1990). WHY AND UNDER WHICH CONDITIONS INDIVIDUALS COSTLY PUNISH 20 Another relevant individual difference is that of right wing authoritarianism (RWA). One dimension of RWA (i.e., authoritarian aggression) reflects the belief that ingroup norm deviants have to be punished (Cohrs, 2013; Kessler & Cohrs, 2008). RWA is relevant here because uncooperative behavior can be considered to be a violation of a fairness norm by an ingroup member (Crockett, 2009; Fehr & Fischbacher, 2003, 2004). Thus, one can assume that individuals who possess the belief that ingroup norm deviants have to be punished (i.e., individuals with a relatively strong disposition for authoritarian aggression) are more likely to engage in costly punishment as compared with individuals who possess only a weak attitude of authoritarian aggression (cf. Kessler & Cohrs, 2008). Another individual difference worth mentioning with regard to norm violations is the prevention focus. Specifically, prevention-focused individuals possess a vigilant sensitivity to negative social information, especially regarding norm violations (Higgins, 1997; Keller & Pfattheicher, in press, Appendix G). On this basis one can argue that prevention-focused individuals should be particularly sensitive to the negative event of an unfair contribution, which likely reflects a violation of a fairness norm (e.g., Crockett, 2009; Fehr & Fischbacher, 2003, 2004). In one of the empirical papers presented below (Pfattheicher & Keller, 2013, Appendix D), it is shown that strongly prevention-focused individuals are indeed more likely to engage in costly punishment as compared with weakly prevention-focused individuals. To sum up, there is strong empirical evidence that costly punishment is predominantly driven by anger on the basis of a fairness norm violation by low contributors. Moreover, as conceptualized in the approaches of individual differences, one can assume that individuals differ in their inclination to punish unfair others. The question that is asked in the following part is whether costly punishment is driven by impulsivity or by a more deliberate process. This is worth discussing because: a) there are contrary perspectives regarding this issue, and b) to shed more light on the psychological process of costly punishment. WHY AND UNDER WHICH CONDITIONS INDIVIDUALS COSTLY PUNISH 21 2.2.2 Impulsivity Theories on social cognition typically emphasize two systems of information processing (e.g., Bless, Fiedler, & Strack, 2004; Gawronski & Bodenhausen, 2006, 2007; Petty, Cacioppo, & Goldman, 1981; Strack & Deutsch, 2004, 2012). In the first system, information is processed automatically, unconsciously, and effortlessly in terms of cognitive resources. In the second system, information is processed in a controlled, conscious, and effortful way. The preconditions for the second system to operate are the motivation to deliberatively process and the availability of cognitive capacities to engage in deliberative processing (Fazio, 1990). For instance, Strack and Deutsch (2004, 2012) have postulated the existence of an impulsive system and a reflective system which can operate in parallel. In the impulsive system, behavioral outcomes are said to be driven by an automatically spreading activation in an associative network, resulting in relatively rapidly executed behavior after a stimulus occurred. In the reflective system, behavioral outcomes are said to be driven by a deliberative, resource-consuming decision process, resulting in relatively slowly executed behavior after a stimulus occurred. The impact of the impulsive and reflective system with regard to economic choice is an issue of recent research. Rand, Greene, and Nowak (2012) have shown that the more individuals contribute to a public good the faster, that is, the more impulsively (Strack & Deutsch, 2004, 2012) they make their decision. In several subsequent studies Rand et al. (2012) have documented that prosocial, as compared with antisocial, behavior in different economic games is rather impulsively than deliberately executed. Generally speaking, the research by Rand et al. (2012) contributes to the debate over whether humans are basically selfish actors and whether this selfish “default mode” needs to be overwritten by the reflective system (e.g., Binmore, 2005; Binmore & Shaked, 2010; DeWall, Baumeister, Gailliot, & Maner, 2008; Haidt & Kesebir, 2010) or whether humans can also act as genuine prosocial actors with no need for the reflective system to control a selfish default mode (Haidt & Kesebir, 2010; Zaki & Mitchell, 2013). Research by Rand et al. (2012; see also Cappelletti, Goth, & Ploner, 2011; Schulz, Fischbacher, Thöni, & Utikal, in press) indicates that reducing the impact of the reflective system (e.g., through ego depletion or stimulating intuitive thinking; Cappelletti et al., 2011; WHY AND UNDER WHICH CONDITIONS INDIVIDUALS COSTLY PUNISH 22 Rand et al., 2012; Schulz et al., in press) increases prosocial behavior and cooperation. If the reflective system had overwritten a selfish default mode, selfish behavior should have been more likely to emerge when the reflective system had been reduced. Actually, the reverse was the case, which speaks to the notion that humans can act as genuinely prosocial actors.7 Regarding costly punishment, some scholars have argued that costly punishment is based on the reflective system, specifically, that costly punishment is deliberatively executed in order to uphold a fairness norm (Knoch & Fehr, 2007; Knoch, Pascual-Leone, Meyer, Treyer, & Fehr, 2006;). Others have argued that costly punishment is based on the impulsive system, specifically, that costly punishment is executed impulsively (Crockett et al., 2010; Sanfey, Rilling, Aronson, Nystrom, & Cohen, 2003; Tabibnia, Satpute, & Lieberman, 2008). Empirical evidence for the notion that costly punishment is based on the reflective system comes from research on a brain region called the right dorsolateral prefrontal cortex (rDLPFC) which is related to self-controlled, reflective processes (Miller & Cohen, 2001). Knoch et al. (2006) have shown that disrupting rDLPFC activity via transcranial magnetic stimulation reduces costly punishment in an ultimatum game, suggesting that in the default mode (when the rDLPFC is not disrupted) self-controlled processes are at work driving costly punishment. However, exactly the opposite results have been documented by Brüne and colleagues (Brüne, Juckel, & Enzi, 2013; Brüne et al., 2012). In their studies, disrupting the rDLPFC increased costly punishment in an ultimatum game and a third-party punishment paradigm. Further neuropsychological evidence for the notion that costly punishment is based on the impulsive system comes 7 Of note, when integrating research on aggression and ego depletion, that is, ego depletion increases aggression after a provocation (DeWall, Baumeister, Stillman, Gailliot, 2007; Stucke & Baumeister, 2006), one has to conclude that humans are not per se prosocial or antisocial but that it is dependent on the context. Specifically, when provoked, individuals have to override an antisocial tendency (i.e., aggression; DeWall et al., 2007; Stucke & Baumeister, 2006), but in more affectively neutral contexts there seems to be a tendency in favor of the assumption that humans can also act as genuinely prosocial actors with no need for the reflective system to control a selfish default mode (Zaki & Mitchell, 2013). WHY AND UNDER WHICH CONDITIONS INDIVIDUALS COSTLY PUNISH 23 from Tabibnia et al. (2008). These authors were able to document a positive relation between activation in the right ventrolateral prefrontal cortex (rVLPFC), a brain region that is associated with regulatory processes in terms of emotions, and individuals’ acceptance of unfair offers in the ultimatum game.8 This result suggests that refraining from costly punishment (accepting an unfair offer) for selfish reasons requires regulatory, controlled processes. To sum up the neuropsychological literature, findings for the notion that costly punishment is based on the reflective system are rather mixed. Social psychological research has also dealt with the question of which system costly punishment may be based on. Wang et al. (2011) have investigated costly punishment in an ultimatum game in which they varied whether individuals could punish immediately after an unfair offer occurred versus a time delay between the unfair offer and the decision to punish. Results based on three studies involving different time delay conditions (simply counting numbers for 5 minutes, no distraction for 5 or 2.5 minutes) convincingly showed that costly punishment was substantially reduced when individuals made the decision to punish after a time delay. Thus, disturbing the possibility of impulsivity using a time delay (e.g., Papies, Barsalou, & Custers, 2012), that is, taking away the impulsive component of the punishment decision, reduces the amount of costly punishment.9 From these findings one can infer that costly punishment is an impulsive choice. Moreover, Ben-Shakhar, Bornstein, Hopfensitz, and van Winden (2007) showed in a 8 One has to note, however, that the correlation between the activation of the rVLPFC and individuals’ acceptance of unfair offers was based on only eleven participants and was extremely high (r = .76), possibly too high to be true (cf. Vul, Harris, Winkielman, & Pashler, 2009). 9 This experimental approach is in line with the notion of showing a process by disrupting it (Jacoby & Sassenberg, 2011). Specifically, a default condition in which the hypothesized process can function is compared to a condition in which the process is eliminated. The behavior of interest (or in general ‘the outcome’) should be reduced when the process that accounts for the outcome is eliminated (cf. Spencer, Zanna, & Fong, 2005). In the study by Wang et al. (2011), the process (i.e., the impulsive system) is disrupted by the time delay and a reduction in costly punishment is shown. WHY AND UNDER WHICH CONDITIONS INDIVIDUALS COSTLY PUNISH 24 power-to-take game10 that costly punishers as compared with non-punishers had a significantly greater skin conductance level (SCL) before and after engaging in costly punishment. SCLs are related to arousal (e.g., Critchley, Elliott, Mathias, & Dolan, 2000).11 Thus, these results imply that costly punishment accompanies arousal. Strack and Deutsch (2004) argued that high arousal interrupts the reflective system making the impulsive system more dominant. Consequently, the findings of Ben-Shakhar et al. (2007) bolster the assumption that costly punishment is based on the impulsive system. Additional evidence that costly punishment reflects an impulsive action stems from research on ego-depletion (cf. Baumeister, 2002). Research on ego-depletion has shown that impulsive behavior is more likely to emerge when cognitive resources are depleted (DeWall et al., 2007; Robinson, Schmeichel, & Inzlicht, 2010; Stucke & Baumeister, 2006). Interestingly, Halali, Bereby-Meyer, and Meiran (in press) showed that egodepletion increased costly punishment in an ultimatum game. In another study, these authors showed that participants were faster in terms of reaction times in rejecting an unfair offer than in accepting it. As outlined above, faster reactions are assigned to the impulsive system (Strack & Deutsch, 2004, 2012). Taking a biopsychological perspective on costly punishment in terms of impulsivity, recent research has shown that the basal level of the neurotransmitter serotonin in blood is negatively related to costly punishment in an ultimatum game (Emanuele, Brondino, Bertona, Re, & Geroldi, 2008) and, accordingly, that the depletion of tryptophan, which lowers brain serotonin levels, increases costly punishment (Crockett et al., 2010). This is particularly noteworthy because the depletion of serotonin was positively related to the expression of anger and impulsivity in other research (Castrogiovanni, Capone, 10 In a power-to-take game, Player A can take money from the endowment of Player B. Subsequently, Player B can destroy both assets (both receive nothing which is equivalent to the ultimatum game). Destroying both assets reflects costly punishment if Player B would still have possessed something. 11 Of note, SCLs are not valence specific; for instance, Khalfa, Isabelle, Jean-Pierre, and Manon (2002) found that SCLs increase when an individual listens to fearful music but also when they listen to happy music. WHY AND UNDER WHICH CONDITIONS INDIVIDUALS COSTLY PUNISH 25 Maremmani, Marazziti, 1994; Kavoussi, Armstead, & Coccaro, 1997; Krakowski, 2003), supporting the notion that costly punishment is indeed driven by impulsivity. To sum up the literature, costly punishment can be considered to be predominantly driven by anger (Dawes et al., 2007; Fehr & Gächter, 2002; Pillutla & Murnighan, 1996; Rotemberg, 2008; Small & Loewenstein, 2005; van’t Wout et al., 2006) on the basis of a fairness norm violation by low contributors (Cubitt, Drouvelis, Gächter, & Kabalin, 2011; Fehr & Fischbacher, 2004; Knoch, Gianotti, Baumgartner, & Fehr, 2010). Some scholars have argued that costly punishment is based on the reflective system (Knoch et al., 2006; Knoch & Fehr, 2007) whereas others have argued that costly punishment is based on the impulsive system, specifically, that costly punishment is impulsively executed (Crockett et al., 2010; Sanfey et al., 2003; Tabibnia et al., 2008). Evaluation of the literature reviewed above reveals that the evidence largely supports the impulsive account. This does not mean that every decision to punish is impulsively executed. Rather, costly punishment seems to be predominately impulsively executed. 2.2.3 Anticipated reward Some scholars argue that “all vengeful acts are attempts to escape pain” (Frijda, 1994, p. 279). Applied to the context of costly punishment the argument is put forward that individuals engage in costly punishment because they anticipate reward (Carlsmith, Wilson, & Gilbert, 2008; de Quervain et al., 2004; Knutson, 2004). That is, after the negative experience of anger in response to the unfair behavior of an uncooperative other, individuals assume that they can improve their mood by punishing the uncooperative other. Of note is the idea that anticipated reward is not in contrast with the impulsivity approach because the basic motive of an impulsive action can indeed be anticipated reward. This notion is well in line with Gray’s reinforcement sensitivity theory (RST; Gray, 1970, 1982) and empirical findings (Torrubia, Avila, Moltó, & Caseras, 2001) that emphasize reward-seeking through impulsive actions. Self-control theory (Mischel, 1961, 2012) specifies this relation and postulates that impulsive actions (based on a lack of self-control) are often executed to seek short-term rather than longterm rewards. WHY AND UNDER WHICH CONDITIONS INDIVIDUALS COSTLY PUNISH 26 Empirical evidence does suggest that when individuals are treated unfairly they expect to feel better after engaging in costly punishment (Carlsmith et al., 2008; of note, in this study participants actually felt worse after engaging in costly punishment). In line with this finding, de Quervain et al. (2004) found that the contemplation of costly punishment is related to activation in a brain region typically associated with reward (i.e., the dorsal striatum; Balleine, Delgado, & Hikosaka, 2007). On basis of these findings, de Quervain et al. (2004) argue that individuals engage in costly punishment because they anticipate reward. However, the argument of de Quervain et al. (2004) seems to be a weak one as the activation of the dorsal striatum is also associated with aversive, unexpected, or novel stimuli (e.g., Bromberg-Martin, Matsumoto, & Hikosaka, 2010; Delgado, Li, Schiller, & Phelps, 2008). Based on the logic of de Quervain et al. (2004), one can equally argue that individuals punish because they anticipate feeling worse (which is obviously not plausible) or because they anticipate engaging in a novel experience by means of punishing. What must be said is that the activation of a brain area is often too unspecific to enable conclusions to be drawn about the motives of behavior. Thus, the study of de Quervain et al. (2004) actually remains salient regarding the driving forces of costly punishment (cf. Peacock, 2007), although it is frequently citied to support the idea of anticipated reward when punishing (e.g., Guala, 2012). Gollwitzer and Bushman (2012) have questioned that individuals typically punish in order to improve their mood or to seek reward. They argue that costly punishment reflects retributive punishment elicited by the violation of social norms and that people punish unfair others in order to give the uncooperative others what they deserve, but not merely because they want to improve their mood. Gollwitzer and Bushman (2012) have tested the assumption that individuals strategically engage in costly punishment in order to feel better. They implemented two conditions and used costly punishment in a public goods game as the dependent variable. In the first condition, participants were told that they could not improve their mood in the study (because their mood was frozen by means of a pill, in reality a placebo). In the second condition, participants were not given a pill. Gollwitzer and Bushman (2012) first showed that anger about uncooperative WHY AND UNDER WHICH CONDITIONS INDIVIDUALS COSTLY PUNISH 27 behavior did not differ between the conditions.12 If participants improve their mood by means of costly punishment, costly punishment would be more likely to be shown in the condition in which the participants could actually improve their mood, that is, the condition without mood freezing. However, Gollwitzer and Bushman (2012) reported that costly punishment did not differ across the two conditions (although statistical power was sufficiently high).13 Remarkably, this finding was able to be conceptually replicated twice by the authors (see Study 2 and 3 in Gollwitzer & Bushman, 2012). By evaluating the (although sparse) empirical findings on anticipated reward one can come to the conclusion that individuals believe that engaging in costly punishment improves their mood (Carlsmith et al., 2008). However, as Gollwitzer and Bushman (2012) showed, participants did not strategically engage in costly punishment in order to improve their mood. One has to note that merely agreeing with the notion that one can improve one’s mood by means of costly punishment (like the participants in Carlsmith et al., 2008) is different from anticipated reward being the actual motive. Nevertheless, Carlsmith et al. (2008) stated that “people use punishment to strategically repair their negative mood” (p. 1323, emphasis added). However, this was not tested by these authors; they did not show, for instance, an association between the belief in anticipated reward and costly punishment. Only Gollwitzer and Bushman (2012) directly tested whether individuals strategically engage in costly punishment to improve their mood. Therefore, the conclusion of Gollwitzer and Bushman (2012) should be preferred, that is, individuals typically do not strategically costly punish to improve their mood. The study by Gollwitzer and Bushman (2012) speaks against the “strategic perspective” of costly punishment, specifically, that costly punishment is part of a benefit-maximizing 12 Indeed, one could criticize the “pill-study” because if the pill actually had frozen one’s mood, anger should not be elicited. However, given that Gollwitzer and Bushman (2012) replicated the main finding twice with different methods, their conclusion seems valid. 13 This still represents a problem because with typical statistical methods (as used by Gollwitzer & Bushman, 2012) one cannot accept but only reject a null-hypothesis. Gollwitzer and Bushman (2012) could have tested against a small effect, as recently proposed by Simonsohn (2013). That is, to reject the null-hypothesis that there is a small effect leading to the conclusion that there is a theoretically negligible smaller-than-a-small-effect or a null-effect. WHY AND UNDER WHICH CONDITIONS INDIVIDUALS COSTLY PUNISH 28 strategy (i.e., the psychological benefit of improved mood). Building on the findings of Gollwitzer and Bushman (2012), it seems unlikely that costly punishment is typically part of a (mood repairing) strategy. Still, this finding does not contradict the notion that costly punishment is strategically used in another sense, for instance to gain a valuable reputation. This notion is discussed in the following section. 2.2.4 Reputation In their seminal study, Fehr and Gächter (2002) wrote: “To rule out that repetition created cooperation or punishment through [...] reputation, the group composition changed from period to period such that no subject ever met another subject more than once” (p. 137, emphasis added). Several years later, Gächter and Herrmann (2009) wrote that individuals “cooperate and punish others even if there are no gains from future cooperation or any other reputational gains” (p. 791, emphasis added). The question that arises from these statements is: do individuals strategically punish to gain a good reputation? The statements of Fehr and Gächter (2002) as well as Gächter and Herrmann (2009) do suggest this. Also, the considerations of several other scholars point in this direction (Barclay, 2006; Dos Santos, Rankin, & Wedekind, 2011; Hagen & Hammerstein, 2006; Hilbe & Traulsen, 2012; Kurzban et al., 2007; Nelissen, 2008; Piazza & Bering, 2008; Shaw & Santos, 2012; Sylwester, Herrmann, & Bryson, 2013; Tennie, 2012). If individuals strategically punish to gain a good reputation, they should be more likely to engage in costly punishment when reputational concerns are activated. In the empirical paper presented below (Pfattheicher et al., 2014, Appendix C) the opposite is shown: costly punishment is actually reduced under conditions of reputational concerns. Reconsidering the strategic perspective on costly punishment (costly punishment as part of a benefit-maximizing strategy), the findings speak against the notion that costly punishment is strategically used to gain benefits, in this case reputational benefits. The issue of reputation and costly punishment is outlined in detail below during the discussion of the empirical paper (Pfattheicher et al., 2014, Appendix C). WHY AND UNDER WHICH CONDITIONS INDIVIDUALS COSTLY PUNISH 29 2.3 Summary The previous chapter has dealt with the question of why and under which conditions individuals punish. One can conclude that costly punishment can be considered to be driven by anger on the basis of a fairness norm violation by low contributors. It reflects behavior that seems to result from the impulsive system rather than the reflective system, that is, costly punishment can be considered to be an impulsive act. Furthermore, research on anticipated reward and reputation suggests that costly punishment is neither strategically executed in order to improve one’s mood nor in order to gain a valuable reputation. The findings, therefore, question the benefit-maximizing strategic perspective. Although research on costly punishment has produced a large amount of articles in recent years (to date, Fehr and Gächter’s seminal article of 2002 has been cited more than 2,700 times according to Google Scholar), considerable research gaps still exist. The empirical papers I present in the following sections all address several neglects in the field of costly punishment. One research gap relates to the endocrinology of costly punishment. Specifically, in the first paper on costly punishment it is argued that costly punishment reflects, at least to some degree, reactive aggression. We then built on recent findings documenting that basal cortisol was negatively related to reactive aggression (e.g., Böhnke, Bertsch, Kruk, & Naumann, 2010). In line with these findings, it was possible to show a negative relation between cortisol and costly punishment, a relation that had not been previously documented. The first paper not only aimed to address a research gap by investigating the relation of basal cortisol and costly punishment, it was also written to explicitly link costly punishment to reactive aggression. That is, the first manuscript also makes a point on the conceptual level. The second paper on costly punishment deals with the strategic perspective on costly punishment. As outline above, several scholars consider costly punishment to be strategically executed to gain reputational benefits, although this notion was barely tested. As such, the second paper on costly punishment constitutes an important contribution in that it empirically – and not only on a theoretical level like so many others before – addresses the relation of reputation and costly punishment. WHY AND UNDER WHICH CONDITIONS INDIVIDUALS COSTLY PUNISH 30 The third paper on costly punishment attends to another gap in research on costly punishment, specifically, linking costly punishment to individual differences. As far as I can judge following an extensive literature review, the paper presented below reflects the first piece of research that considers the relation of individual differences and costly punishment in public goods situations empirically. Specifically, it is shown that dispositional prevention focus (Higgins, 1997) but not dispositional behavioral inhibition (Carver & White, 1994) predicts costly punishment. That is, the aim was to investigate costly punishment (a) from the perspective of individual differences and (b) from the perspective of basal motivational orientations and to contribute in that way to a better understanding of costly punishment. The fourth paper on costly punishment deals with the “dark side” of costly punishment. In this paper the biopsychology of antisocial punishment, that is, the punishment of cooperative individuals was investigated. Little is currently known about this behavior that reliably emerges in public goods games when an option to punish is available (Dreber & Rand, 2012; Herrmann, Thöni, & Gächter, 2008). The paper proposes that, when scoring off cooperative group members, dominance motives are at work. In line with these considerations, it is shown that the dominance related hormone testosterone as well as psychological dominance motives predict antisocial punishment under the condition of a relatively low cortisol level (reflecting the so-called dual-hormonehypothesis, see Carré & Mehta, 2011; Mehta & Josephs, 2010). Of note, the present paper reflects the first empirical work that aims to shed light on the motives and physiology of antisocial punishment and, therefore, also attempts to fill a considerable research gap. In sum, the papers presented in the following section paint a biopsychological picture of costly punishment. This is the aim of the present dissertation: to understand costly punishment from a biopsychological perspective. The empirical papers presented below all address specific gaps in the field of costly punishment. As a whole they shed light on underlying biopsychological factors and boundary conditions of costly punishment in public goods situations. EMPIRICAL PAPERS 31 3 Empirical papers In this chapter I present and discuss five empirical papers that are the result of my time as a doctoral candidate (a sixth, a seventh, and an eighth paper do not exactly fit into the theme of the present dissertation but are attached in Appendix F, G, and H). 3.1 Towards a biopsychological understanding of costly punishment: The role of basal cortisol (Pfattheicher & Keller, in press, Appendix A) This paper is built on recent findings that have documented an inverse relation of basal cortisol and aggression after a provocation (i.e., reactive aggression; Böhnke, Bertsch, Kruk, & Naumann, 2010; Böhnke, Bertsch, Kruk, Richter, & Naumann, 2010; Feilhauer, Cima, Korebrits, & Nicholson, 2013; Poustka et al., 2010).14 Reactive aggression can be defined as an angry, impulsive response to perceived provocation or interpersonal frustration (Crick & Dodge, 1996; van Goozen, Fairchild, Snoek, & Harold, 2007).15 As outlined above, anger seems to be the emotion that drives costly punishment, and it seems to be an impulsive response to uncooperative behavior and the violation of a fairness norm, that is, a perceived provocation or an interpersonal frustration. Therefore, given that costly punishment corresponds to the main criteria of reactive aggression, one can reasonably assume that costly punishment reflects, at least to some degree, reactive aggression. Indeed, Ernst Fehr16 himself called costly punishment “retaliation” (Fehr & Fischbacher, 2004) which is used as a synonym for reactive aggression (Hubbard, Dodge, Cillessen, Coie, & Schwartz 2001). 14 Of note, Alink et al. (2008) found no significant inverse relation between basal cortisol and aggression in a meta-analysis for adolescents (it was only found for young children). However, Alink et al. (2008) did not differentiate between specific forms of aggression (e.g., reactive or proactive aggression, overt or covert aggression, social ostracism, blind rage etc.). Thus, they do not consider the issue regarding the specific relations of specific forms of aggression and basal cortisol, which would be, however, quite important given that specific forms of aggression are differently correlated with basal cortisol (see e.g., Poustka et al., 2010). 15 A clear distinction between reactive and proactive aggression in terms of costly punishment is made in the empirical paper (Pfattheicher & Keller, in press, Appendix A). 16 The first author of the seminal article Fehr and Gächter (2002). EMPIRICAL PAPERS 32 On this basis we assumed that costly punishment should be related to biopsychological factors similar to reactive aggression, in this case, the steroid hormone cortisol. As reported in Pfattheicher and Keller (in press, Appendix A), basal cortisol was indeed significantly negatively related to costly punishment.17 Remarkably, research on reactive aggression has produced similar results to the research on costly punishment. As with costly punishment, reactive aggression is increased when cognitive resources are depleted (DeWall et al., 2007; Stucke & Baumeister, 2006; Robinson et al., 2010), it is mainly driven by anger in response to a provocation (Crick & Dodge, 1996; Denson, Pedersen, Ronquillo, & Nandy, 2009; Wilkowski & Robinson, 2008), and it reflects an impulsive action (Crick & Dodge, 1996; Denson, von Hippel, Kemp, & Teo, 2010; Raine et al., 2006; Richetin & Richardson, 2008). Why, apart from corresponding empirical findings, should cortisol be inversely related to costly punishment? Van Goozen and colleagues (van Goozen, Fairchild, & Harold, 2008; van Goozen et al., 2007; see also Alink et al., 2008; Bushman & Huesmann, 2010; Eysenck, 1970) postulate a theory of underarousal. They emphasize that under-aroused individuals possess a pronounced tendency to engage in aggressive and impulsive acts. That is to say, under-aroused individuals seek stimulation that may be possible through behaving aggressively. Van Goozen and colleagues (van Goozen et al., 2008; van Goozen et al., 2007) have predicted and reported corresponding literature that underaroused individuals (e.g., individuals with a low level of cortisol) are more likely to engage in aggressive and impulsive acts as compared with normally aroused individuals (see also Schmidt et al., 2013, and Raine et al., 2006). Accordingly, under-aroused individuals seek stimulation that may be gained by punishing uncooperative free-riders. Thus, one can assume that individuals with low cortisol levels tend to engage in impulsive actions. Given that costly punishment can be considered to be an impulsive 17 In this chapter I focus on basal endogenous cortisol while acknowledging that situationally elevated cortisol levels, individual differences in cortisol reactivity to stressors, and cortisol awakening responses may also contribute to a better understanding of aggression. However, heterogeneous results are reported in these vast fields of research (cf. van Goozen, 2005) which is beyond the scope of the present dissertation. EMPIRICAL PAPERS 33 act, it seems reasonable to assume that costly punishment is particularly shown by individuals with low cortisol levels.18 In contrast, high levels of cortisol have been linked to behavioral withdrawal (Blair et al., 2004; Brown et al., 1996; Montoya et al., 2012; Nava et al., 2006; Tops & Boksem, 2011; van Honk et al., 2010; Windle, 1994). In this regard, the omission of costly punishment can be regarded as behavioral withdrawal (cf. Pfattheicher & Keller, 2013, Appendix D) which can lead to the deduction that individuals with high cortisol levels tend to engage in behavioral withdrawal and do not costly punish. Another approach to the question of why endogenous cortisol and costly punishment are inversely related relates to the concept of vigilance. Research by van Honk and colleagues (1998, 2000) has documented that low cortisol levels are positively related to vigilant responses to negative social information. We have shown (Pfattheicher & Keller, 2013, Appendix D) that individuals with a strong prevention focus, that is, individuals possessing a vigilant sensitivity to negative social information, were more likely to engage in costly punishment compared with weakly prevention-focused individuals. Integrating these lines of research, we argue that individuals with relatively low levels of cortisol possess a special vigilance to negative social information. Building on the notion that the uncooperative behavior of another group member constitutes negative social information, that is, the violation of a fairness norm, it seems plausible to assume that individuals that are relatively low (vs. high) in basal cortisol are more likely to engage in costly punishment due to their special vigilance regarding negative social information.19 I have proposed a multiple mediator perspective here (impulsivity, behavioral withdrawal, vigilance), which is in line with recent theorizing that emphasizes several routes to behavior (Bullock et al., 2010; Fiedler et al., 2011; Hayes, 2013). This is worth mentioning because proposing several mediators is not common in social psychological 18 To establish transparency, I want to mention that this paragraph includes sentences taken from Pfattheicher and Keller (in press, Appendix A). 19 To establish transparency, I want to mention that this paragraph includes sentences taken from Pfattheicher and Keller (in press, Appendix A). EMPIRICAL PAPERS 34 literature (although it is not explicitly denied). For instance, when researchers use the Baron and Kenny (1986) approach and report that a direct path between an independent variable X and a dependent variable Y is reduced to zero after controlling for a third variable M, they often speak of “full mediation” (Rucker, Preacher, Tormala, & Petty, 2011). Full mediation implies that a researcher has fully explained the relation of X and Y. However, “full mediation” simply means that the shared variance between X and Y can be statistically explained by M. However, M can be correlated with other mediators (Z) which are then indirectly involved in the statistical mediation of M regarding X and Y (Fiedler et al., 2011). Then the relation of X and Y is not only explained by M but by M and Z. It is also possible that a third variable (say, W) suppresses part of the effect of X on Y, so controlling for W actually increases the direct effect (MacKinnon, Krull, & Lockwood, 2000) which is then not fully mediated anymore by M, although neither M nor X and Y have changed (Rucker et al., 2011). Basically, a multiple mediator perspective is a worthwhile approach given that several routes can lead to specific behavior (Bullock et al., 2010; Fiedler et al., 2011; Hayes, 2013). This perspective was also applied in terms of the relation of basal cortisol and costly punishment. 3.1.1 Discussion In our study (Pfattheicher & Keller, in press, Appendix A) we found that basal cortisol was negatively related to costly punishment. This relation has not been documented before and, therefore, successfully addresses a gap in the field of costly punishment. The work is not only important regarding costly punishment and cortisol but also regarding costly punishment and reactive aggression. The connection between costly punishment and reactive aggression has been made before (Crockett et al., 2010; Osumi et al., 2012; Stirrat & Perrett, 2010) but this empirical paper (Pfattheicher & Keller, in press, Appendix A) represents the first work, as far as I can judge after an extensive literature review, that explicitly builds on findings of reactive aggression and shows corresponding results. Thus, the presented paper does not only relate costly punishment to a prominent and frequently investigated endocrinological factor (cortisol) but also emphasizes and explicitly states that costly punishment should be investigated from the perspective of reactive aggression. This claim is supported by van Lange et al. (2013) who stated “[…] EMPIRICAL PAPERS 35 it is surprising that aggression has received so little attention in social dilemmas, because – unless research suggest otherwise – aggression seems an important orientation in social dilemmas, albeit one that seems activate primarily by the behavior of others” (p. 75). After having established a correlational relation between two concepts of interest (here: cortisol and costly punishment), social psychologists often experimentally manipulate X to investigate X’s causal influence on Y. From this consideration it seems an obvious next step to manipulate cortisol and to analyze whether this manipulation affects costly punishment. Indeed, an enormous amount of literature investigates the effects of exogenous cortisol (e.g., using an oral dose of cortisol) on a variety of behavioral and cognitive outcomes (Dickerson & Kemeny, 2004). Exogenous cortisol actually increases endogenous cortisol levels compared with placebo groups and was even found to increase reactive aggression in women (e.g., Böhnke, Bertsch, Kruk, Richter, & Naumann, 2010). However, after exogenous cortisol is given, a negative feedback loop can be observed, that is, an actually down-regulation of the HPA axis resulting in less endogenous cortisol (Calogero, Gallucci, Gold, & Chrousos, 1988; Kruk, Halasz, Meelis, & Haller, 2004). Additionally, hormones crosstalk on several levels (Viau, 2002), for instance it has been observed that exogenous cortisol lowers endogenous testosterone levels (Cumming, Quigley, & Yen, 1983). Basically, manipulating cortisol levels through exogenous cortisol does not seem to be a valuable approach when investigating the causal relation of endogenous cortisol and costly punishment given that exogenous cortisol seems to affect several biopsychological variables, not only the level of cortisol per se. One may consider manipulating endogenous cortisol not via exogenous cortisol but via psychological stress. For instance, the Trier Social Stress Test (TSST; Kirschbaum, Pirke, & Hellhammer, 1993) or the newer TSST for groups (TSST-G; von Dawans, Kirschbaum, & Heinrichs, 2011) are paradigms that are frequently used to manipulate stress and to increase cortisol levels (although there is typically a non-negligible amount of cortisol non-responders; see e.g., Kuhlmann & Wolf, 2006). The experimental condition of the TSST typically includes a speech task and mathematical task carried out EMPIRICAL PAPERS 36 in front of a jury. However, the TSST has several confounds (e.g., evaluative social presence only in the experimental condition, or activating concepts such as “authorities”, and mood effects; Kirschbaum & Hellhammer, 1994). The confound problem also applies to other manipulations of stress (e.g., the cold pressure task, Smith, Edwards, & McCann, 2007). Moreover, following the emergence of a stressor, the length of time after which specific behavior is investigated is relevant. This is important because cortisol activates cognitive resources to cope with a stressor, which, however, takes some time (cf. Vinkers et al., 2013). Having more cognitive resources may strengthen the deliberative system relative to the impulsive system which may lead to reduced punishment. That is, it seems to depend on the time costly punishment is investigated following the emergence of a stressor. Thus, using the TSST and other methods to manipulate cortisol levels via social stress seems highly problematic because one does not know exactly why specific effects are found. To conclude, a clean experimental investigation of the causal relation of cortisol and costly punishment is almost impossible to accomplish. The present work remains silent regarding the causal nature of the basal cortisol-costly punishment relation. It is possible that future research will not solve this problem. In critically discussing the correlation between costly punishment and cortisol, it could be the case that there is, in fact, no direct causal relation. That is to say, it is not cortisol itself that influences costly punishment but other constructs that are associated with cortisol (e.g., vigilance in individuals with relatively low cortisol levels). From this perspective one can directly investigate the mediators that explain the relation of basal cortisol and costly punishment. I have proposed that the impulsive system could be relevant here, as relatively low basal cortisol levels as well as costly punishment are related to impulsivity (see above). Specifically, one could manipulate or eliminate the mediator (cf. Jacoby & Sassenberg, 2011; Spencer et al., 2005), that is, reduce the influence of the impulsive system. Applying the approach of Wang et al. (2011), one can include a time delay before giving individuals the option to costly punish. In this way the impulsive component in costly punishment can be reduced (Papies et al., 2012; Wang et EMPIRICAL PAPERS 37 al., 2011). If impulsivity is responsible for the cortisol-costly punishment relation, cortisol should not be a predictor when the impulsive component in costly punishment is reduced. Applying the opposite research strategy, one can activate the impulsive system, for instance through ego-depletion (Halali et al., in press) or through time pressure (Sutter, Kocher, & Strauß, 2003). This should increase costly punishment, especially in individuals who are sensitive in terms of impulsivity (i.e., individuals with relatively low cortisol levels). The same approach could be applied with respect to another proposed mediator, vigilance in relatively low cortisol individuals. For instance, one can decrease the vigilant system (e.g., through an induction of mindfulness, e.g., Arch & Craske, 2006; Grier et al., 2003) and should find decreased costly punishment, especially in individuals with a strong vigilant system (i.e., individuals with a relatively low level of cortisol). To conclude, the presented work (Pfattheicher & Keller, in press, Appendix A) represents a valuable step in the investigation of the endocrinological factors that underlie costly punishment. Our work not only aimed to address a research gap by investigating the relation between basal cortisol and costly punishment, we also explicitly linked costly punishment to reactive aggression and made a point on the conceptual level. As such, our work contributes to a better understanding of costly punishment. This goal was also pursued in the papers presented in the following section. 3.2 The eye cue manipulation as subtle induction of a sense of being watched: Empirical validation and theoretical integration (Pfattheicher & Keller, 2014, Appendix B) As outlined above, some scholars have suggested that individuals strategically costly punish in order to gain a valuable reputation (e.g., Barclay, 2006; Dos Santos et al., 2011; Hagen & Hammerstein, 2006; Hilbe & Traulsen, 2012; Kurzban et al. 2007; Nelissen, 2008; Piazza & Bering, 2008; Shaw & Santons, 2012; Sylwester et al., 2013; Tennie, 2012). We tested this assumption in several studies as presented below (Pfattheicher et al., 2014, Appendix C). In one of these studies, we activated reputational concerns via a subtle cue of being watched (i.e., stylized watching eyes). We used this EMPIRICAL PAPERS 38 cue of being watched because its subtle nature provides several methodological advantages in comparison with classic manipulations of reputational concerns and social presence manipulations such as an actual audience or a one-way mirror. These manipulations always include confounds such as sex, attractiveness or group membership of observers and may additionally activate other constructs such as private self-awareness (cf. Pfattheicher & Keller, 2014, Appendix B). In the paper presented below we validated this subtle cue of being watched. Starting in 2005 with the seminal article by Haley and Fessler, subtle cues of being watched have become increasingly popular (for meta-analyses, see Nettle et al., 2013, and Sparks & Barclay, 2013). All eye cue studies published thus far are displayed in Table 1. Papers presenting empirical studies involving subtle cues of being watched typically report the influence of watching eyes on prosocial and antisocial behavior (Nettle et al., 2013; Sparks & Barclay, 2013). Specifically, individuals’ prosocial behavior increases and individuals’ antisocial behavior decreases when subtle cues of being watched are presented. Research on watching eyes has proposed that a sense of being seen is induced by subtle cues of being watched (e.g., Izuma, 2012; Nettle et al., 2013). However, as yet no empirical evidence has tested this assumption. Accordingly, there is a substantial amount of published articles that have built on the not empirically tested assumption that subtle cues of being watched induce an increased sense of being seen. This strongly calls for a validation study. We (Pfattheicher & Keller, 2014; Appendix B) tested the validity of a subtle cue of being watched building on the spotlight effect (Gilovich, Kruger, & Medvec, 2002; Gilovich, Medvec, & Savitsky, 2000). The spotlight effect reflects individuals’ tendency “to believe that the social spotlight shines more brightly on them than it really does” (Gilovich et al., 2000, p. 211). Given that the spotlight effect reflects an increased sense of being seen, we applied this paradigm. In a study involving two independent samples, we asked participants to imagine that they were wearing a T-shirt displaying a wellknown public figure (the pop singer Florian Silbereisen or the terrorist Osama bin EMPIRICAL PAPERS 39 Table 1. Overview of published studies involving subtle cues of being watched Manuscript Eyes Cue Condition Control Condition Criterion Bateson et al. (2006) Photos of human eyes Photos of flowers Honest payments Bateson et al. (2013) “signs featuring a large pair No Eyes Littering behavior Photo of flowers Disapproval of moral of staring eyes” (p. 2) Bourrat et al. (2011) Photo of neutral human eyes transgressions Burnham & Hare Actual present robot with No present robot Contributions in repeated public (2007) large eyes Carbon & Hesslinger Photo of angry human eyes Photo of flowers Pro- and antisocial scenarios Photo of neutral human eyes Photo of flowers Charitable donations in a goods games (2011) Ekström (2011) supermarket Ernest-Jones et al. Photos of human eyes Photos of flowers Littering behavior in a university (2010) Fehr & Schneider cafeteria Ornate eyes and nose Neutral graphic Trust game Francey & Photos of neutral human Photos of flowers Littering behavior at a bus stop Bergmuller (2012) eyes Haley & Fessler Ornate eyes and nose PC desktop background Dictator game (2010) (2005) Keller & Pfattheicher with laboratory emblem Neutral-looking Eyes Blank (no eyes) Proenvironmental donations Angry-looking eyes White desktop Dictator game (2011) Mifune et al. (2010) background Nettle et al. (2012) Female and male eyes Emblem of the institute Dictator game (2 conditions) Nettle et al. (2013) Photo of angry human eyes No eyes Bicycle theft Oda et al. (2011) Ornate eyes and nose Blank (no eyes) Single dictator game Panagopoulos (2014, Photos of human eyes American flag, palm tree Voting behavior in press) Powell et al. (2012) (2 control conditions) Neutral-looking eyes Three geometric stars Charitable donations in a supermarket Raihani & Bshary Photo of neutral human eyes (2012) Photo of flowers, black Dictator game square, blank (3 control conditions) Rigdon et al. (2009) Three dots resembling eyes: Sparks & Barclay . . . Three dots not Dictator game . resembling eyes: . . Ornate eyes and nose Landscape image Dictator game Ornate eyes and nose Butterfly Dictator game (2013) Tane & Takezawa (2011) EMPIRICAL PAPERS 40 Laden) and to estimate how many people would notice their T-shirt. Results revealed that under conditions of watching eyes (vs. no watching eyes) participants gave higher estimations regarding the number of people who would notice the T-shirt (i.e., an increased sense of being seen). The findings speak to the notion that subtle cues of being watched do induce an increased sense of being seen.20 3.2.1 Discussion The question remains of how exactly subtle cues of being watched operate. For instance, it is possible that subtle cues of being watched increase arousal which in turn influences a sense of being seen, because arousal is associated with evaluative social presence (Dickerson & Kemeny, 2004). Indeed, evaluative social presence was even used to induce arousal, that is, the psychological state of stress (Kirschbaum et al., 1993). To test the assumption that subtle cues of being watched operate via arousal, one could vary the presence of a subtle cue of being watched while tracking individuals arousal on-line for instance via electroencephalography (Klimesch, 1999). From a motivational perspective, subtle cues of being watched can induce the motivation to influence others’ perception of oneself (i.e., impression management; Leary, 1995; Leary & Kowalski, 1990). In other words, subtle cues of being watched activate individuals’ motivation to present themselves in a positive way, that is, to gain a valuable reputation (Barclay, 2013; Oda, Niwa, Honma, & Hiraishi, 2011). This can be achieved by means of socially desirable actions such as prosocial behavior. These considerations are well in line with the empirical findings that show that subtle cues of being watched increase prosocial behavior (Nettle et al., 2013; Sparks & Barclay, 2013).21 These notions also fit with the concepts of public self-awareness (Gervais & Norenzayan, 2012; Mifune, Hashimoto, & Yamagishi, 2010) and reputational concerns (Emler, 1990), which reflect a state in which one’s attention is directed to how one appears in the eyes 20 To establish transparency, I want to mention that this paragraph includes sentences taken from Pfattheicher and Keller (2014, Appendix B). 21 These considerations are further implemented in costly signaling theory (Grafen, 1990; Zahavi, 1975) which is discussed in the next chapter (3.3). They also correspond to the notion of the ought-self implemented in regulatory focus theory which is discussed in Chapter 3.4. EMPIRICAL PAPERS 41 of others (Fenigstein, Scheier, & Busss, 1975; Fenigstein & Vanable, 1992). Given that humans often present themselves in a valuable way when others are present and are motivated to gain a valuable reputation (Griskevicius, Tybur, & Den Bergh, 2010; van Vugt, Roberts, & Hardy, 2007), it seems reasonable to assume that subtle cues of being watched activate the reputation system. That is, subtle cues of being watched increase individuals’ motivation to present themselves in a socially desirable, reputationincreasing way (Nettle et al., 2013; but see the discussion below regarding this point). Recently, Bateson et al. (2013) attended to the question of whether subtle cues of being watched universally increase prosocial behavior, or whether they induce conformity to social norms. Often, these two notions fall together given the social norm to behave prosocially (e.g., Nettle et al., 2013). Bateson et al. (2013) suggested disentangling the two notions and proposed testing subtle cues of being watched in a situation where there is a social norm to behave antisocially. They tried to implement this by investigating subtle cues of being watched in a situation where the descriptive norm (i.e., what others do) is to litter the environment, specifically, when the ground was littered with leaflets (Cialdini, Reno, & Kallgren, 1990). Bateson et al. (2013) showed that subtle cues of being watched increased prosocial behavior (not littering the environment); but they found no effect for a pronounced descriptive norm under watching eyes. From this finding one can conclude that subtle cues of being watched do not, at least in this case, induce conformity to descriptive social norms. The findings of Bateson et al.’s (2013) study make sense from the perspective of the focus theory of normative conduct (Cialdini et al., 1990). This theory proposes that individuals align their behavior to present social norms in a given situation (i.e., descriptive and/or injunctive norms). From this theoretical perspective, it is possible that Bateson et al. (2013) did not fully disentangle prosocial behavior and social norms because individuals still may focus on the present injunctive norm (what one ought to do, that is, not littering). Thus, the injunctive norm was not eliminated in the study, and individuals may still have focused on the injunctive norm, especially when being watched. Focusing on the injunctive norm when being watched may, therefore, run against the effect suggested by Bateson et al. (2013). EMPIRICAL PAPERS 42 From my perspective, it is likely that individuals align their behavior to norms, especially to injunctive norms, when a subtle cue of being watched is present. This seems reasonable because only injunctive norms and not descriptive norms include the notion of social disapproval (i.e., negative sanctions or punishment by others) when the injunctive norm is not fulfilled (Cialdini et al., 1990), and social disapproval is only possible when others are present, that is, under conditions of subtle cues of being watched. Accordingly, it seems reasonable to assume that injunctive norms are likely to be pronounced under subtle cues of being watched given that the violation of injunctive norms are particularly disapproved of when noticed by present others. Turning to the more fine-tuned cognitive level, Barclay (2013) suggested that subtle cues of being watched operate on an unconscious rather than on a conscious level. This assumption has implications for measuring the actual psychological state that is produced by subtle cues of being watched. To clarify this issue, one could ask participants explicit questions about their current state, for instance via items from the situational public self-awareness scale (Govern & Marsch, 2001; a sample item reads “Right now, I am concerned about the way I present myself”). However, if subtle cues of being watched operate on an unconscious level, participants may not be able to give an explicit account of their current inner state (Nisbett & Wilson, 1977). These considerations highlight that one needs to assess current psychological states using indirect methods. For instance, one could let individuals present themselves in a more positive, reputation-increasing way which should be pronounced when a subtle cue of being watched is presented. Specifically, one could use a social desirability scale (e.g., Crowne & Marlowe, 1960) and experimentally vary the presence of a subtle cue of being watched. If subtle cues of being watched lead to increased impression management, one should find increased socially desirable responding when a subtle cue of being watched is presented (vs. not presented). This approach could contribute knowledge to the field of subtle cues of being watched in that it would test not only whether subtle cues of being watched increase prosocial and decrease antisocial behavior, but also that reputational concerns are actually induced by subtle cues of being watched. EMPIRICAL PAPERS 43 These considerations lead to a critical point in our studies in which subtle cues of being watched were applied (this also holds true for the study reported in the following chapter in which we investigated the effect of subtle cues of being watched on costly punishment). Specifically, the validation study does not provide direct evidence that the psychological state of reputational concerns is activated by subtle cues of being watched. We were able to show that subtle cues of being watched lead to an increased sense of being seen. It is reasonable to assume that reputational concerns are activated in turn, because individuals often present themselves in a valuable way and are motivated to gain a valuable reputation when others are present (Griskevicius et al., 2010; van Vugt et al., 2007; see also costly signaling theory in Chapter 3.3.3). However, I want to acknowledge that the validation study provides no direct evidence for the assumption that subtle cues of being watched render reputational concerns salient whereas it provides good evidence that subtle cues of being watched lead to an increased sense of being seen, on which basis one can reasonably assume that reputational concerns are activated. 3.2.2 Methodological remarks It is important to mention that in research on watching eyes the question of how to adequately operationalize the control group arises. Some researchers have argued for using non-social symbols such as pictures of flowers as a control condition (e.g., Bateson, Nettle, & Roberts, 2006). This approach, however, has some significant drawbacks. For instance, Raihani and Bshary (2012) show that pictures of flowers increase prosocial behavior as compared with a more neutral condition in which no cues or symbols were presented. Based on these results, I argue that a condition in which no cues or symbols could activate certain concepts is the most valid control condition. This approach was universally applied in the studies presented in this dissertation.22 Another methodological issue is the question of what the stylized eyes should look like. It is reasonable to assume that angry eyes (e.g., used by Haley and Fessler, 2005) lead to 22 To establish transparency, I want to mention that this paragraph includes sentences taken from Pfattheicher and Keller (2014, Appendix B). EMPIRICAL PAPERS 44 a different cognitive state as compared with friendly eyes (e.g., used by Burnham and Hare, 2007). Specifically, one can assume that individuals engage in prosocial behavior when being watched by angry eyes in order to avoid negative sanctions (e.g., social disapproval or punishment) whereas one can assume that individuals engage in prosocial behavior when being watched by friendly eyes in order to gain positive sanctions (e.g., social approval or reward). In all studies presented here we used neutral-looking eye in order to deal with this concern. Moreover, one could ask the question of under which conditions subtle cues of being watched are able to operate. Powell, Roberts, and Nettle (2012) offer a precondition. They showed that a subtle cue of being watched increased donations to a charity organization in a supermarket only if the supermarket was poorly crowded. It makes sense that when social presence is already given subtle cues of being watched cannot, on top of this, increase social presence. Another idea is that social presence (and subtle cues of being watched) lead to prosocial behavior only if accountability for one’s behavior is given (cf. van Bommel, van Prooijen, Elffers, & van Lange, in press). Social presence is indeed given in classic studies on the bystander effect which show that the more people who are present the less people help a suffering other (Fischer et al., 2011; Latané & Nida, 1981). The bystander effect is, inter alia, explained by the diffusion of responsibility and reduced accountability of one’s behavior (Garcia, Weaver, Moskowitz, & Darley, 2002; Weesie, 1993). In contrast to the studies concerning the bystander effect, activated social presence via a subtle cue of being watched is not activated by the presence of several people (and eyes). It seems reasonable to assume (van Bommel et al., in press, put this argument forward) that subtle cues of being watched do not reduce one’s level of accountability. When facing a decision (e.g., in a dictator game) it should be clear that the decider is responsible for the decision. The decision cannot be passed on to other present individuals as there are none. Thus, it seems unlikely that subtle cues of being watched reduce one’s accountability and that they can be used to replicate the bystander effect. EMPIRICAL PAPERS 45 Another interesting finding in terms of methodology comes from Sparks and Barclay (2013) who show that prolonged exposure to a subtle cue of being watched did not increase prosocial behavior in a dictator game. It is unclear, however, why this result emerged (e.g., because the eyes are consciously processed and individuals more explicitly regulate their behavior). Nonetheless, Sparks and Barclay (2013) emphasize that the prolonged presentation of subtle cues of being watched may not result in the effects typically found with these cues (increased prosocial behavior and decreased antisocial behavior). This indicates that a precondition for subtle cues of being watched to work is relatively short exposure. In sum, subtle cues of being watched seem to be a valid approach to investigating social presence and, accordingly, reputational concerns. This conclusion is worth noting because research on watching eyes has assumed but not empirically tested the hypothesis that a sense of being seen is induced by subtle cues of being watched (e.g., Izuma, 2012; Nettle et al., 2013). Therefore, the presented work was indeed necessary in that it has addressed a remarkable gap in this field of research. In the next paper presented, a subtle cue of being watched is applied to test whether individuals are more or less likely to engage in costly punishment when reputational concerns are activated. 3.3 Punishing for the sake of reputation? Effects of reputational concerns on costly punishment (Pfattheicher, Landhäußer, & Keller, 2014, Appendix C) As mentioned above, some scholars have suggested that individuals strategically costly punish in order to gain a valuable reputation and to benefit from that good reputation thereafter (e.g., Barclay, 2006; Dos Santos et al., 2011; Fehr & Gächter, 2002; Gächter & Herrmann, 2009; Hagen & Hammerstein, 2006; Hilbe & Traulsen, 2012; Kurzban et al. 2007; Nelissen, 2008; Piazza & Bering, 2008; Shaw & Santons, 2012; Sylwester et al., 2013; Tennie, 2012). As outlined in the introduction (see Chapter 2.2.3), this strategic perspective on costly punishment implies that costly punishment is executed to maximize benefits, that is, costly punishment is considered to be part of a benefitmaximizing strategy. If individuals strategically punish to gain a beneficial good reputation which serves them in future interactions (Milinski, Semmann, & Krambeck, EMPIRICAL PAPERS 46 2002; Nowak & Sigmund, 1998; Roberts, 1998; van Vugt et al., 2007; Wedekind & Braithwaite, 2002) they should be more likely to engage in costly punishment when reputational concerns are activated. In the empirical studies outlined in detail below we experimentally tested this strategic perspective. In the manuscript we made use of costly signaling theory (Grafen, 1990; Zahavi, 1975) to provide a theoretical basis for the empirical studies. The theoretical framework of costly signaling theory suggests that specific types of costly behavior are likely to emerge in conditions where the actor can gain a valuable reputation through engagement in these behaviors (Griskevicius et al., 2010; van Vugt et al., 2007). Accordingly, these types of costly behavior should be more likely to emerge when reputational concerns are activated (vs. not activated). Thus, costly signaling theory constitutes a meaningful general theoretical framework regarding the relation of reputational concerns and costly punishment (costly signaling theory is discussed in Chapter 3.3.3).23 Remarkably, to the best of my knowledge, there is only one serious empirical work (Kurzban et al., 2007) that has tested the notion of whether individuals costly punish for reputational concerns.24 However, there are several articles that consider the relation 23 To establish transparency, I want to mention that this paragraph includes sentences taken from Pfattheicher et al. (2014, Appendix C). 24 Kurzban et al. (2007) reported on audience effects on costly punishment in a third party punishment scenario and found increased costly punishment under conditions where an experimenter and other participants were present (vs. an explicit statement towards anonymity in the control condition). However, the studies have several shortcomings such as the possibility of demand characteristics (Orne, 1962), Pygmalion effects (Rosenthal & Jacobson, 1968), the lack of a neutral control condition (explicitly inducing anonymity in the “control” condition), and confounding costly punishment and the money participants kept, that is, participants behaved more egoistically in the anonymous condition (punishing less, keeping more) which is in line with several empirical studies (Hoffman, McCabe, & Smith, 1996; Milinski, Semmann, Krambeck, & Marotzke, 2006; Rege & Telle, 2004). The work of Kurzban et al. (2007) in comparison with our approach is further discussed in the general discussion of Pfattheicher et al. (2014, Appendix C). To complete the list, Piazza & Bering (2008) also manipulated the degree of anonymity in three conditions but did not find any significant differences (even with collapsed groups all ps were > .24). Notably, this study lacks statistical power to detect even medium effects (three conditions, total N = 42, power was below 68% to detect an existing effect (p < .05) with medium effect size, f = .25). EMPIRICAL PAPERS 47 between reputation and costly punishment theoretically (e.g., Fehr & Gächter, 2002; Gächter & Herrmann, 2009; Hilbe & Traulsen, 2012; Shaw & Santons, 2012; Sylwester et al., 2013; Tennie, 2012), test how costly punishment is perceived, that is, whether costly punishers are ascribed a good reputation (Barclay, 2006; Nelissen, 2008), and make assumptions regarding the relation for computer simulations (Dos Santos et al., 2011; Hilbe & Traulsen, 2012). The absence of valid empirical work is even more noteworthy given that costly punishment and reputation both represent two essential concepts in evolutionary psychology and biology. Therefore, investigating the relation of reputation and costly punishment addresses a remarkable gap in this field of study. 3.3.2 The empirical studies In the empirical paper in which we tested whether reputational concerns increase or decrease costly punishment, we first introduced and validated a public self-awareness manipulation to render reputational concerns salient. Specifically, we asked participants in a validation study to describe the self that they should possess in the eyes of others (cf. the method section in Pfattheicher et al., 2014, Appendix C). Reputation refers to the judgments of relevant others about one’s personal qualities and how one behaves (Emler, 1990). Reputational concerns, therefore, refer to concerns regarding how others think about one’s personal qualities. Accordingly, reputational concerns correspond to the psychological concept of public self-awareness (Gervais & Norenzayan, 2012; Mifune et al., 2010) which reflects a state in which one’s attention is directed to how one appears in the eyes of others (Fenigstein et al., 1975; Fenigstein & Vanable, 1992). Therefore, we manipulated reputational concerns and tested whether the manipulation was valid in that it affected responses on the situational public self-awareness scale by Govern and Marsch (2001). Using structural equation modeling, we were able to show increased public self-awareness when participants described the self that they should possess in the eyes of others as compared with a neutral control condition. Importantly, the manipulation significantly affected situational public self-awareness but not private selfawareness and awareness of surroundings. The findings of the validation study speak to EMPIRICAL PAPERS 48 the applicability of the manipulation which was then implemented in two consecutive studies.25 In these studies, we applied a public goods game under conditions of anonymity so as to minimalize default reputational concerns. We also precluded mutual interactions (i.e., we used one-shot games) between participants to minimize default strategic concerns when engaging in costly punishment. As outlined in detail in Chapter 1.4, if strategic considerations had not been minimized (i.e., if it was possible that costly punishment was strategically executed) the likelihood that we would have been able to have observed an effect in terms of reputation on top of already strategically executed costly punishment would have been fairly low. To put it another way, we could not have investigated the central research question of whether costly punishment is executed to strategically gain a valuable reputation. We manipulated reputational concerns as outlined above. In two studies using a hypothetical public goods game and a public goods game involving real interactions (via z-Tree; Fischbacher, 2007) and real monetary rewards, we were able to document that costly punishment is reduced when reputational concerns were rendered salient. No effects were found regarding the contribution to the public good (cf. the discussion below regarding this finding). In an additional study we replicated these results by showing that costly punishment is also reduced when reputational concerns are rendered salient by means of a subtle cue of being watched (as discussed in the last chapter and in Pfattheicher and Keller, 2014, Appendix B). In sum, in the three studies using different manipulations of reputational concerns we showed that costly punishment is actually reduced under conditions of reputational concerns. The question remains of why exactly individuals reduce costly punishment under reputational concerns conditions. In the empirical paper, we built on findings that 25 To establish transparency, I want to mention that this paragraph includes sentences taken from Pfattheicher et al. (2014, Appendix C). EMPIRICAL PAPERS 49 antisocial behavior is typically reduced under social presence and when individuals are motivated to gain a valuable reputation, that is, when reputational concerns are activated (Andreoni & Bernheim, 2009; Ernest-Jones, Nettle, & Bateson, 2010; Haley & Fessler, 2005; Mifune et al., 2010; Milinski et al., 2002; Milinski et al., 2006; Oda et al., 2011). We argued that costly punishment reflects negative reciprocity (cf. Bowles & Gintis, 2003; Brandstätter & Königstein, 2001; Reuben & van Winden, 2008) and revenge (de Quervain et al., 2004; Gollwitzer & Bushman, 2012; McCullough, 2008) and, building on the considerations outlined above (cf. Pfattheicher & Keller, in press, Appendix A), one can add reactive aggression (Crockett et al., 2010; Osumi et al., 2012; Stirrat & Perrett, 2010). I argue that negative reciprocity, revenge, and reactive aggression reflect antisocial tendencies which are, as reviewed above, less likely to be shown when reputational concerns are activated. This implies that potential punishers hold beliefs about how costly punishment is socially construed by others and they shape their behavior accordingly when others are relevant (i.e., when reputational concerns are activated). The findings of the three studies presented do suggest that costly punishment is considered to be a reputation reducing, socially undesirable tendency by the potential punisher. A fourth study was conducted to examine this notion directly. We tested whether individuals consider engagement in negative reciprocity and revenge socially undesirable. If costly punishment and the corresponding tendencies of negative reciprocity and revenge are considered to be reputation reducing, socially undesirable tendencies, we should have found modest support for negative reciprocity and revenge with significantly lower approval for negative reciprocity and revenge when reputational concerns were activated. This was revealed to be the case (cf. Study 4 in Pfattheicher et al., 2014, Appendix C).26 26 To establish transparency, I want to mention that this paragraph includes sentences taken from Pfattheicher et al. (2014, Appendix C). EMPIRICAL PAPERS 50 3.3.1 Discussion The findings obtained strongly speak against the strategic perspective of costly punishment. Costly punishment does not seem to be strategically executed to gain reputational benefits. The findings are important because they contradict the assumptions made by several scholars (Barclay, 2006; Dos Santos et al., 2011; Fehr & Gächter, 2002; Gächter & Herrmann, 2009; Hagen & Hammerstein, 2006; Hilbe & Traulsen, 2012; Kurzban et al. 2007; Nelissen, 2008; Piazza & Bering, 2008; Shaw & Santons, 2012; Sylwester et al., 2013; Tennie, 2012) and should, therefore, be taken into account in future (especially evolutionary-focused) theorizing involving the interplay of costly punishment and reputation. Our findings are in line with research done by Rockenbach and Milinski (2011) who told their participants that their decision to punish could be observed by other subjects, and then gave their participants the possibility of hiding the amount they invested in costly punishment. They found that the probability of individuals hiding their punishment increased the more money was spent on costly punishment. Rockenbach and Milinski (2011) interpreted this result as evidence that individuals fear losing their reputations when engaging in costly punishment. That is, Rockenbach and Milinski (2011) argued that individuals’ reputational concerns are activated when they are observed and engage in costly punishment. As such, their argument is in line with ours. However, Rockenbach and Milinski (2011) did not manipulate the psychological state of reputational concern. That is, their conclusions rely on correlational evidence, and their explanations were made ex post. As such, our findings are in line with the findings of Rockenbach and Milinski (2011) but extend them in a meaningful way in that we directly show that the manipulation of reputational concerns decreased costly punishment. I do not claim that costly punishment cannot have benefits for punishing individuals. For instance, in line with the conceptualization of costly punishment as reactive aggression, costly punishment can benefit an individual in that costly punishment serves as an instrumental means of achieving the goal of harming an uncooperative interaction partner. Reaching a goal can indeed satisfy a need (e.g., Higgins, 2012a), that is, benefit EMPIRICAL PAPERS 51 an individual. However, I do criticize the assumption that costly punishment is strategically executed to gain reputational benefits, thereby questioning the considerations of the aforementioned scholars (Barclay, 2006; Dos Santos et al., 2011; Fehr & Gächter, 2002; Gächter & Herrmann, 2009; Hagen & Hammerstein, 2006; Hilbe & Traulsen, 2012; Kurzban et al. 2007; Nelissen, 2008; Piazza & Bering, 2008; Shaw & Santons, 2012; Sylwester et al., 2013; Tennie, 2012) and how they specifically conceptualize the strategic nature of costly punishment. In all studies, no significant effects were found regarding the contribution to the public good. At first glance, this finding seems to be a non-replication of several studies that have shown that activating reputational concerns leads to an increased contribution to the public good (e.g., Burnham & Hare, 2007; Milinski et al., 2002; Rege & Telle, 2004). However, all studies exclusively investigated the effects of reputational concerns on the contribution to the public good in the absence of costly punishment. This is worth noting because the presence of the option to costly punish others substantially changes the nature and amount of contributions to the public good in that individuals contribute significantly more to the public good if an option to costly punish is present (Fehr & Gächter, 2002). That is to say, when an option to costly punish is available, the contribution to the public good is far from being purely prosocial behavior and is often executed strategically to avoid punishment (Berg et al., 1995). I do not deny that some contributions to the public good are prosocial when costly punishment is possible. However, when an option to costly punish is present, strategic contributions executed to avoid being punished increase substantially so that one cannot distinguish between “real” prosocial contributions and “strategic” non-prosocial contributions. In such a situation, individuals cannot reliably signal prosocial motives. From the perspective of costly signaling theory it is important that the behavior that may function as a signal must reliably signal the underlying characteristics or motives of an individual (Bliege Bird, Smith, & Bird, 2001; Griskevicius et al., 2010; Smith & Bliege Bird, 2000).27 This is not 27 Nonetheless, one could argue that costly punishment of uncooperative individuals signals prosocial tendencies because costly punishment is positively correlated with contributions to the public good (e.g., Pfattheicher & Keller, 2013, Appendix D). However, costly punishment of uncooperative individuals is EMPIRICAL PAPERS 52 sufficiently the case when strategic non-prosocial contributions cannot be differentiated from real prosocial contributions. Therefore, the contributions to the public good when an option to punish is available should not increase when reputational concerns are activated, which is in line with our results.28 Another argument points in this direction. If reputational concerns should increase contributions to the public good, neglecting the argument above for a moment, this effect must be present on top of the high level of cooperation that already exists when the option of costly punishment is present (Fehr & Gächter, 2002). That is, if contributions are already high, the likelihood that an additional factor further increases the contributions decreases (i.e., a ceiling effect; see, e.g., Rigdon, Ishii, Watabe, & Kitayama, 2009, for a similar argument). That is to say, only a strong effect could run against a ceiling effect. Essentially, these two arguments speak to the notion that it was unlikely that we would have observed increased contributions to the public good when reputational concerns were activated. 3.3.2 Further remarks I have argued that it is unlikely that the ultimate motives in costly punishing are prosocial. Rather, I have argued that antisocial tendencies drive costly punishment. I want to note that I do not argue that costly punishment and the corresponding concepts of negative reciprocity, revenge, and reactive aggression do not have prosocial consequences. There is a lot of research that shows that negative reciprocity, revenge, and reactive aggression can lead to valued outcomes such as cooperation in groups, status, and a state of peace through deterrence (e.g., Banny, Heilbron, Ames, & Prinstein, 2011; Fehr & Gächter, 2002; Griskevicius et al., 2009; Hawley & Vaughn, 2003). Using the terms of Batson and colleagues (Batson et al., 2008; Batson et al., 2002), I take the perspective that the prosocial effects of costly punishment reflect unintended consequences whereas the ultimate goal (the actual motive) reflects revenge and also positively correlated with antisocial punishment (e.g., Pfattheicher et al., in press, Appendix E). Thus, based on this logic, one could equally argue that costly punishment may signal antisocial tendencies. 28 To establish transparency, I want to mention that this paragraph includes sentences taken from Pfattheicher et al. (2014, Appendix C). EMPIRICAL PAPERS 53 antisocial tendencies (representing tendencies that are likely to reduce the actor’s social reputation). Moreover, I do not argue that individuals generally disapprove of the punishment of norm deviants. The legal punishment of criminals, for instance, is well in line with individuals’ beliefs and values (Carlsmith & Darley, 2008; Carlsmith, Darley, Robinson, 2002). In this case, the punishment is executed by legitimized institutions. However, the work presented is about individuals’ costly punishment in public good games, executed by one’s own hand. Costly punishment executed by one’s own hand is fundamentally different from the punishment of criminals by legitimized institutions. Indeed, research in the field of justice has shown that individuals typically consider self-administered justice, that is, the punishment of a potential criminal executed by one’s own hand, socially undesirable (Raney, 2009). Of course, there are substantial differences between the punishment of a potential criminal and costly punishment of an uncooperative individual in a public goods game. These considerations emphasize that it is important to take into account who is punishing and whether a punishing entity is legitimized (this issue is considered again below). 3.3.3 Discussing costly signaling theory As outlined above, the theoretical framework of costly signaling theory suggests that specific types of costly behavior are likely to emerge in conditions where the actor can gain a valuable reputation through engagement in these behaviors (Griskevicius et al., 2010; van Lange et al, 2013; van Vugt et al., 2007). Costly signaling theory was originally developed in order to explain characteristics that seem to be costly rather than beneficial at first sight. The classic example is the peacock’s tail (Petrie, Halliday, & Sanders, 1991; Zahavi & Zahavi, 1997). The peacock’s tail is a remarkable handicap in terms of fitness at first sight as it is more costly (to grow and when escaping predators; Zahavi, 1975) than beneficial. However, the notion emerges that the peacock’s tail signals underlying phenotypic qualities. Specifically, a peacock with an impressive tail survives although it is such a fitness handicap. On this basis, one can infer that the peacock must have good phenotypic qualities that can compensate for the costs. EMPIRICAL PAPERS 54 Crucially, peacocks possessing the most costly and impressive tails gain benefits in the future because they are more likely to be chosen as a mating partner (i.e., reproductive success, see Petrie et al., 1991). Thus, costly signaling theory explains why apparently unreasonable, costly characteristics and behavior persist: costly signal provides benefits in the future.29 It is worth noting that costly signaling theory is not an exclusive evolutionary approach in terms of sexual selection and fitness benefits (e.g., Bliege Bird et al., 2001; Hamilton & Zuk, 1982). Spence (1973), for instance, applied the logic of costly signaling to the job market. Basically, high compared with low quality applicants for a job have fewer difficulties to gain good education credentials due to their higher abilities. The idea in the approach of Spence (1973) is that job applicants signal their underlying working qualities through good education credentials because especially high quality applicants will gain good education credentials. Thus, high quality applicants can be distinguished from low quality applicants on the basis of education credentials which, as a consequence, represent a signal of high working qualities. Given that costly signaling theory is not an exclusive evolutionary approach and costly signaling takes place in domains other than sexual selection, our work did not aim to contribute to the literature on evolutionary psychology. Rather, we used costly signaling theory to build a theoretical basis for the assumption that socially desirable, prosocial behavior is likely to emerge under conditions of reputational concerns (Griskevicius et al., 2010; van Vugt et al., 2007). In critically discussing costly signaling theory, one has to acknowledge that postulations that a specific characteristic may function as a costly signal are often made ex post. This is, for instance, the case for the peacock’s tail (Petrie et al., 1991; Zahavi & Zahavi, 1997) where the emergence of the tail is explained ex post by the fitness benefit it provides. Costly signaling theory cannot explain why other birds and animals in general do not possess such an impressive tail. That is, costly signaling theory cannot explain 29 To establish transparency, I want to mention that this paragraph includes sentences taken from Pfattheicher et al. (2014, Appendix C). EMPIRICAL PAPERS 55 why specific behavior exists but only why a specific characteristic persists (because of benefits). These considerations also correspond to the fundamental axiom that all explanations are causal explanations, and that behavior cannot be explained by its’ (beneficiary) consequences (Elster, 2007). Of course, beneficial consequences strengthen the appearance of a behavior or characteristic in future (i.e., classic positive reinforcement). However, beneficial consequences cannot explain the appearance of a behavior or characteristic in the first place, because at this point no beneficial consequences had occurred. Explaining behavior by its consequences is, however, often done in evolutionary psychology (Elster, 2007; West, El Mouden, & Gardner, 2011). The work presented made use of costly signaling theory because this theory proposes that prosocial behavior, which typically results in a good reputation as outlined above, is more likely to be shown when reputational concerns are activated. In contrast, costly signaling theory proposes that antisocial behavior, which typically results in a bad reputation, is less likely to be shown when reputational concerns are activated. Building on these considerations, it makes sense that costly punishment, which I linked to the antisocial tendencies of negative reciprocity, revenge, and reactive aggression, is reduced when reputational concerns are activated. The purpose of applying costly signaling theory was not to explain the existence or persistence of costly punishment per se. Rather, costly signaling theory was used to theoretically integrate the concepts of reputational concerns and costly punishment. On the basis of costly signaling theory, Barclay (2006) and Nelissen (2008) argue that costly punishment can function as a costly signal, signaling prosocial tendencies. Indeed, Nelissen (2008) showed that strong costly punishers gained reputational benefits from punishment: they were perceived as fair, friendly, and generous by third parties. Additionally, they received more trust in a standard trust game as compared with nonpunishers (Berg et al., 1995). Congruently, Barclay (2006) reported that costly punishers (vs. non-punishers) are perceived to be more trustworthy, group focused, and worthy of respect. He also showed that costly punishers benefited in a subsequent trust game. This research actually shows that costly punishment can have reputational benefits (cf. EMPIRICAL PAPERS 56 Barclay, 2013). However, receiving (reputational) benefits is only one side of the coin. Sundie et al. (2011; see also Bliege Bird et al., 2001; Griskevicius et al., 2007) emphasized that behavior that is said to be a costly signal needs also be signaled by an actor under conditions where the signal can work, that is, under social presence. If costly punishment is considered a reputation-increasing tendency by individuals, costly punishment should increase when reputational concerns are activated. However, as outlined above, we have shown reduced costly punishment under reputational concerns conditions. 3.3.4 Explaining actor-observer discrepancies Obviously, there is a discrepancy between the actors’ construal of the engagement in costly punishment as compared with the construal by observers. The folk conceptual theory of Malle and colleagues (Knobe & Malle, 2002; Malle & Knobe, 1997, 2001; Malle, Knobe, & Nelson, 2007) provides a theoretical framework to explain this issue. It is described in detail below in order to establish a theoretical grounding for explaining actor-observer discrepancies regarding costly punishment. Folk conceptual theory was originally developed to explain actor-observer discrepancies, as shown in experiments on the fundamental attribution error (Jones & Harris, 1967; Ross, Amabile, & Steinmetz, 1977). The fundamental attribution error reflects the idea that observers tend to explain behavior with an emphasis on personal factors whereas actors tend to explain behavior with an emphasis on situational factors. 30 Malle and colleagues (Malle et al., 2007, see also Knobe & Malle, 2002) were able to show that the distinction between personal and situational attributions regarding actors and observers is not crucial. Instead, they postulate (and empirically show) three other dimensions in which actors and observers differ which were finally implemented in folk conceptual theory. First, actors tend to explain behavior by reasons, because actors have direct access (although subjectively and potentially biased) to the reasons and motives of their behavior. Also, actors tend to see themselves as a meaningful, reasonably acting actor 30 Later, it was shown in a meta-analysis (Malle, 2006) that this attribution holds, if ever, only for negative events that happen to an actor. EMPIRICAL PAPERS 57 and are motivated to present themselves in such a way. Observers, on the other hand, tend to explain behavior by describing the actor as relatively less rational, as acting less consciously, and, speaking in the terms used by Malle and colleagues, observers use rather a causal history of reasons to explain behavior. Second, actors tend to explain behavior through beliefs whereas observers tend to explain behavior through desires. Third, actors are less likely to use marked belief reasons (e.g., “I work so much because I think it is good to earn some money”; using “I think” is relatively uncommon, cf. Malle et al., 2007) whereas observers do indeed use marked belief reasons (e.g., “Dan works so much because he wants to earn some money”; using “he wants” is relatively usual).31 The first aspect of folk conceptual theory in particular is relevant in the context of actorobserver discrepancies regarding costly punishment. That is, Malle and colleagues explain actor-observer differences by arguing that actors in particular take their motives, reasons, and the decision process into account when evaluating their behavior, given that they have cognitive access to their motives, their reasons, and the decision process underlying their actions. Therefore, it seems reasonable to assume that potential punishers do indeed take their anger (Fehr & Gächter, 2002; Pillutla & Murnighan, 1996; cf. Chapter 2.2.1) and revenge motives (de Quervain et al., 2004; Gollwitzer & Bushman, 2012; McCullough, 2008) into account when judging how they should behave appropriately (i.e., when reputational concerns are activated). Folk conceptual theory emphasizes that observers do not have direct access to the decision process of an actor and therefore have to rely on other inferences to which they have access. These are causal history of reason explanations such as traits or cultural norms (Malle, 1999; Malle 31 This third dimension, emphasizing linguistic differences between actors’ and observers’ explanations, actually explains why the fundamental attribution error is apparently empirically found (e.g., in Jones & Harris, 1967). Raters of observer statements such as “He took the umbrella because he thinks it is raining” are more likely categorized as a “person attribution” (due to the use of “he thinks”) whereas raters of actor statements categorize the same statement with only the source varying (now the actor) more likely to the situation (“I took the umbrella because it is raining”). The actual explanation (“it is raining”) is given in both the actors’ and observers’ explanations. So, actually, actors and observers do not differ in their explanation in this example, but their explanations were categorized either as “person attribution” or “situation attribution”. EMPIRICAL PAPERS 58 et al., 2007). Thus, it seems reasonable to assume that observers explain costly punishment with reference to a fairness norm and ascribe fairness motives and prosocial traits to costly punishers, which is in line with the findings of Barclay (2006) and Nelissen (2008). Another reasonable explanation for the actor-observer difference regarding costly punishment can be found in the notion of emotion appropriateness (d’Arms & Jacobson, 2000; Aune, 1997; Aune, Aune, & Buller, 1994). This notion implies that an expressed emotion should be appropriate in interpersonal situations, that is, when others are present. Building on this notion, one can assume that individuals who experienced anger as a reaction to a fairness norm violation do not consider their anger to be appropriate or its expression socially desirable, which may be especially relevant in situations in which they are concerned about their reputation and present others. Thus, from this perspective, one can argue that costly punishment (i.e., the expression of anger) is not considered to be an appropriate response, which may be particularly relevant when reputational concerns are activated. As a result, individuals are less likely to engage in costly punishment when reputational concerns are rendered salient. In contrast, perceivers of costly punishment do not directly observe (at least in the experiments of Barclay, 2006, and Nelissen, 2008) the anger of the costly punishers. Thus, they may not be able to consider anger when making a judgment about an individual who engaged in costly punishment. Reconsidering folk conceptual theory (Knobe & Malle, 2002; Malle & Knobe, 1997, 2001; Malle et al., 2007), observers must rely on other inferences. In sum, folk conceptual theory and the notion of emotion appropriateness suggest that it is important to differentiate between the actor’s and the observer’s perspective and to explain actor-observer discrepancies in costly punishment. Another line of research may be able to explain why the pattern of reduced costly punishment under conditions of reputational concerns emerges. Specifically, social psychological research on deindividuation suggests that individuals in a state of decreased self-evaluation and increased anonymity (i.e., deindividuation; Festinger, Pepitone, & Newcomb, 1952) are more likely to engage in disinhibited, aggressive, and EMPIRICAL PAPERS 59 antisocial behavior (Diener, Fraser, Beaman, & Kelem, 1976; Diener, Lusk, DeFour, & Flax, 1980). In his theory of deindividuation, Zimbardo (1969) explained these effects, inter alia, by a reduced concern for one’s evaluation by others. He wrote: “If others can’t identify or single you out, they can’t evaluate, criticize, judge, or punish you” (p. 255). Empirically, Rogers and Ketchen (1979) have shown that when individuals were aroused they were more likely to engage in aggressive behavior (using the Buss, 1961, aggression machine to give electroshocks for false answers in a learning experiment), but only if they were de-individuated (participants wore white lab coats and hoods vs. casual clothes). These considerations fit our reasoning on costly punishment and reputational concerns. Specifically, it may be possible that in the control, as compared with the reputational concerns condition, individuals experience an increased sense of anonymity and behave in a less inhibited way whereas in the reputational concerns condition individuals are more inhibited (for a similar argument, see Bushman and Huesmann, 2010). As a result, individuals in the control condition are more likely to follow their emotions and engage in costly punishment whereas participants in the reputational concerns condition are more likely to show inhibitory tendencies and are less likely to engage in costly punishment (which is in line with our work on behavioral inhibition, as presented in the following paper, see Chapter 3.4 below and Pfattheicher and Keller, 2013, Appendix D). One must note that the explanations offered by deindividuation, emotion appropriateness as well as the application of folk conceptual theory are made ex post. A direct, ex ante, empirical test is therefore needed. For instance, one could directly investigate the explanation of costly punishment by actors versus observers of costly punishment and apply the dimensions proposed by Malle et al. (2007). Using this strategy, one could shed light on the distinct evaluations of costly punishment by actors and observers. In sum, it seems a valuable approach for future research to examine actor-observer discrepancies in costly punishment. It still remains an open question as to why exactly reputational concerns reduced costly punishment. As outlined above, it could be the case that individuals consider their EMPIRICAL PAPERS 60 emotional state, that is, the expression of anger, as inappropriate and not socially desirable. It is also possible that costly punishment itself is not considered appropriate or socially desirable or that individuals do not feel legitimized to engage in costly punishment, particularly when they are observed. Moreover, research on deindividuation suggests that when individuals act without the activation of what others think (i.e., without the activation of reputational concerns), they are more likely to do what they want (i.e., follow their emotions and punish uncooperative others). Another question is which specific others one needs to be concerned about regarding one’s reputation. That is to say, the specific audience seems of importance when it comes to costly punishment. Froming, Walker, and Lopyan (1982), for instance, showed that participants are less likely to attack another individual (using the Buss aggression machine) when the electroshocks had to be executed in the presence of an audience (vs. no audience) that was against the use of electroshocks. The reverse was found when the audience was in favor of electroshocks, that is, the electroshocks were more frequently used when the electroshocks were socially desirable (vs. no audience). Congruently, one could imagine that when an audience is in favor of costly punishment, it will be more likely to emerge (vs. no audience). In the studies presented we did not include this boundary condition as this was beyond the scope of the research. Our research question was more basic, that is, whether “general” reputational concerns increase or decrease costly punishment. In this way we could target the general claim by several scholars that costly punishment is strategically executed to gain reputational benefits. As outlined above, we were able to refute this claim. I do not deny that costly punishment can have some reputational benefits. Rather, I suggest that the hypothesis that costly punishment is generally used to gain reputational benefits needs to be reformulated. In line with Griskevicius et al. (2009), it could be that costly punishment is sometimes used to impress others which corresponds to the idea of “aggress to impress.” Investigating the boundary condition of the relation between costly punishment and reputational concerns appears to be an interesting approach for future research. EMPIRICAL PAPERS 61 In sum, there are obviously some questions that could not be answered in the studies presented, but could (and should) be targeted in future research. Nonetheless, the work presented represents a new and promising approach to the study of costly punishment and reputational concerns. Our findings demonstrate that the activation of reputational concerns reduced costly punishment. The findings are important because they contradict the suggestions of several scholars (e.g., Barclay, 2006; Fehr & Gächter, 2002; Gächter & Herrmann, 2009; Hagen & Hammerstein, 2006; Kurzban et al. 2007; Nelissen, 2008) in that the findings strongly speak against the strategic perspective: costly punishment does not seem to be strategically executed to gain reputational benefits. The work presented should therefore be taken into account in future (especially evolutionaryfocused) theorizing involving the interplay of costly punishment and reputation. 3.4 Vigilant self-regulation and costly punishment in public goods situations (Pfattheicher & Keller, 2013, Appendix D) The last paper presented here (see Chapter 3.3 above) documents that costly punishment is reduced under reputational concerns conditions. In the following work (Pfattheicher & Keller, 2013, Appendix D) it is shown that chronically prevention-focused individuals, that is, individuals who possess a strong ought-self (which one could argue corresponds to the notion of reputational concerns, see below), are more likely to engage in costly punishment as compared with relatively weakly prevention-focused individuals. Before discussing these counter-intuitive findings, I will integrate and discuss regulatory focus theory with respect to other motivational theories (beyond what is already said in Pfattheicher & Keller, 2013, Appendix D). That is, the following section will outline in detail the distinctiveness and specificity of regulatory focus theory in comparison with other motivational theories. From this basis, then, the prediction that the vigilant orientation of regulatory focus theory (i.e., the prevention focus) is positively related to costly punishment, but not vigilant orientations as conceptualized in other motivational theories, will become clearer. This is why several motivational theories are outlined in the following section. EMPIRICAL PAPERS 62 3.4.1 Theories of motivation and regulatory focus theory Self-regulation is the operation by individuals to (consciously or unconsciously) modify and adjust their own habits or actual state to bring these into alignment with a positive standard (Vohs & Baumeister, 2004; Vohs & Schmeichel, 2003). Self-regulation refers to the general hedonic principle that individuals are motivated to approach pleasure and to avoid pain and that individuals regulate their current state according to this principle. This notion is implemented in several motivational theories, going back to Kurt Lewin (1943). Lewin (among others, e.g., Fishbein & Ajzen, 1975; Rotter, 1954) can be considered to be a theorist postulating that individuals do not generally strive for positive end-states but depending on Value × Expectancy considerations. That is to say, individuals are more likely to be motivated to achieve a specific goal (i.e., regulate toward a desired end-state) the higher they value it and if there is a sufficient expectation that the goal will be reached. If expectancies are low, however, individuals’ motivational energy and drive (to use the terms of early motivational theorists such as Hull, 1943, 1952) are reduced even if the goal is considered highly valuable. This theoretical approach was further developed by Atkinson and colleagues (Atkinson, 1957, 1964; McClelland, Atkinson, Clark, & Lowell, 1953) who added specific motivational orientations to the Value × Expectancy approach, resulting in the model of Value × Expectancy × Motive. Atkinson (1957) focused on the field of task performance and postulated two different motivational orientations that are relevant in goal striving. The first one is the basal motivation of achieving and approaching success (termed “hope for success”). The relevant standards of this motivational orientation are “achievement, affiliation, power” (Atkinson, 1957, p. 360). The second orientation is the basal motivation of avoiding failure (termed “fear of failure”). The relevant standard of this motivational orientation is to minimize pain. According to Atkinson’s model, approach motivation and corresponding actions of approaching a target or standard are elicited if hope for success is situationally stronger than fear of failure, and pride is experienced when a goal is successfully approached. Conversely, avoidance motivation and corresponding actions of avoiding a target or standard are elicited if fear of failure is EMPIRICAL PAPERS 63 situationally stronger than hope for success, and shame and humiliation are experienced when a goal is not reached. The core of Atkinson’s theory of motivation is that individuals generally approach pleasure (i.e., hope for success) or avoid pain (i.e., fear of failure), a notion also found in other motivational theories postulating two systems of self-regulation. In Carver and Scheier’s self-discrepancy theory (Carver, 2006; Carver, Lawrence, & Scheier, 1999; Carver & Scheier, 1981, 1990, 2011) motivation is understood as movement toward pleasure and away from pain. The movement aspect was also emphasized above when defining the term self-regulation. If one’s current state is compared to a positively valued reference point, discrepancy reducing approach motivation is elicited; if one’s current state is compared to a negatively valued end-state, discrepancy increasing avoidance motivation is elicited. Gray’s widely applied reinforcement sensitivity theory (RST; Gray, 1970, 1982) of personality also deserves a mention. Gray’s approach focuses on two orthogonal personality dimensions (cf. Corr, 2009): the first dimension is the behavioral inhibition system (BIS), which is sensitive to conditioned signals of punishment, non-reward (frustration), and (less strongly) novelty. A strong BIS should be reflected in a greater proneness to anxiety, fear, frustration, and the use of vigilant strategies in goal striving. The motivational aspect of the BIS, that is, how this system regulates movements toward goals, is that the BIS inhibits movements toward negative outcomes in order to avoid punishment and/or non-rewards, that is, an avoidance motivation. The second dimension is the behavioral activation system (BAS), which is sensitive to conditioned appetitive stimuli and is activated by signals of non-punishment and reward. A strong BAS should be reflected in the experience of positive affect. The motivational aspect of the BAS is that it initiates movements toward positive outcomes (e.g., reward and/or nonpunishment), that is, an approach motivation. Moreover, Gray developed a third system, the fight-flight system (FFS), which is sensitive to unconditioned aversive stimuli and mediates the emotions of panic and rage, but was not implemented as a personality factor EMPIRICAL PAPERS 64 (cf. Carver & White, 1994). As in the other motivational two system models, individuals self-regulate to approach pleasure and to avoid pain. In an advancement of classic motivational theories, Elliot and colleagues (Elliot, 1999; Elliott & Dweck, 1988; Elliot & McGregor, 1999, 2001; Moller & Elliot, 2006) went beyond the simple notion that positive end-states are approached and negative end-states are avoided. Elliot and colleagues emphasized that it is necessary to differentiate between specific standards that can either be approached or avoided. Specifically, it is proposed that individuals can possess mastery approach goals, which relates to the development of competence through task mastery; individuals can also possess performance approach goals, which relates to the demonstration of competence relative to other individuals (Elliot & McGregor, 2001). Congruently, it is proposed that individuals can have mastery avoidance goals, which relates to preventing failures in terms of task mastery; individuals can also possess performance avoidance goals, which relates to not performing worse than other individuals (Elliot & McGregor, 2001). So, the specific standard of what is approached or avoided is fundamental to this theory. The standard of mastery is related to absolute, intrapersonal standards of what is ideally being approached or ideally being avoided. Performances goals are related to normative standards of what ought to be approached or ought to be avoided in comparison to others.32 The theories outlined above share the idea that the vigilant avoidance system regulates movements away from negative outcomes (i.e., “pain” in a general sense). That is, individuals in a vigilant avoidance mode use avoidance and inhibitory tendencies and behaviors to reach the goal of avoiding negative outcomes. In contrast to all of the 32 Other theoretical models make similar assumptions and postulate two systems of motivation, emphasizing different standards and regulatory strategies (e.g., locomotion and assessment concerns when moving to and evaluating behavioral options, see Kruglanski et al., 2002; or individualistic concerns that regulate the self in an independent way in distinction to others, and collectivist concerns that regulate the self in a way dependent on others; Markus & Kitayama, 1991). These models emphasize different standards and regulatory strategies; the core, however, remains the same as in the models of Atkinson, Gray, Carver, and Elliot: approaching pleasure and avoiding pain. EMPIRICAL PAPERS 65 motivational theories outlined, regulatory focus theory (RFT; Higgins, 1997, 1998, 2012; Scholer & Higgins, 2008, 2011) goes beyond the notion that the vigilant avoidance system is exclusively related to avoidance and inhibitory tendencies. RFT proposes that the vigilant avoidance system can also entail approach strategies and the active initiation of behavior. Specifically, RFT emphasizes that it is necessary to differentiate between specific standards as well as specific preferred strategies of how positively evaluated standards are approached and how negatively evaluated standards are avoided. These are fundamental and important departures from all of the other theories mentioned that generally postulate that positive end-states are approached and negative end-states are avoided. RFT proposes two distinct regulatory systems – a prevention-focused orientation and a promotion-focused orientation (Higgins, 1997, 1998, 2012; Scholer & Higgins, 2008, 2011). The input factors (i.e., valued standards or reference points) of the preventionfocused orientation are safety and security needs. Individuals possessing a prevention focus are oriented toward significant others, that is, they are concerned with fulfilling oughts and responsibilities that reflect normative standards. Moreover, preventionfocused individuals are motivated to avoid losses and to approach non-losses. If a goal is reached, prevention-focused individuals experience quiescence/calmness-related emotions whereas if a goal is missed, prevention-focused individuals experience agitation/anxiety-related emotions (Molden, Lee, & Higgins 2008; Higgins, 1997). The input factors of the promotion-focused orientation are growth, advancement, and accomplishment. Individuals possessing a promotion focus are oriented toward ideals, wishes, and aspirations. Promotion-focused individuals are, moreover, motivated to avoid non-gains and to approach gains. If a goal is reached, promotion-focused individuals experience cheerfulness/happiness-related emotions whereas if a goal is missed romotion-focused individuals experience dejection/sadness-related emotions (Molden et al., 2008; Higgins, 1997).33 33 Of note, promotion focus represents a distinct construct and is not the opposite dimension to prevention focus. An intuitive parallel are the “Big Five” personality dimensions in which, for instance, neuroticism is EMPIRICAL PAPERS 66 In a recent advancement of RFT, three independent levels of self-regulation have been proposed: the system, the strategic, and the tactical level (Higgins, 2012b; Scholer & Higgins, 2008, 2011). On the system level, prevention focus and promotion focus are orthogonal to the classic approach-avoidance distinction, because prevention focus includes approaching safety, security, and non-losses but also avoiding insecurity and losses. Congruently, promotion focus includes approaching growth, advancement, and gains but also avoiding the absence of these standards. On the strategic level, prevention and promotion focus differ in the preferred strategies of how the respective standards are approached and avoided. In a prevention-focused mode, individuals approach a specific end-state (e.g., security) in a vigilant and rather defensive manner. That is, prevention-focused individuals typically prefer avoidance strategies and are concerned with the presence or absence of negative outcomes and information (Higgins, 2012b; Scholer & Higgins, 2008, 2011). In a promotion-focused mode, individuals approach specific end-states (e.g., accomplishment) in an eager manner. That is, promotion-focused individuals typically prefer approach strategies and are concerned with the presence or absence of positive outcomes and information (Higgins, 2012b; Scholer & Higgins, 2008, 2011). The tactical level reflects a more concrete level and refers to which behavioral patterns prevention- and promotion-focused individuals typically use in particular situations. As with the system and the strategic level, the tactical level is independent from the other two levels. Thus, it is possible that an individual is motivated to avoid pain on the system level (e.g., generally avoiding nosocomial infections), use a vigilant avoidance strategy (e.g., being careful and vigilant regarding infections across different situations) but use approach tactics to reach the goal (e.g., approaching hand hygiene, participating in workshops on how to prevent nosocomial infections). Typically, avoidance strategies tend to fit avoidance tactics. For instance, Crowe and Higgins (1997) show in a signal clearly distinct from contentiousness (Zillig, Hemenover, & Dienstbier, 2002). When investigating neuroticism, contentiousness is rather neglected (e.g., Scheier, Carver, & Bridges, 1994). Congruently, promotion focus is neglected in this work. EMPIRICAL PAPERS 67 detection task that prevention-focused individuals have a defensive response bias, that is, they vigilantly use an avoidance tactic to insure correct rejections and insure against errors of commission whereas promotion-focused individuals have a risky response bias, that is, they eagerly use an approach tactic to ensure correct hits and insure against errors of omission. If prevention-focused individuals constantly use avoidance tactics one should find that prevention-focused individuals always show a defensive and inhibitory conservative bias, for instance in the domain of risk behavior. However, Scholer, Zou, Fujita, Stroessner, and Higgins (2010) have shown that prevention-focused individuals show a risky bias in a state of a loss, that is, they adopt an approach tactic to prevent a negative event. The previous section emphasized the distinctiveness of RFT in comparison with other motivational theories. Only the vigilant orientation in RFT explicitly entails the notion that approach strategies are used to reach a goal, that is, it is in line with RFT that prevention-focused individuals take action and show disinhibited tendencies (rather than merely executing defensive and inhibitory tendencies). This should be particularly true when it comes to the negative event of a norm violation, given that prevention-focused individuals are concerned with negative events as well as oughts and responsibilities which reflect normative standards. That is to say, it is reasonable to assume that strongly prevention-focused individuals are likely to engage in costly punishment. The paper presented in the following section was devoted to examining the relation of the prevention focus and costly punishment. The distinctiveness of RFT is also one important part of the paper; specifically, prevention focus was theoretically and empirically contrasted to general inhibitory tendencies. The empirical paper is discussed in detail below. 3.4.2 The empirical paper As outlined above, prevention-focused individuals are particularly sensitive to negative outcomes and information; they are, moreover, concerned with oughts and responsibilities, reflecting normative standards. To look again at the literature on costly punishment, I have outlined that costly punishment is a response to a negative event (i.e., EMPIRICAL PAPERS 68 uncooperative behavior resulting in the violation of a fairness norm). Due to the sensitivity to negative outcomes involving normative standards, it seems reasonable to assume that prevention-focused individuals react particularly strongly to such a negative outcome and are prone to punish those identified as the cause for the negative outcome. This is shown in Pfattheicher and Keller (2013, Appendix D); the disposition of prevention-focused self-regulation was significantly positively related to costly punishment. This finding fits the theoretical considerations discussed above. On a strategic level, prevention focus is related to vigilant avoidance strategies. However, as outlined, this does not mean that prevention-focused individuals always use avoidant tactics, as reflected in behavioral inhibition or inaction (Gable, Reis, & Elliot, 2000; Scholer & Higgins, 2008). That is exactly what we can document; strongly preventionfocused individuals were more likely to take action and punish as compared with weakly prevention-focused individuals. Scholer and Higgins (2008) wrote: “It is common to associate approach and avoidance at the behavioral level with action and inaction, respectively” (p. 491). If the assumption holds true that an avoidance tactic should lead to behavioral inhibition or inaction, that is, the omission of costly punishment, we should be able to document a negative relation, or at least a non-relation, between behavioral inhibition and costly punishment. Indeed, behavioral inhibition, as measured with Carver and White’s (1994) BIS scale, had a close to zero-order relation to costly punishment; when prevention and promotion were controlled for, a negative relation was found (although this relation did not reach conventional levels of significance, B = -.15, p = .14). These findings support our arguments that prevention focus is related to a special concern with normative standards and entails regulatory tactics to take action. This is not the case for the BIS as conceptualized in Gray’s theory (1970, 1982) and Carver and White’s (1994) approach (cf. Pfattheicher and Keller, 2013, Appendix D). In sum, the empirical paper (Pfattheicher & Keller, 2013, Appendix D) made three important contributions to the scientific literature. First, we were able to differentiate prevention focus from behavioral inhibition on the tactical level which is well in line EMPIRICAL PAPERS 69 with recent developments of RFT (Higgins, 2012a, 2012b; Scholer & Higgins, 2008, 2011). Second, our approach to examine the association between basal motivational orientations (specifically, prevention-focused self-regulatory orientation and behavioral inhibition) and costly punishment addresses a gap in the field of costly punishment in social dilemma situations. Third, from the perspective of individual differences, the presented work is the first study that relates costly punishment in a public goods game to individual differences. Interpersonal differences regarding cooperative behavior in social dilemma situations have previously been repeatedly shown (e.g., Hilbig, Zettler, & Heydasch, 2012; Hirsh & Peterson, 2009; Kurzban & Houser, 2001). The work presented here, however, is the first study to empirically relate costly punishment in public goods games to individual differences. 3.4.3 Integrating reputational concerns and oughts As outlined, reputation refers to judgments of relevant others about ones’ personal qualities and how one behaves (Emler, 1990), and reputational concerns refer to the concerns regarding how others think about one’s personal qualities and behavior. Reputational concerns therefore include how one thinks one ought to behave, that is, one’s perceived duties, responsibilities, and social expectations as set by others. In other words, one can argue that reputational concerns correspond to the ought-self. In Pfattheicher et al. (2014, Appendix C; cf. Chapter 3.3 above) it is documented that costly punishment was reduced when the ought-self was activated, that is, when reputational concerns were rendered salient. In contrast, prevention-focused individuals, that is, individuals who possess a strong ought-self, are more likely to engage in costly punishment compared with relatively weakly prevention-focused individuals. How can these apparently inconsistent findings be integrated? I postulate that the ought-system in prevention-focused individuals needs to be differentiated. Specifically, I argue that prevention-focused individuals possess an oughtfocus that is relevant for the self, but they also possess an ought-focus that is relevant for others. The ought-self-focus is activated in situations when it is relevant how “oneself” behaves in the eyes of others. These are situations in which an individual should fulfill EMPIRICAL PAPERS 70 social expectations, duties, and responsibilities as is the case when reputational concerns are rendered salient. The ought-other-focus is activated in situations when it is relevant how others behave in one’s own eyes. These are situations in which others should fulfill social norms. I propose that the ought-other-focus is activated when other group members behave uncooperatively, that is, when others violate a fairness norm. In contrast, the ought-focus that is relevant for the self is activated in situations when it is relevant how one behaves in the eyes of others, that is, when reputational concerns are rendered salient. As documented, when the ought-self-focus is activated through rendering reputational concerns salient, different effects can be found than one would expect when the oughtother-focus is activated (i.e., reduced costly punishment when the ought-self-focus is activated vs. increased costly punishment when the ought-other-focus is activated). Of course, the differentiation of the ought-foci needs direct empirical validation. For instance, one could experimentally test the proposed differentiation by activating the ought-self-focus in one experimental group (e.g., activating one’s focus on how oneself ought to behave, for instance through activation of reputational concerns), the oughtother-focus in another (e.g., through activating one’s focus on how others ought to behave), and comparing these two conditions to a neutral control condition. Assuming that the uncooperative behavior of another individual should already activate the oughtother-focus (also in the neutral control group), one should not necessarily find a difference between the control condition and the condition in which the ought-otherfocus is rendered salient. In line with our studies (Pfattheicher et al., 2014, Appendix C), however, one should find reduced costly punishment when the ought-self-focus is rendered salient. 3.4.4 Additional theoretical remarks One has to acknowledge that the empirical paper presented remains silent regarding the causal nature of the prevention-costly punishment relation. Several different methods have been proposed to manipulate prevention focus such as to activate current security concerns (Friedman & Förster, 2001), or current ought-self concerns (Scholer et al., EMPIRICAL PAPERS 71 2010), or by simultaneously activating security and ought-self concerns (Higgins et al., 2001). Indeed, it seems a valuable approach to experimentally manipulate prevention focus and to use a causal-analytic approach. However, one must note that it appears important which dimension of prevention focus is manipulated. In line with the considerations regarding the differentiation of the ought-foci (see above), a differentiation of prevention focus could also be considered. In specific domains, an ought-self manipulation may not result in the same outcomes as a manipulation rendering security concerns salient. This may hold true because different regulatory tactics are applied depending on the activated dimension. For instance, it seems reasonable that rendering security concerns salient results in a defensive, risk-averse tactic (Friedman & Förster, 2001) whereas an ought-self manipulation results in active impression management. As a consequence one could ask whether it is actually meaningful to consider prevention focus to reflect one construct. The evaluative dimensions of whether prevention focus should be considered to be one construct could be (a) the parsimoniousness of a theory and (b) the ability of a theory to make predictions. Emphasizing the parsimoniousness of a theory, one should reject the differentiation of prevention focus. Neglecting the parsimoniousness of a theory and moving toward a theory of middle range or in an even more concrete direction (Merton, 1968), one should consider prevention focus to be one construct with different dimensions. This is not the case in current conceptualizations of RFT; prevention focus (and promotion focus) is considered to be one construct. Taking the other evaluative dimension into account, that is, the ability of a theory to make predictions, it seems reasonable to differentiate the prevention focus. This claim is supported by the present findings that ought-self concerns reduced costly punishment whereas ought-other concerns probably relate positively to costly punishment, and thus move in exactly the opposite direction. Congruently, one can expect distinct effects if one renders security concerns or ought concerns salient, because different regulatory tactics are likely to be executed (see above). That is, without a differentiating prevention focus precise predictions are not possible. EMPIRICAL PAPERS 72 In this regard, a comparative model could be the conceptualization of “social class” or socioeconomic status (SES), defined as the rank of an individual in comparison to others in a society with regard to wealth, occupation, and education (Adler, Epel, Castellazzo, & Ickovics, 2000). Piff, Stancato, Côté, Mendoza-Denton, and Keltner (2012) suggest that upper-class individuals, relative to lower-class individuals, behave more unethically. Specifically, they have shown that individuals driving upper-class (vs. lower-class) vehicles in terms of make, age, and appearance are more likely to cut off other vehicles and pedestrians. Moreover, they have shown that individuals’ subjective SES was negatively correlated with tendencies toward a variety of unethical decisions, and it was positively correlated with positive attitudes toward greed and lying. Piff et al. (2012) focused on specific dimensions of social class, that is, individuals’ subjective belief of being superior to others (as measured by individuals’ subjective SES) and individuals’ (economic) ability to drive so-called “upper-class vehicles”. This surely neglects certain dimensions of social class, for instance one’s objective educational achievement or one’s subjective job prestige.34 Interestingly, Krause (2011) has shown a small negative correlation between individuals’ objective educational achievement and the antisocial attitude of hostility. Likewise, Hessing, Elffers, Robben, and Webley (1993) documented that individuals who fraudulently claimed unemployment benefits were less educated than a honest control group. These findings suggest that one dimension of social class (i.e., education) may in fact be negatively related to antisocial behavior. This comparative example emphasizes that in order to make precise predictions about a general construct one has to distinguish its specific dimensions. Otherwise, one would make false theoretical conclusions, for instance as done by Piff et al. (2012). They concluded that “upper-class individuals behave more unethically than lower-class individuals” (p. 4086) which has to be refuted in light of the findings by Krause (2011). A solution would be to differentiate the concept of social 34 It is another question whether subjective and objective class constitute one dimension, as Piff et al. (2012) indirectly assumed; already Karl Marx (1847/2009) emphasized the importance of this differentiation when he spoke about a class “in itself” (i.e., objective class, or common standard in terms of means of production) as opposed to a class “for itself” (i.e., subjective class, or class consciousness). EMPIRICAL PAPERS 73 class (as typically done in the field of sociology, for instance by Bourdieu, 1979) and to outline that the different dimensions of social class may be differentially related to unethical behavior. Likewise, one can propose a general prevention focus dimension including specific domains such as security concerns and ought concerns with a differentiation of the latter into ought-self and ought-other concerns. This claim is in line with Karl Popper’s idea of falsifying (instead of verifying) theories (Popper, 2002). If a general prevention focus dimension cannot predict outcomes whereas a prevention focus including specific domains can, the general prevention focus dimension should be rejected in favor of a prevention focus including specific domains. 3.4.5 Integrating findings on cortisol and prevention focus I have shown that endogenous cortisol is negatively related to costly punishment whereas prevention-focused self-regulation is positively related to costly punishment. By integrating these findings and considerations one can argue that prevention focus should only be positively related to costly punishment when cortisol levels are relatively low, because high cortisol levels are related to behavioral withdrawal and inhibition (Blair et al., 2004; Brown et al., 1996; Nava et al., 2006; Tops & Boksem, 2011; van Honk et al., 2010; Windle, 1994). Consequently, one can assume that cortisol may inhibit the pathway between prevention focus and costly punishment. A re-analysis of a data set in which cortisol and prevention focus were measured (N = 72) indeed revealed a significant interaction between endogenous cortisol and prevention focus (p < .01). Simple slope analyses showed that prevention was only significantly positively related to costly punishment when basal cortisol was relatively low (1 SD below the mean; p < .001), but not when basal cortisol was relatively high (1 SD above the mean; p = .46). These findings strengthened the notion that cortisol is indeed related to behavioral withdrawal and inhibition and they suggest that endogenous cortisol may indeed inhibit the pathway between prevention focus and costly punishment. In sum, the empirical work presented documents that self-regulatory orientations play a crucial role in guiding individuals’ thoughts and behavior in social dilemma situations. EMPIRICAL PAPERS 74 Considering the case of costly punishment in particular, I emphasized that it is necessary to elaborate on self-regulatory orientations in order to reach a comprehensive understanding of costly punishment. Therefore, it seems important to take individuals’ self-guide into account, that is, whether individuals act in accordance to the social expectations of others (the proposed ought-self-focus) or whether individuals act in accordance to the social expectations of oneself (the proposed ought-other-focus). To conclude, the work presented addressed a gap in the literature on costly punishment and individual differences as well as basal motivational orientations. Notably, we were able to add valuable empirical evidence regarding the distinctiveness of prevention focus in comparison with another vigilant self-regulatory orientation. As such, the work presented represents a valuable contribution to the literature on costly punishment, individual differences, and basal motivational orientations. So far, the present dissertation has focused on costly punishment of uncooperative individuals in public goods situations. Interestingly, a specific destructive behavior emerges in public goods situations when a system of costly punishment is implemented: antisocial punishment, that is, costly punishing cooperative individuals (cf. Herrmann et al., 2008). The “dark side” of costly punishment is the focus of the following chapter. 3.5 Individual differences in antisocial punishment in public goods situations: The interplay of cortisol with testosterone and dominance (Pfattheicher, Landhäußer, & Keller, in press, Appendix E) When reviewing the literature on antisocial punishment, it can be seen that only a few empirical papers have investigated this interesting behavioral phenomenon, that is, the investigation of antisocial punishment has been almost completely neglected in social dilemma research thus far (cf. Dreber & Rand, 2012; Herrmann et al., 2008). Published empirical papers exclusively focus on the boundary conditions of antisocial punishment. For instance, Herrmann et al. (2008) showed that antisocial punishment is more likely to emerge in societies with relatively weak norms of civic cooperation and an established and functioning judiciary (see also Gächter & Herrmann, 2009). Lamba and Mace (2011) showed that antisocial punishment is more likely to emerge when an outgroup member EMPIRICAL PAPERS 75 (as compared with an ingroup member) can be punished (for similar findings see also Bernhard, Fischbacher, & Fehr, 2006, and Goette, Huffman, Meier, & Sutter, 2012). Building on these findings Sylwester et al. (2013) argue that antisocial punishment of outgroup members is used to increase one’s own group’s status through the devaluation of an outgroup. A biopsychological perspective on antisocial punishment that investigates endocrinological and psychological factors is completely lacking. Our empirical work (Pfattheicher et al., in press, Appendix E) has examined antisocial punishment from a biopsychological perspective and has, therefore, addressed a remarkable gap in this line of research. In our paper we have argued that antisocial punishment in a typical public goods game is in line with destructive dominant behavior, which we define as a propensity toward forceful, competitive, and aggressive behavior to attain social rank (Cheng, Tracy, Foulsham, Kingstone, & Henrich, 2013; Mazur & Booth, 1998). Basically, in a typical public goods game as applied in the present work, punishing other group members has the effect that one’s own payoff is reduced by a specific amount of money and the punished individual’s payoff is reduced by a factor of three. So, individuals can increase their rank by destructively punishing others (because the costs of punishment are greater for the punished than for the punisher). That is to say, punishing cooperative individuals reflects an aggressive act that allows an increase in rank.35 These considerations exactly fit those of Sylwester et al. (2013) who also emphasized the aggressive component in antisocial punishment and the possibility of increasing one’s rank in comparison to others. These authors wrote: “This suggests that some instances of costly punishment, in particular antisocial punishment, may function as aggressive acts, and are not contingent on the previous cooperative behavior of the punished individuals. In sum, in apparently irrational costly antisocial behavior, the decisions to punish are, at least in some studies, logically tied to the effectiveness of such punishment and to the 35 To establish transparency, I want to mention that this paragraph includes sentences taken from Pfattheicher et al. (in press, Appendix E). EMPIRICAL PAPERS 76 ability to increase the positive difference between others’ payoffs and one’s own” (p. 172, emphases added). Given that antisocial punishment corresponds to the basic notion of dominance, we proposed that antisocial punishment should be related to psychological dominance and the dominance-related hormone testosterone (Mehta et al., 2008; Sellers, Mehl, & Josephs, 2007). Additionally, we applied the dual-hormone perspective according to which testosterone is related to dominant and destructive behavior but only in individuals with a low level of endogenous cortisol (Carré & Mehta, 2011; Mehta & Josephs, 2010). Congruently, we have argued that psychological dominance (i.e., forceful, competitive, and aggressive orientations to attain social rank) should be positively related to antisocial punishment and, in line with the dual-hormone perspective, this relation should only hold for individuals with a low level of endogenous cortisol. Indeed, in two studies we were able to document that antisocial punishment was positively related to testosterone and to psychological dominance, but only in individuals with a relatively low level of cortisol. Cortisol again seems to inhibit a pathway, this time the pathway between testosterone and dominance concerns about antisocial punishment. In contrast, testosterone and psychological dominance were not significantly related to costly punishment of uncooperative individuals, neither as a main effect nor as an interaction involving cortisol (see the discussion below regarding this point and Pfattheicher et al., in press, Appendix E). As mentioned above, research on costly punishment in social dilemma situations has almost completely neglected the case of antisocial punishment (Dreber & Rand, 2012; Herrmann et al., 2008). As such, the work presented addressed a remarkable gap in this line of research by showing that one has to take the endocrinological factor of testosterone and the psychological factor of dominance as well as their interaction with cortisol into account in order to reach a comprehensive understanding of antisocial punishment. To conclude, antisocial punishment does indeed seem to be driven by dominance concerns, as suggested by Sylwester and colleagues (2013). The work presented is the first work that has empirically tested this notion. EMPIRICAL PAPERS 77 3.5.1 Relations to other work In the empirical paper we discussed possible underlying mechanisms of the findings and related our work to interesting work by other researchers (cf. the General Discussion in Pfattheicher et al., in press, Appendix E). In order to avoid redundancies, this discussion is not repeated. There is one line of research that is not addressed in the paper. Specifically, it has been shown that men with a relatively high level of endogenous testosterone are more likely to reject unfair offers in an ultimatum game as compared with men with a relatively low level of testosterone (Burnham, 2007; Mehta & Beer, 2010). That is to say, costly punishment of unfair others is positively related to endogenous testosterone (assuming that one can treat the rejection in an ultimatum game as costly punishment of uncooperative behavior). In contrast, we did not find a positive association between testosterone and costly punishment of uncooperative individuals in the public goods game. Given that testosterone is related to dominance concerns (Eisenegger, Naef, Snozzi, Heinrichs, & Fehr, 2010), it seems possible that costly punishment of uncooperative others in an ultimatum game but not in a public goods game can more easily fulfill one’s need for dominance. For instance, given the direct head-to-head constellation in the ultimatum game but not in the public goods game it may be the case that one can more easily prevent the first player being “better off” than oneself by destroying both payoffs, that is, by engaging in costly punishment. The differences found in costly punishment with respect to costly punishment in a public goods game and in an ultimatum game are grist to the mill for people emphasizing the difference between costly punishment in an ultimatum game and in a public goods game. Future research should investigate the different motives of these two forms of costly punishment (cf. Chapter 1.4). Other work has claimed to test the causal effect of testosterone on costly punishment. Specifically, Zak et al. (2009) showed that testosterone administration is associated with increased costly punishment in an ultimatum game in men, which was, however, not replicated in women (Eisenegger et al., 2010). Zethraeus et al. (2009) also did not find this effect in women after long-term testosterone administration. However, one has to be EMPIRICAL PAPERS 78 cautious when interpreting these experimental findings. What can be said is that the administration of testosterone can have a causal effect on ultimatum game rejections (Zak et al., 2009). What cannot be said is that testosterone itself directly affects costly punishment because hormones, and specifically testosterone, cross-talk on several levels (Viau, 2002). For instance, it is shown that testosterone inhibits the cortisol releasing HPA axis (Rubinow et al., 2005), which speaks to the notion that testosterone administration lowers endogenous cortisol levels. As shown in our work, individuals with a relatively low (vs. high) cortisol level are more likely to engage in costly punishment. From this basis one could assume that cortisol levels may also drive the effects of testosterone administrations. That is to say, testosterone administration influences several biological pathways to behavior. In other words, testosterone administrations are confounded in that it is not only endogenous testosterone levels that are manipulated. What can additionally be said is that negative feedback loops following the exogenous administration of testosterone are very possible, that is, the actual downregulation of the testosterone releasing HPG axis (Eisenegger, Haushofer, & Fehr, 2011). As with the investigation of exogenous cortisol (cf. Chapter 3.1), the investigation of exogenous testosterone is problematic, at least when one would like to draw causal inferences regarding testosterone itself. 3.5.2 Proposals for future research In line with Sylwester et al. (2013), we (Pfattheicher et al., in press, Appendix E) proposed that individuals increase their rank by destructively punishing others because the costs of punishment are greater for the punished than for the punisher. If antisocial punishment in our studies is, at least in some part, driven by status and dominance concerns, antisocial punishment should be reduced when status and dominance concerns cannot be fulfilled through antisocial punishment. For instance, one could reduce the effectiveness of costly punishment to a level where the amount that is invested in costly punishment is equal to the reduction of another individuals’ payoff (cf. Shinada, Yamagishi, & Ohmura, 2004). Therefore, one could not, at least, increase their monetary rank, which should reduce antisocial punishment if status and dominance motives are at work when engaging in antisocial punishment. EMPIRICAL PAPERS 79 An intriguing approach in the investigation of antisocial punishment would be to relate antisocial punishment to individual differences. If antisocial punishment is indeed driven by interindividual comparisons (i.e., status and dominance concerns), individuals possessing a strong competitive orientation, as implemented in the social value orientation of van Lange, De Bruin, Otten, and Joireman (1997), should be likely to engage in antisocial punishment. Another intriguing approach would be to relate antisocial punishment to social values, as conceptualized in Schwartz’s model of basic human values (Schwartz, & Bilsky, 1990; Schwartz et al., 2012). In the recently revised model of basic human values (Schwartz et al., 2012), three candidates may be related to antisocial punishment as conceptualized in this dissertation (i.e., antisocial punishment as destructive and dominant aggression toward cooperative group members). First, antisocial punishment should be negatively related to the prosocial human value of “benevolence-caring” which is defined as the devotion of welfare to ingroup members. Antisocial punishment seems to involve rather opposite tendencies in this regard. Second, antisocial punishment should be negatively related to the prosocial human value of “benevolence-dependability” which is defined as being reliable and trustworthy toward ingroup members. Again, antisocial punishment seems to involve rather opposite tendencies in this regard. Third, if antisocial punishment is executed to control other individuals’ payoff and to increase one’s status, antisocial punishment should be positively related to the human value of “power-resources” because this value reflects the need for power through controlling material and social resources. Basically, one can conclude that research on antisocial punishment would benefit from an individual difference perspective because this approach could shed at least some light on the motives for antisocial punishment. Integrating research on reputational concerns and costly punishment, Sylwester et al. (2013) proposed that antisocial punishment can function as a costly signal. Specifically, antisocial punishment can be executed to attain a reputation for aggressiveness and to signal social dominance. Griskevicius et al. (2009), for instance, have shown that aggression can be used to impress others. However, as suggested in our work on reputational concerns and costly punishment of uncooperative individuals (Pfattheicher EMPIRICAL PAPERS 80 et al., 2014, Appendix C), costly punishment may be considered socially undesirable. Therefore, one must consider specific situations in which antisocial punishment may not be socially undesirable and can therefore function as a costly signal (e.g., competitive male-to-male aggression in young men to acquire a reputation for dominance, as documented by Hilton, Harris, & Rice, 2000). To sum up, I have shown that testosterone and psychological dominance (given low cortisol) relate to one interesting behavior that emerges in public goods games when costly punishment is possible, that is, antisocial punishment. As such, the work presented contributes to a better understanding of antisocial punishment which is important given that research has almost completely neglected antisocial punishment thus far (Dreber & Rand, 2012; Herrmann et al., 2008). Moreover, I have outlined that future research can aim to answer questions regarding psychological boundary conditions, individual differences, and the specific cognitive processes that explain antisocial punishment. The present work can surely represent a meaningful basis in this regard. GENERAL DISCUSSION 81 4 General discussion In social dilemma situations, individuals face a mutually interdependent situation in that their benefits depend on the behavior of the other individuals involved in the situation. Social dilemmas are further characterized by conflicting interests; specifically, maximizing one’s individual benefit stands in conflict with maximizing the benefit of the collective. This is the specific quality that is inherent in social dilemma situations (Camerer, 2003) and that is why Hardin (1968) speaks of a tragedy: behaving selfishly is always the most benefitting strategy from a benefit-maximizing perspective. The problem is also manifested in a Nash equilibrium that exists when all individuals behave uncooperatively, because no one has any incentive to individually change their behavior. That is to say, the quality of social dilemmas is that they are intractable, strong situations in which individuals benefit from acting against the collective (Esser, 2000). Another aspect of social dilemmas makes them worth investigating, that is, the quantity of their appearance (van Lange et al., 2007; van Lange et al., 2013). Humans face social dilemmas on several levels (Yurdusev, 1993), on the macro-level, for instance when it comes to the issue of climate change, on the meso-level, when it comes to diverging interests in a village concerning the water irrigation system (cf. Ostrom, 1990), and on the micro-level, when students undertake group work and can benefit from being a freerider. The quality and the quantity argument constitute the rationale for why factors that foster cooperation in social dilemma situations should be investigated. Kollock (1998) has systematically outlined three different perspectives on how to solve social dilemmas. Whereas the structural perspective and the strategic perspective emphasize the fundamental goal of maximizing benefits (Kollock, 1998), the motivational (psychological) perspective emphasizes that individuals not only take their own benefit into account but also that of other individuals involved in the situation. Batson and colleagues (Batson et al., 2008; Batson, et al., 2002) specified the motivational perspective and claimed three general non-egoistic motivations for why people act for the public good (collectivism, principlism, and altruism). In the present work I have extended this view to one important behavior that increases cooperation in a GENERAL DISCUSSION 82 remarkable way: costly punishment (Balliet et al., 2011; Fehr & Gächter, 2002). Specifically, I have outlined that costly punishment can represent a structural solution for establishing cooperation (cf. Fehr & Gächter, 2002). Furthermore, I have discussed the possibility that costly punishment is strategically executed to obtain benefits. Specifically, I have focused on claims that costly punishment is strategically executed to improve one’s mood and to gain reputational benefits. These claims could be refuted, as summarized below. Generally, I have emphasized the third perspective introduced by Kollock (1998), that is, the question of why individuals are motivated, beyond strategic and structural considerations, to punish uncooperative and cooperative others. This motivational perspective and the corresponding empirical findings from the literature and the studies presented are summarized in the following section. 4.1 Summarizing the findings As outlined in the introduction, research on costly punishment in public goods situations has documented that costly punishment of uncooperative others can be considered to be predominantly driven by anger on the basis of a fairness norm violation by low contributors (e.g., Cubitt et al., 2011; Fehr & Fischbacher, 2004). Costly punishment reflects a behavior that seems to result from the impulsive system rather than the reflective system, that is, costly punishment can be considered to be an impulsive act (e.g., Crockett et al., 2010; Halali et al., in press). Moreover, research on costly punishment suggests that costly punishment corresponds to the idea of reactive aggression (e.g., Crockett et al., 2010; Osumi et al., 2012; Stirrat & Perrett, 2010). Research on anticipated reward (Gollwitzer & Bushman, 2012) and our work on reputation (Pfattheicher et al., 2014, Appendix C) show that costly punishment is neither strategically executed in order to improve one’s mood nor to gain a valuable reputation. The findings therefore question the benefit-maximizing strategic perspective. This acquired knowledge is indeed a valuable contribution to the literature because the findings contradict the conceptualization of costly punishment as a benefit-maximizing strategy as proposed by several scholars in the field of costly punishment (Barclay, 2006; Dos Santos et al., 2011; Fehr & Gächter, 2002; Gächter & Herrmann, 2009; Hagen & GENERAL DISCUSSION 83 Hammerstein, 2006; Hilbe & Traulsen, 2012; Kurzban et al. 2007; Nelissen, 2008; Piazza & Bering, 2008; Shaw & Santons, 2012; Sylwester et al., 2013; Tennie, 2012). Although research on costly punishment has produced a large number of articles in recent years, there still exist remarkable research gaps. The empirical papers I have presented address several neglected areas in this field of research. I have shown that endogenous cortisol is negatively related to costly punishment. From this finding one can conclude that a relatively low level of cortisol can function as a condition for engaging in costly punishment. This consideration is supported by the finding that strongly prevention-focused individuals are more likely to engage in costly punishment of uncooperative individuals as compared with weakly prevention-focused individuals, but only when strongly prevention-focused individuals have a relatively low level of cortisol. In distinguishing prevention focus from a general inhibitory tendency, I have documented that only prevention focus significantly predicts costly punishment whereas behavioral inhibition is instead negatively related to costly punishment (although not significantly at a conventional level). Therefore, this work did not only contribute to research on costly punishment in social dilemma situations but also to a better understanding of prevention focus in distinction to other motivational theories. Following this, I outlined and discussed our study showing that subtle cues of being watched lead to an increased sense of being seen, an assumption that was made in other research but had not been empirically tested before. Applying this subtle cue of being watched to render reputational concerns salient, I documented that activating (vs. not activating) reputational concerns reduced costly punishment. In this regard, I have proposed that one has to differentiate an ought-self-focus from an ought-other-focus because one can make different predictions depending on which focus is activated. These considerations are also relevant for RFT because they emphasize that, when considering the ought-self of the prevention focus, one has to specify which ought-focus is relevant in a given situation in order to make precise predictions. In a final step I shed light on biopsychological factors that can explain the punishment of cooperative individuals, that is, antisocial punishment. A biopsychological analysis of GENERAL DISCUSSION 84 this interesting behavioral phenomenon has not been done before. Showing that testosterone and psychological dominance predict antisocial punishment given a relatively low cortisol level provides a solid basis for future research on antisocial punishment. In sum, the empirical papers presented have addressed several research gaps in the field of costly punishment. Together, they have surely contributed to a better understanding of costly punishment in public goods situations, which was the main aim of the present dissertation. However, it should have become clear in the course of this dissertation that there are a remarkable number of research questions still to be considered. In the following sections I want to discuss methodological issues that apply to the specific paradigm applied in our studies as well as methodological issues that apply to the biopsychological perspective. 4.2 Discussion of the applied paradigm In the studies reported, we used the paradigm of Fehr and Gächter (2002) to investigate costly punishment in public goods situations. This paradigm has several methodological strengths. First, our participants behaved under anonymous conditions. This approach ensured that individuals’ behavior was not influenced by strategic behavioral shifts due to a lack of anonymity. Indeed, strategic behavioral shifts are commonly observed when anonymity is taken away (e.g., Bushman & Huesmann, 2010; Diener, 1976). Second, one-shot games were applied, that is, individuals interacted only once with another individual. Thus, strategic considerations where individuals try to strategically shape the behavior of others in order to gain personal benefits in future interactions were minimized because there were no future interactions (at least within the studies). This is particularly important given that we investigated whether costly punishment is strategically executed in order to gain a valuable reputation; if costly punishment had already been strategically executed (i.e., if strategic considerations had not been minimized, for instance when mutual interactions were possible) the likelihood that we would have been able to have observed an effect in terms of reputation on top of already strategically executed costly punishment would have been fairly low. GENERAL DISCUSSION 85 Moreover, by applying a reduced situation we were able to investigate costly punishment beyond strategic considerations, thus focusing on the essence of costly punishment. Generally speaking, our aim was to understand the basic of costly punishment beyond strategic considerations. This was possible using the parsimonious paradigm of Fehr and Gächter (2002). 4.3 Discussion of the biopsychological perspective Another notable strength of the work presented is the application of a biopsychological perspective. This approach enabled us to show that costly punishment of uncooperative individuals can be predicted by basal levels of cortisol. Hence, we could relate costly punishment to processes typically associated with basal levels of cortisol, that is, impulsivity, vigilance, and behavioral withdrawal. This is worth mentioning because individuals often have difficulties and a restricted ability to correctly report the motives and processes underlying their behavior (Nisbett & Wilson, 1977), and may engage in socially desirable responding (which is not the case when assessing hormone levels). Of course, future research is needed to provide more direct empirical evidence regarding the process (e.g., via a manipulation; cf. Jacoby & Sassenberg, 2011; Spencer et al., 2005). Our research can constitute a meaningful basis in this regard. By relating antisocial punishment to testosterone and dominance concerns (given a relatively low level of cortisol) we were able to shed light on the underlying factors of antisocial punishment. Indeed, taking interactions between hormones (cortisol, testosterone) and psychological motivations (dominance concerns) into account prevented us from drawing false conclusions. If we had not assessed cortisol, we could have come to the probably false conclusion that dominance concerns and testosterone may not play a role in antisocial punishment. Interestingly, the relation of the prevention focus and costly punishment was moderated by basal cortisol in that a positive relation could only be documented in individuals with a relatively low level of cortisol. Thus, a biopsychological perspective also offers a meaningful boundary condition (given cortisol’s positive link to behavioral withdrawal; Blair et al., 2004; Brown et al., 1996; Nava et al., 2006; Tops & Boksem, 2011; van GENERAL DISCUSSION 86 Honk et al., 2010; Windle, 1994) of the relation of one important basal motivational orientation and costly punishment. In sum, a biopsychological perspective offers the potential to draw conclusions but also to prevent false or no conclusions. That is to say, a biopsychological perspective does indeed provide a meaningful framework to reach a better understanding of costly punishment in public goods situations. I want to acknowledge, nonetheless, that the biopsychological perspective also has its shortcomings. First of all, the present research remains silent regarding the causal nature of the observed relations and the more specific endocrinological pathway. Whereas the specific endocrinological pathway was not the focus of the present research and requires the knowledge of endocrinologists to reach a more fine-grained level of analysis, showing causal relations is deeply rooted in the field of psychology. As outlined above, it is possible to manipulate cortisol (this applies to testosterone levels, too) via exogenous cortisol or via situational stressful demands. This approach, however, has major setbacks given that exogenous cortisol and typically applied manipulations to increase cortisol levels, for instance the Trier Social Stress Test (TSST), have a nonnegligible amount of confounds (cf. Chapter 3.1.1). In sum, one has to acknowledge that the present work remains silent regarding the causal nature of the observed relations. This should not, however, limit the valuable conclusions that could be drawn using the existing studies. In the following section I want to go beyond specific research findings and discuss costly punishment in social dilemma situations from a more general perspective. Specifically, I will address three main questions: first, given that the present work is based on studies from the laboratory, I ask how adequate it is to investigate social dilemma situations and costly punishment in the laboratory. The second question builds on these considerations and asks what can be deduced from the studies presented for behavior in “real life”. Third, given that Fehr and Gächter (2002) termed costly punishment of uncooperative individuals “altruistic punishment” and given that this term is frequently used in the literature, I will discuss the role of altruism in costly punishment. GENERAL DISCUSSION 87 4.4 The subjective construction of social dilemmas The famous Thomas-Theorem is grounded in the sentence “if men define situations as real, they are real in their consequences” (Thomas & Thomas, 1928). That is, individuals behave according to their subjective construction of reality (Esser, 2000; Smith & Mackie, 2007). When participants face a public goods game in the laboratory, the subjective conditions of such a situation indeed reflect a social dilemma situation. Typically, individuals ascribe value to money, that is, they subjectively construe the value of money (e.g., Bruner & Goodman, 1947). Having subjectively ascribed value to money and wanting to maximize the amount they have of it (regardless of the actual motive such as greed, selfishness, satisfying security needs etc.), individuals face a social dilemma situation when confronted with a public goods game in the laboratory. If individuals subjectively want more money the best strategy in this regard would be to behave uncooperatively. The strategy of maximizing one’s own benefit has the effect that the benefit of the collective is reduced as compared with a cooperative strategy. This subjectively construed situation does reflect a social dilemma situation. As such, one can certainly investigate social dilemma situations per se in the laboratory. There are substantial advantages to investigating social dilemmas in the laboratory. Only laboratories allow the investigation of social dilemma situations in a simple, reduced situation in which external influences can be controlled and causal analytic approaches applied, which would be rather difficult when investigating social dilemma situations in the field (cf. van Lange et al., 2014). With regard to the subjective construction of reality, individuals construe social dilemma situations differently. Halevy et al. (2012) have impressively shown that when individuals should describe a conflicting two-person situation, they mainly use either the benefit matrix of a Prisoner’s Dilemma (in which the benefits of the two persons maximally diverge), a Chicken Game (in which the benefits of the two persons moderately diverge), an Assurance Game (in which the benefits of the two persons also moderately diverge), or a Maximizing Difference Game (in which the benefits of the two GENERAL DISCUSSION 88 persons correspond positively).36 Given that individuals construe a conflict differently, it seems likely that individuals also construe an objective benefit matrix differently and in accordance with their basic needs, motivations, attitudes, and values (Halevy, Chou, & Murnighan, 2011). In other words, I propose that individuals construe their subjective benefit within a given objective payoff matrix of a theoretical game paradigm. For instance, individuals with a basic prosocial orientation (e.g., chronically altruistic individuals; Kuhl & Kazén, 1997) should ascribe a greater value to cooperation in comparison with competitive individuals (van Lange, 1997) because cooperation is more in line with their basic values (Halevy et al., 2011). While I argue that it is possible to investigate social dilemmas in the laboratory, the issue of how specifically individuals subjectively construe an objectively given payoff matrix in a social dilemma game still needs investigating. This also holds true for the subjective construction of costly punishment. It has been shown that the fewer objective resources one has to invest in costly punishment and the higher the impact on the punished is the more individuals use costly punishment (Anderson & Putterman, 2006; Egas & Riedl, 2005). However, given that reality is a subjective construction, this question should also be investigated from a subjective perspective, that is, does the same effect emerge when individuals subjectively ascribe higher as opposed to lower costs to costly punishment? This question is important given the strong influence of costly punishment on human cooperation (Fehr & Gächter, 2002). Specifically, if individuals subjectively ascribe too many costs to punishment the problem of how to establish cooperation is surely pronounced. Another future line of research could also contribute to a better understanding of how individuals construe costly punishment. Specifically, one could investigate how prevention-focused individuals construe the benefit of costly punishment and, consequently, whether a possible specific subjective construction predicts their costly punishment behavior. In this regard, an investigation of the subjective value of costly 36 This game actually represents no conflict because mutual cooperation is the joint optimum and a Nash equilibrium. GENERAL DISCUSSION 89 punishment when others are present (e.g., when a subtle cue of being watched is given) also seems to be a valuable approach. Specifically, if one’s own reputational concerns drive the effects, the subjectively considered benefit from engaging in costly punishment should be reduced when others are present. This, in turn, should predict the actual reduction of costly punishment under conditions of social presence. Generally, it would be a valuable approach to investigate how individuals subjectively construe costly punishment as well as the consequences of this subjectively construed reality on objective cooperation levels. This strategy would, indeed, provide a better understanding of why and under which conditions individuals engage in costly punishment. 4.5 Implications for behavior in “real life” Of course, studies in the laboratory remain silent (and should remain silent) about humans’ general behavior in social dilemma situations in the “real world” (Mook, 1983). This is, however, not considered when Camerer and Fehr (2004) state that “[f]or example, if many people in a society exhibit inequality aversion or reciprocity, they will be willing to punish those who do not share food, so no formal mechanism is needed to govern food sharing. Without such preferences, formal mechanisms are needed to sustain food sharing (or sharing does not occur at all)” (p. 56). This direct transfer from the laboratory to general human behavior in real life is not an exceptional case (cf. Guala, 2012). It remains unclear whether motives, processes, or the function of specific behavior observed in the laboratory also holds true in real life. For instance, it is plausible that specific forms of punishment in real life are not driven by impulsivity (e.g., when a ticket inspector punishes a free-riding fare dodger). That is, situations in real life are often qualitatively different from those in the laboratory. Consequently, one should avoid a direct transfer from the laboratory to general human behavior in real life. Elinor Ostrom is a good example of how to integrate research from the laboratory and research from the field. In her research, Ostrom (1990) investigated costly punishment in social dilemma situations in the laboratory. In a next step, she observed punishment of uncooperative individuals and its effects on free-riders in the real world. Not till then did GENERAL DISCUSSION 90 she conclude that “graduated sanctions” (p. 94) represent one possibility for reducing the free-rider problem in real world social dilemma situations. Of note, Ostrom speaks about sanctions, not about costly sanctions or costly punishment. In line with this view, I want to emphasize that the aspect of costs was not at the center of this dissertation and with good cause given that the specificity of costly (monetary) punishment in comparison with other forms of punishment (e.g., social disapproval) needs solid investigation in future research. This was also reflected in the articles presented when I spoke about reactive aggression but not about costly reactive aggression. It is still an unsolved issue whether costly punishment, as conceptualized by evolutionary psychologists and biologists (i.e., the costs of punishing are greater than the benefits) emerges in real life (cf. Guala, 2012). As a consequence of these considerations, I want to take an in-between step and emphasize first what can be inductively concluded from the present research’s findings and what can, from this theoretical basis, be deductively concluded for behavior in real life. Given the quantity of the appearances of social dilemmas in real life (van Lange et al., 2013) I will pick one incisive example to make my argument. This example relates to social ostracism, defined as the act of ignoring or excluding an individual from social interaction (Williams, 1997; Williams, Cheung, & Choi, 2000). Ostracism emerges in a variety of situations in real life (cf. Williams, 2007), for instance when it comes to bullying at school, when women are not allowed to join students’ fraternities, or when an obstructionist is excluded from a political party. Recently, Feinberg, Willer, and Schultz (in press; see also Feinberg et al., 2012) have argued that social ostracism reflects one form of punishment that leads to cooperation in social dilemma situations. In fact, these authors showed that punishing uncooperative group members using ostracism in a social dilemma situation leads to (a) increased cooperation on the collective level and (b) an increase in the cooperative behavior of ostracized individuals after being ostracized (i.e., the individual level). In real life, a student study group may face a social dilemma because individuals are best off when they do not contribute to the common group project but let the others do all the work. In such situations, free-riding group members may be ignored or even excluded from the group. In that way an uncooperative GENERAL DISCUSSION 91 individual is punished by the other group members. This behavior can also be framed as reactive aggression, given that the uncooperative individual is harmed in response to a provocation. In this regard, I do not directly claim that the punishment toward a freerider in a student study group is more likely to be executed by individuals possessing relative low (vs. high) cortisol levels, or more likely to be executed by strongly rather than weakly prevention-focused individuals, or less likely to be executed when individuals are in a state of reputational concern. Instead, I propose a theoretical step inbetween. Specifically, what can be inductively concluded is that cortisol negatively relates to the punishment of unfair and uncooperative group members which is likely impulsively executed. Moreover, strongly prevention-focused individuals are more likely than weakly prevention-focused individuals to engage in costly punishment, presumably because of their specific sensitivity to negative social information involving norm violations. Finally, in a state of reputational concern individuals engage less strongly in costly punishment, most likely because costly punishment may not be considered to be a reputation-increasing behavior. These considerations represent a theoretical framework for when and under which conditions individuals may engage in the punishment of uncooperative others. From this basis then one has to analyze whether social ostracism in a study group fits into the framework. This is questionable because ostracism in a study group may not reflect impulsive behavior but is deliberately debated in the group, and there may be a local social norm to ostracize (i.e., it is socially desirable to exclude an uncooperative group member). On the other hand it is possible that strongly preventionfocused individuals particularly react to this negative event which involves a norm violation. Thus, from this theoretical basis one can also come to different conclusions regarding how two variables are related in real life, for instance that cortisol levels must not be related to social ostracism in a study group. Nonetheless, the investigation of the main concepts of the present work in real life is an interesting approach when one has the aim of understanding these concepts as they apply in real life. For instance, how are cortisol levels related to the support of punishment of deviant behavior in the context of tax evasion? How is testosterone related to proactive aggression, for instance in football supporters? Does cortisol inhibit this relation? Can the analysis of reputational concerns in this context contribute to a better understanding GENERAL DISCUSSION 92 of proactive aggression, especially when varying the source of reputational concerns (e.g., security cameras, the police, or other supporters from one’s own team)? To conclude, what I wish to emphasize here is that deduction for real life needs to result from the rigorous analysis of a theoretical approach and the behavior of interest in real life. The present work can surely offer a theoretical framework in this regard. 4.6 The role of altruism in costly punishment In this section I will discuss the third issue under consideration, that is, the role of altruism in punishing uncooperative group members. I am not the first to discuss the question of whether costly punishment is an altruistic act, be it from a social psychological perspective or from the perspective of evolutionary psychology and biology (e.g., Clavien & Klein, 2010; Elster, 2007; Kurzban & DeScioli, 2013; Peacock, 2007; Sober & Wilson, 1998; West et al., 2011). The discussion, and the confusion, started with Fehr and Gächter (2002) terming costly punishment of uncooperative individuals “altruistic punishment.” The use of this term built on the notion that any behavior that is “costly and yields no pecuniary benefits” (Fehr & Gächter, 2002, p. 137) for the acting individual but benefits any other individual in any way reflects altruism. Fehr and Gächter (2002) wrote: “punishment may well benefit the future group members of a punished subject, if that subject responds to the punishment by raising investments in the following periods. In this sense, punishment is altruistic” (p. 137). Let us take a step back and reflect on what researchers in social psychology and evolutionary psychology and biology typically imply when they use the term “altruism”. From the perspective of social psychology, altruism reflects behavior with the ultimate goal of increasing the welfare of one or more other individuals (Batson et al., 2002). This conceptualization does not deny that behaving altruistically can benefit the altruistic individual. However, an altruistic act from the perspective of social psychology is that an individual’s ultimate motive is to increase the welfare of others. Benefits that are obtained (e.g., the relief of a negative state) reflect unintended consequences (cf. Batson et al., 2002). From the perspective of evolutionary psychology and biology, altruism reflects a behavior that directly benefits others at a cost to oneself whereas the actual GENERAL DISCUSSION 93 psychological motive of the behavior must not be “psychologically altruistic” (Kerr, Godfrey-Smith, & Feldman, 2004; Sober & Wilson, 1998). In other words, the basis of sociobiological altruism is that individual A benefits individual B and individual A bears the costs of doing so (Peacock, 2007; Sober & Wilson, 1998; West et al., 2011). Fehr and Gächter (2002) reduce the concept of altruism ad absurdum (cf. Peacock, 2007). The definition of altruism given by these authors involves the logic that individual A can be spiteful toward individual B which leads individual B to behave altruistically (from a sociobiological viewpoint) toward individual C. On this basis, Fehr and Gächter (2002) would claim that the spiteful act of individual A is altruistic although individual A has no direct influence or control over the benefit of individual C. One can illustrate the absurdity of this logic by claiming that if individual A kills individual B which benefits individual C (e.g., through inheriting the estate of deceased individual B), the killing of individual A would be altruistic in the sense dictated by Fehr and Gächter (2002) because individual A killing B benefits C (cf. Peacock, 2007). Accordingly, this conceptualization of altruism by Fehr and Gächter (2002) does not fit the common definition of altruism found in the field of evolutionary psychology and biology, given that the common definitions restrict altruism to the notion of individual A helping B. Individual C is not considered. Additionally, one can criticize the Fehr and Gächter (2002) definition of altruism because they neglect what evolutionary theorists often emphasize, that is, costs and benefits are calculated on the basis of the lifetime fitness consequences of a behavior (e.g., Hamilton, 1964; West et al., 2011). Fehr and Gächter (2002), however, calculate costs and benefits of a specific situation (i.e., the public goods game). So, it is possible that individuals engage in costly behavior that benefits some other individuals (e.g., through costly punishment), and Fehr and Gächter (2002) would conclude that this is altruism. However, when calculated on the basis of lifetime benefits, it could actually be that the costly behavior, in sum over a lifetime, leads to a reduced benefit for the actor (e.g., because costly punishment destroys a sense of community and individuals have less trust in others when costly punishment is possible; cf. Shinada et al., 2004). As such, GENERAL DISCUSSION 94 Fehr and Gächter (2002) do not distinguish between the classic rational choice approach (i.e., maximizing benefits in a specific situation) and evolutionary models (i.e., maximizing benefits in the long run; cf. West et al., 2011). When evaluating whether a behavior is altruistic in an evolutionary sense, one has to apply a lifetime cost-benefit analysis and not, as Fehr and Gächter (2002) did, a cost-benefit analysis of a specific situation (i.e., the public goods game). To conclude, the definition of altruism given by Fehr and Gächter (2002) is definitely not in line with the typical conceptualization of altruism in the field of evolutionary biology. There is still the possibility that costly punishment reflects altruism in a social psychological sense, that is, individuals costly punish uncooperative others with the ultimate prosocial motive of increasing the welfare of others with whom the punished individual will interact in future (possibly in a more cooperative manner). For instance, it could be the case that the observation of uncooperative behavior leads to anger which in turn elicits the motivation to reinstall justice and, accordingly, to help people (Haidt, 2003). Peacock (2007), however, rightly states in relation to this that “upholding justice carries no necessary intent to benefit others” (p. 14). Our own work (Pfattheicher et al., 2014, Appendix C) can contribute to this issue. The finding that prosocial behavior with prosocial motives is more likely shown when reputational concerns are activated (Nettle et al., 2013; Sparks & Barclay, 2013) whereas costly punishment was actually reduced in our experiments, does not bolster the notion that prosocial, altruistic motives drive costly punishment. Additionally, costly punishment of uncooperative individuals is considered to be driven by revenge (Gollwitzer & Bushman, 2012; de Quervain et al., 2004) and revenge includes the ultimate goal of harming another individual (McCullough, 2008), which contradicts an altruistic motivation. This is in line with our own work (Pfattheicher & Keller, in press, Appendix A) which conceptualizes costly punishment as reactive aggression and shows corresponding empirical findings. To sum up, it is unlikely that costly punishment of uncooperative individuals is driven by altruistic motives (although I do not want to completely exclude this motive for all individuals). The term “altruistic punishment” does not seem appropriate, be it from a GENERAL DISCUSSION 95 social psychological perspective or from the perspective of evolutionary psychology and biology and should, therefore, be avoided. A few last words: the present dissertation proposed that investigating cooperation and punishment in social dilemma situations and, more generally, corresponding concepts such as aggression, dominance, impulsivity, selfishness, status and fairness concerns, group orientations, and social norms is a worthwhile approach. In fact, the analysis of behavior in social dilemma situations offers fruitful possibilities to acquire knowledge about human behavior. The present dissertation represents the reaping of some of these fruits, but certainly not the end of the harvest. REFERENCES 96 References Adler, N. E., Epel, E. S., Castellazzo, G., & Ickovics, J. R. (2000). Relationship of subjective and objective social status with psychological and physiological functioning: Preliminary data in healthy white women. Health Psychology, 19, 586-592. Alink, L. R., van IJzendoorn, M. H., Bakermans-Kranenburg, M. J., Mesman, J., Juffer, F., & Koot, H. M. (2008). Cortisol and externalizing behavior in children and adolescents: Mixed meta-analytic evidence for the inverse relation of basal cortisol and cortisol reactivity with externalizing behavior. Developmental Psychobiology, 50, 427-450. Anderson, C. M., & Putterman, L. (2006). Do non-strategic sanctions obey the law of demand? The demand for punishment in the voluntary contribution mechanism. Games and Economic Behavior, 54, 1-24. Anderson, C. A., & Bushman, B. J. (2002). Human aggression. Annual Review of Psychology, 53, 27-51. Andreoni, J., & Bernheim, B. D. (2009). Social image and the 50-50 norm: A theoretical and experimental analysis of audience effects. Econometrica, 77, 1607-1636. Arch, J. J., & Craske, M. G. (2006). Mechanisms of mindfulness: Emotion regulation following a focused breathing induction. Behaviour Research and Therapy, 44, 1849-1858. Atkinson, J. W. (1957). Motivational determinants of risk-taking behavior. Psychological Review, 64, 359-372. Atkinson, J. W. (1964). An introduction of motivation. Princeton, NJ: van Nostrand. Aune, K. S. (1997). Self and partner perceptions of the appropriateness of emotions. Communication Reports, 10, 133-142. REFERENCES 97 Aune, K. S., Aune, R. K., & Buller, D. B. (1994). The experience, expression, and perceived appropriateness of emotions across levels of relationship development. The Journal of Social Psychology, 134, 141-150. Axelrod, R., & Hamilton, W. D. (1981). The evolution of cooperation. Science, 211, 1390-1396. Balleine, B. W., Delgado, M. R., & Hikosaka, O. (2007). The role of the dorsal striatum in reward and decision-making. The Journal of Neuroscience, 27, 8161-8165. Balliet, D., Mulder, L. B., & van Lange, P. A. (2011). Reward, punishment, and cooperation: A meta-analysis. Psychological Bulletin, 137, 594-615. Banny, A. M., Heilbron, N., Ames, A., & Prinstein, M. J. (2011). Relational benefits of relational aggression: Adaptive and maladaptive associations with adolescent friendship quality. Developmental Psychology, 47, 1153-1166. Barclay, P. (2006). Reputational benefits for altruistic punishment. Evolution and Human Behavior, 27, 325-344. Barclay, P. (2013). Strategies for cooperation in biological markets, especially for humans. Evolution and Human Behavior, 34, 164-175. Baron, R. M., & Kenny, D. A. (1986). The moderator-mediator variable distinction in social psychological research: Conceptual, strategic, and statistical considerations. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 51, 1173-1182. Bateson, M., Callow, L., Holmes, J. R., Redmond Roche, M. L., & Nettle, D. (2013). Do images of ‘watching eyes’ induce behaviour that is more pro-social or more normative? A field experiment on littering. PLOS ONE, 8, e82055. Bateson, M., Nettle, D., & Roberts, G. (2006). Cues of being watched enhance cooperation in a real-world setting. Biology Letters, 2, 412-414. REFERENCES 98 Batson, C. D., Ahmad, N., Powell, A. A., & Stocks, E. L. (2008). Prosocial motivation. In J. Y. Shah & W. L. Gardner (Eds.), The handbook of motivation science (pp. 135-149). New York: Guilford Press. Batson, C. D., Ahmad, N., & Tsang, J. A. (2002). Four motives for community involvement. Journal of Social Issues, 58, 429-445. Baumeister, R. F. (2002). Yielding to temptation: Self-control failure, impulsive purchasing, and consumer behavior. Journal of Consumer Research, 28, 670-676. Becker, G. S. (1976). The economic approach to human behavior. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Bendor, J., & Mookherjee, D. (1990). Norms, third-party sanctions, and cooperation. Journal of Law, Economics, & Organization, 6, 33-63. Ben-Shakhar, G., Bornstein, G., Hopfensitz, A., & van Winden, F. (2007). Reciprocity and emotions in bargaining using physiological and self-report measures. Journal of Economic Psychology, 28, 314-323. Berg, J., Dickhaut, J., & McCabe, K. (1995). Trust, reciprocity and social history. Games and Economic Behavior, 10, 122-142. Bernhard, H., Fischbacher, U., & Fehr, E. (2006). Parochial altruism in humans. Nature, 442, 912-915. Blair, C., Peters, R., & Granger, D. (2004). Physiological and neuropsychological correlates of approach/withdrawal tendencies in preschool: Further examination of the behavioral inhibition system/behavioral activation system scales for young children. Developmental Psychobiology, 45, 113-124. Bless, H., Fiedler, K., & Strack, F. (2004). Social cognition: How individuals construct social reality. Hove: Psychology Press. REFERENCES 99 Bliege Bird, R., Smith, E. A., & Bird, D. W. (2001). The hunting handicap: Costly signaling in human foraging strategies. Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology 50, 9-19. Binmore, K. G. (2005). Economic man-or straw man? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 28, 817-818. Binmore, K., & Shaked, A. (2010). Experimental economics: Where next? Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 73, 87-100. Böhnke, R., Bertsch, K., Kruk, M. R., & Naumann, E. (2010). The relationship between basal and acute HPA axis activity and aggressive behavior in adults. Journal of Neural Transmission, 117, 629-637. Böhnke, R., Bertsch, K., Kruk, M. R., Richter, S., & Naumann, E. (2010). Exogenous cortisol enhances aggressive behavior in females, but not in males. Psychoneuroendocrinology, 35, 1034-1044. Bolton, G. E., & Ockenfels, A. (2000). A theory of equity, reciprocity, and competition. American Economic Review, 90, 166-193. Bourdieu, P. (1979). Distinction: A social critique of the judgment of taste. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Bourrat, P., Baumard, N., & McKay, R. (2011). Surveillance cues enhance moral condemnation. Evolutionary Psychology, 9, 193-199. Bowles, S., & Gintis, H. (2003). Origins of human cooperation. In P. Hammerstein (Ed.), Genetic and cultural evolution of cooperation (pp. 429-443). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Boyd, R., & Richerson, P. J. (1992). Punishment allows the evolution of cooperation (or anything else) in sizable groups. Ethology and Sociobiology, 13, 171-195. REFERENCES 100 Brandstätter, H., & Königstein, M. (2001). Personality influences on ultimatum bargaining decisions. European Journal of Personality, 15, 53-70. Bromberg-Martin, E. S., Matsumoto, M., & Hikosaka, O. (2010). Dopamine in motivational control: Rewarding, aversive, and alerting. Neuron, 68, 815-834. Brown, L. L., Tomarken, A. J., Orth, D. N., Loosen, P. T., Kalin, N. H., & Davidson, R. J. (1996). Individual differences in repressive-defensiveness predict basal salivary cortisol levels. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 70, 362-371. Brüne, M., Juckel, G., & Enzi, B. (2013). “An eye for an eye”? Neural correlates of retribution and forgiveness. PLOS ONE, 8, e73519. Brüne, M., Scheele, D., Heinisch, C., Tas, C., Wischniewski, J., & Güntürkün, O. (2012). Empathy moderates the effect of repetitive transcranial magnetic stimulation of the right dorsolateral prefrontal cortex on costly punishment. PLOS ONE, 7, e44747. Bruner, J. S., & Goodman, C. C. (1947). Value and need as organizing factors in perception. The Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 42, 33-44. Bullock, J. G., Green, D. P., & Ha, S. E. (2010). Yes, but what’s the mechanism? (Don’t expect an easy answer). Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 98, 550558. Burnham, T. C. (2007). High-testosterone men reject low ultimatum game offers. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 274, 2327-2330. Burnham, T. C., & Hare, B. (2007). Engineering human cooperation. Human Nature, 18, 88-108. Bushman, B. J., & Anderson, C. A. (2002). Violent video games and hostile expectations: A test of the General Aggression Model. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 28, 1679-1686. REFERENCES 101 Bushman, B. J., & Huesmann, L. R. (2010). Aggression. In S. T. Fiske, D. T. Gilbert & G. Lindzey (Eds.), Handbook of social psychology (5th ed., pp. 833-863). New York: John Wiley & Sons. Buss, A. H. (1961). The psychology of aggression. New York: Wiley. Caldwell, M. D. (1976). Communication and sex effects in a five-person Prisoner’s Dilemma Game. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 33, 273-280. Calogero, A. E., Gallucci, W. T., Gold, P. W., & Chrousos, G. P. (1988). Multiple feedback regulatory loops upon rat hypothalamic corticotropin-releasing hormone secretion. Potential clinical implications. Journal of Clinical Investigation, 82, 767-774. Camerer, C. F. (2003). Behavioral game theory: Experiments in strategic interaction. New York: Russell Sage Foundation. Camerer, C. F., & Fehr, E. (2004). Measuring social norms and preferences using experimental games: A guide for social scientists. In J. Henrich, R. Boyd, S. Bowles, C. Camerer, E. Fehr & H. Gintis (Eds.), Foundations of human sociality (pp. 55-95). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Caporael, L. R., Dawes, R. M., Orbell, J. M., & van de Kragt, A. J. (1989). Selfishness examined: Cooperation in the absence of egoistic incentives. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 12, 683-739. Cappelletti, D., Goth, W., & Ploner, M. (2011). Being of two minds: Ultimatum offers under cognitive constraints. Journal of Economic Psychology, 32, 940-950. Carbon, C., & Hesslinger, V. M. (2011). Bateson et al.’s (2006) cues-of-being-watched paradigm revisited. Swiss Journal of Psychology, 70, 203-210. Carlsmith, K. M., & Darley, J. M. (2008). Psychological aspects of retributive justice. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 40, 193-236. REFERENCES 102 Carlsmith, K. M., Wilson, T. D., & Gilbert, D. T. (2008). The paradoxical consequences of revenge. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 95, 1316-1324. Carlsmith, K. M., Darley, J. M., & Robinson, P. H. (2002). Why do we punish? Deterrence and just deserts as motives for punishment. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 83, 284-299. Carré, J. M., & Mehta, P. H. (2011). Importance of considering testosterone-cortisol interactions in predicting human aggression and dominance. Aggressive Behavior, 37, 1-3. Carré, J. M., Putnam, S. K., & McCormick, C. M. (2009). Testosterone responses to competition predict future aggressive behaviour at a cost to reward in men. Psychoneuroendocrinology, 34, 561-570. Carver, C. S. (2006). Approach, avoidance, and the self-regulation of affect and action. Motivation and Emotion, 30, 105-110. Carver, C. S., Lawrence, J. W., & Scheier, M. F. (1999). Self-discrepancies and affect: Incorporating the role of feared selves. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 25, 783-792. Carver, C. S., & Scheier, M. F. (1981). Attention and self-regulation: A control-theory approach to human behavior. New York: Springer. Carver, C. S., & Scheier, M. F. (1990). Origins and functions of positive and negative affect: A control-process view. Psychological Review, 97, 19-35. Carver, C. S., & Scheier, M. F. (2011). Self regulation of action and affect. In K. D. Vohs & R. F. Baumeister (Eds.), Handbook of self-regulation: Research, theory, and application (pp. 3-21). New York: Guilford Press. REFERENCES 103 Carver, C., & White, T. (1994). Behavioral inhibition, behavioral activation, and affective responses to impending reward and punishment: The BIS/BAS scales. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 67, 319-333. Castrogiovanni, P., Capone, M. R., Maremmani, I., & Marazziti, D. (1994). Platelet serotonergic markers and aggressive behaviour in healthy subjects. Neuropsychobiology, 29, 105-107. Cheng, J. T., Tracy, J. L., Foulsham, T., Kingstone, A., & Henrich, J. (2013). Two ways to the top: Evidence that dominance and prestige are distinct yet viable avenues to social rank and influence. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 104, 103125. Clavien, C., & Klein, R. A. (2010). Eager for fairness or for revenge? Psychological altruism in economics. Economics and Philosophy, 26, 267-290. Cialdini, R. B., Reno, R. R., & Kallgren, C. A. (1990). A focus theory of normative conduct: Recycling the concept of norms to reduce littering in public places. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 58, 1015-2026. Cohrs, J. C. (2013). Threat and authoritarianism: Some theoretical and methodological comments. International Journal of Psychology, 48, 50-54. Corr, P. J. (2009). The reinforcement sensitivity theory of personality. In P. J. Corr & G. Matthews (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of personality psychology (pp. 347376). Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press. Crick, N. R., & Dodge, K. A. (1996). Social information‐processing mechanisms in reactive and proactive aggression. Child Development, 67, 993-1002. Critchley, H. D., Elliott, R., Mathias, C. J., & Dolan, R. J. (2000). Neural activity relating to generation and representation of galvanic skin conductance responses: A functional magnetic resonance imaging study. The Journal of Neuroscience, 20, 3033-3040. REFERENCES 104 Crockett, M. J. (2009). The neurochemistry of fairness: Clarifying the link between serotonin and prosocial behavior. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 1167, 76-86. Crockett, M. J., Clark, L., Lieberman, M. D., Tabibnia, G., & Robbins, T. W. (2010). Impulsive choice and altruistic punishment are correlated and increase in tandem with serotonin depletion. Emotion, 10, 855-862. Crowe, E., & Higgins, E. T. (1997). Regulatory focus and strategic inclinations: Promotion and prevention in decision-making. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 69, 117-132. Crowne, D. P., & Marlowe, D. (1960). A new scale of social desirability independent of psychopathology. Journal of Consulting Psychology, 24, 349-354. Cubitt, R. P., Drouvelis, M., Gächter, S., & Kabalin, R. (2011). Moral judgments in social dilemmas: How bad is free riding? Journal of Public Economics, 95, 253264. Cumming, D. C., Quigley, M. E., & Yen, S. S. C. (1983). Acute suppression of circulating testosterone levels by cortisol in men. Journal of Clinical Endocrinology & Metabolism, 57, 671-673. d’Arms, J., & Jacobson, D. (2000). The moralistic fallacy: On the ‘appropriateness’ of emotions. Philosophical and Phenomenological Research, 61, 65-90. Dawes, C. T., Fowler, J. H., Johnson, T., McElreath, R., & Smirnov, O. (2007). Egalitarian motives in humans. Nature, 446, 794-796. Dawes, R. M. (1980). Social dilemmas. Annual Review of Psychology, 31, 169-193. Delgado, M. R., Li, J., Schiller, D., & Phelps, E. A. (2008). The role of the striatum in aversive learning and aversive prediction errors. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 363, 3787-3800. REFERENCES 105 Denson, T. F., Pedersen, W. C., Ronquillo, J., & Nandy, A. S. (2009). The angry brain: Neural correlates of anger, angry rumination, and aggressive personality. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 21, 734-744. de Quervain, D. J.-F., Fischbacher, U., Treyer, V., Schellhammer, M., Schnyder, U., Buck, A., & Fehr, E. (2004). The neural basis of altruistic punishment. Science 305, 1254-1258. Denson, T. F., von Hippel, W., Kemp, R. I., & Teo, L. S. (2010). Glucose consumption decreases impulsive aggression in response to provocation in aggressive individuals. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 46, 1023-1028. DeWall, C. N., Anderson, C. A., & Bushman, B. J. (2011). The General Aggression Model: Theoretical extensions to violence. Psychology of Violence, 1, 245-258. DeWall, C. N., Baumeister, R. F., Gailliot, M. T., & Maner, J. K. (2008). Depletion makes the heart grow less helpful: Helping as a function of self-regulatory energy and genetic relatedness. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 34, 16531662. DeWall, C. N., Baumeister, R. F., Stillman, T. F., & Gailliot, M. T. (2007). Violence restrained: Effects of self-regulation and its depletion on aggression. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 43, 62-76. Dickerson, S. S., & Kemeny, M. E. (2004). Acute stressors and cortisol responses: A theoretical integration and synthesis of laboratory research. Psychological Bulletin, 130, 355-391. Diekmann, A. (2009). Spieltheorie: Einführung, Beispiele, Experimente [Game theory: Introduction, examples, experiments]. Hamburg: Rowohlt. Diener, E. (1976). Effects of prior destructive behavior, anonymity, and group presence on deindividuation and aggression. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 33, 497-507. REFERENCES 106 Diener, E., Fraser, S. C., Beaman, A. L., & Kelem, R. T. (1976). Effects of deindividuation variables on stealing among Halloween trick-or-treaters. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 33, 178-183. Diener, E., Lusk, R., DeFour, D., & Flax, R. (1980). Deindividuation: Effects of group size, density, number of observers, and group member similarity on selfconsciousness and disinhibited behavior. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 39, 449-459. Dos Santos, M., Rankin, D. J., & Wedekind, C. (2011). The evolution of punishment through reputation. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 278, 371-377. Dreber, A., & Rand, D. G. (2012). Retaliation and antisocial punishment are overlooked in many theoretical models as well as behavioral experiments. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 35, 24-24. Egas, M., & Riedl, A. (2005). The economics of altruistic punishment and the demise of cooperation (Working Paper). Amsterdam: Tinbergen Institute. Eisenegger, C., Haushofer, J., & Fehr, E. (2011). The role of testosterone in social interaction. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 15, 263-271. Eisenegger, C., Naef, M., Snozzi, R., Heinrichs, M., & Fehr, E. (2010). Prejudice and truth about the effect of testosterone on human bargaining behaviour. Nature, 463, 356-359. Ekström, M. (2011). Do watching eyes affect charitable giving? Evidence from a field experiment. Experimental Economics, 15, 530-546. Elliot, A. J. (1999). Approach and avoidance motivation and achievement goals. Educational Psychologist, 34, 169-189. REFERENCES 107 Elliot, A. J., & McGregor, H. A. (1999). Test anxiety and the hierarchical model of approach and avoidance achievement motivation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 76, 628-644. Elliot, A. J., & McGregor, H. A. (2001). A 2 × 2 achievement goal framework. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 80, 501-519. Elliott, E. S., & Dweck, C. S. (1988). Goals: An approach to motivation and achievement. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 54, 5-12. Elster, J. (2007). Explaining social behavior. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press. Emanuele, E., Brondino, N., Bertona, M., Re, S., & Geroldi, D. (2008). Relationship between platelet serotonin content and rejections of unfair offers in the ultimatum game. Neuroscience Letters, 437, 158-161. Emler, N. (1990). A social psychology of reputation. European Review of Social Psychology, 1, 171-193. Ernest-Jones, M., Nettle, D., & Bateson, M. (2010). Effects of eye images on everyday cooperative behavior: A field experiment. Evolution and Human Behavior, 32, 172-178. Esser, H. (2000). Soziologie. Soziales Handeln [Sociology. Social action] (3rd ed.). Frankfurt am Main: Campus. Eysenck, H. J. (1970). The biological basis of personality. Springfield, IL: Charles C. Thomas Publisher Ltd. Fazio, R. H. (1990). The MODE model as an integrative framework. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 23, 75-109. Fehr, E., & Fischbacher, U. (2003). The nature of human altruism. Nature, 425, 785-791. REFERENCES 108 Fehr, E., & Fischbacher, U. (2004). Social norms and human cooperation. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8, 185-190. Fehr, E., & Gächter, S. (2002). Altruistic punishment in humans. Nature, 415, 137-140. Fehr, E., & Rockenbach, B. (2003). Detrimental effects of sanctions on human altruism. Nature, 422, 137-140. Fehr, E., & Schmidt, K. M. (1999). A theory of fairness, competition, and cooperation. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 114, 817-868. Fehr, E., & Schneider, F. (2010). Eyes are on us, but nobody cares: Are eye cues relevant for strong reciprocity? Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 277, 1315-1323. Feilhauer, J., Cima, M., Korebrits, A., & Nicholson, N. A. (2013). Salivary cortisol and psychopathy dimensions in detained antisocial adolescents. Psychoneuroendocrinology, 38, 1586-1595. Feinberg, M., Cheng, J. T., & Willer, R. (2012). Gossip as an effective and low-cost form of punishment. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 35, 25-25. Feinberg, M., Willer, R., & Schultz, M. (in press). Gossip and ostracism promote cooperation in groups. Psychological Science. Fenigstein, A., Scheier, M., & Buss, A. (1975). Public and private self-consciousness: Assessment and theory. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology, 43, 522527. Fenigstein, A., & Vanable, P. A. (1992). Paranoia and self-consciousness. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 62, 129-138. Festinger, L., Pepitone, A., & Newcomb, T. (1952). Some consequences of deindividuation in a group. The Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 47, 382-389. REFERENCES 109 Fetchenhauer, D., & Huang, X. (2004). Justice sensitivity and distributive decisions in experimental games. Personality and Individual Differences, 36, 1015-1029. Fiedler, K., Schott, M., & Meiser, T. (2011). What mediation analysis can (not) do. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 47, 1231-1236. Fischbacher, U. (2007). z-Tree: Zurich toolbox for ready-made economic experiments. Experimental Economics, 10, 171-178. Fischer, P., Krueger, J., Greitemeyer, T., Kastenmüller, A., Vogrincic, C., Frey, D., … & Kainbacher, M. (2011). The bystander-effect: A meta-analytic review on bystander intervention in dangerous and non-dangerous emergencies. Psychological Bulletin, 137, 517-537. Fishbein, A. P., & Ajzen, I. (1975). Belief, attitude, intention, and behavior: An introduction to theory and research. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley. Fowler, J. H., Johnson, T., & Smirnov, O. (2005). Egalitarian motive and altruistic punishment. Nature, 433, E1-E2. Fox, J., & Guyer, M. (1978). “Public” choice and cooperation in n-person Prisoner’s Dilemma. Journal of Conflict Resolution, 22, 469-481. Francey, D., & Bergmüller, R. (2012). Images of eyes enhance investments in a real-life public good. PLOS ONE, 7, e37397. Friedman, R. S., & Förster, J. (2001). The effects of promotion and prevention cues on creativity. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 81, 1001-1013. Frijda, N. H. (1994). The lex talionis: On vengeance. In S. H. M. van Goozen, N. E. van der Poll & J. A. Sergeant (Eds.), Emotions: Essays on emotion theory (pp. 263289). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum. REFERENCES 110 Froming, W. J., Walker, G. R., & Lopyan, K. J. (1982). Public and private selfawareness: When personal attitudes conflict with societal expectations. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 18, 476-487. Gable, S. L., Reis, H. T., & Elliot, A. J. (2000). Behavioral activation and inhibition in everyday life. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 78, 1135-1149. Gächter, S., & Herrmann, B. (2009). Reciprocity, culture and human cooperation: Previous insights and a new cross-cultural experiment. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 364, 791-806. Garcia, S. M., Weaver, K., Moskowitz, G. B., & Darley, J. M. (2002). Crowded minds: The implicit bystander effect. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 83, 843-853. Gawronski, B., & Bodenhausen, G. V. (2006). Associative and propositional processes in evaluation: An integrative review of implicit and explicit attitude change. Psychological Bulletin, 132, 692-731. Gawronski, B., & Bodenhausen, G. V. (2007). Unraveling the processes underlying evaluation: Attitudes from the perspective of the APE model. Social Cognition, 25, 687-717. Gervais, W., & Norenzayan, A. (2012). Like a camera in the sky? Thinking about God increases public self-awareness and socially desirable responding. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 48, 298-302. Gilovich, T., Kruger, J., & Medvec, V. H. (2002). The spotlight effect revisited: Overestimating the manifest variability of our actions and appearance. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 38, 93-99. Gilovich, T., Medvec, V., & Savitsky, K. (2000). The spotlight effect in social judgment: An egocentric bias in estimates of the salience of one’s own actions and appearance. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 78, 211-222. REFERENCES 111 Goette, L., Huffman, D., Meier, S., & Sutter, M. (2012). Competition between organizational groups: Its impact on altruistic and anti-social motivations. Management Science, 58, 948-960. Gollwitzer, M., & Bushman, B. J. (2012). Do victims of injustice punish to improve their mood? Social Psychological and Personality Science, 3, 572-580. Govern, J., & Marsch, L. (2001). Development and validation of the situational SelfAwareness Scale. Consciousness and Cognition, 10, 366-378. Grafen, A. (1990). Biological signals as handicaps. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 144, 517-546. Gray J. A. (1970). The psychophysiological basis of introversion-extraversion. Behavior Research and Therapy, 8, 249-266. Gray, J. A. (1982). The neuropsychology of anxiety: An enquiry into the functions of the septo-hippocampal system. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Grier, R. A., Warm, J. S., Dember, W. N., Matthews, G., Galinsky, T. L., Szalma, J. L., & Parasuraman, R. (2003). The vigilance decrement reflects limitations in effortful attention, not mindlessness. The Journal of the Human Factors and Ergonomics Society, 45, 349-359. Griskevicius, V., Tybur, J. M., & Den Bergh, B. V. (2010). Going green to be seen: Status, reputation, and conspicuous conservation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 98, 392-404. Griskevicius, V., Tybur, J. M., Gangestad, S. W., Perea, E. F., Shapiro, J. R., & Kenrick, D. T. (2009). Aggress to impress: Hostility as an evolved context-dependent strategy. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 96, 980-994. Guala, F. (2012). Reciprocity: Weak or strong? What punishment experiments do (and do not) demonstrate. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 35, 1-59. REFERENCES 112 Guney, S., & Newell, B. R. (2013). Fairness overrides reputation: The importance of fairness norms in altruistic cooperation. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 7, 1-12. Gürerk, Ö., Irlenbusch, B., & Rockenbach, B. (2006). The competitive advantage of sanctioning institutions. Science, 312, 108-111. Güth, W., Schmittberger, R., & Schwarze, B. (1982). An experimental analysis of ultimatum bargaining. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 3, 367388. Hagen, E. H., & Hammerstein, P. (2006). Game theory and human evolution: A critique of some recent interpretations of experimental games. Theoretical Population Biology, 69, 339-348. Haidt, J. (2003). The moral emotions. In R. J. Davidson, K. R. Scherer & H. H. Goldsmith (Eds.), Handbook of affective sciences (pp. 852-870). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Haidt, J., & Kesebir, S. (2010). Morality. In S. Fiske, D. Gilbert & G. Lindzey (Eds.), Handbook of social psychology (pp. 797-832), Hobeken, NJ: Wiley. Halali, E., Bereby-Meyer, Y., & Meiran, N. (in press). Between self-interest and reciprocity: The social bright side of self-control failure. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General. Haley, K. J., & Fessler, D. M. T. (2005). Nobody’s watching? Subtle cues affect generosity in an anonymous economic game. Evolution and Human Behavior, 26, 245-256. Halevy, N., Chou, E. Y., & Murnighan, J. K. (2011). Games groups play: Mental models in intergroup conflict and negotiation. Research on Managing Groups and Teams, 14, 79-107. REFERENCES 113 Halevy, N., Chou, E. Y., & Murnighan, J. K. (2012). Mind games: The mental representation of conflict. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 102, 132148. Hamilton, W. D. (1964). The genetical evolution of social behaviour. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 7, 17-52. Hamilton, W. D., & Zuk, M. (1982). Heritable true fitness and bright birds: A role for parasites? Science, 218, 384-387. Hansen, J., Kharecha, P., Sato, M., Masson-Delmotte, V., Ackerman, F., Beerling, D. J., ... & Zachos, J. C. (2013). Assessing “dangerous climate change”: Required reduction of carbon emissions to protect young people, future generations and nature. PLOS ONE, 8, e81648. Hardin, G. (1968). The tragedy of the commons. Science, 162, 1243-1248. Hawley, P. H., & Vaughn, B. E. (2003). Aggression and adaptive functioning: The bright side to bad behavior. Merrill-Palmer Quarterly, 49, 239-242. Hayes, A. F. (2013). Introduction to mediation, moderation, and conditional process analysis. New York: The Guilford Press. Henrich, J., McElreath, R., Barr, A., Ensminger, J., Barrett, C., Bolyanatz, … & Ziker, J. (2006). Costly punishment across human societies. Science, 312, 1767-1770. Hessing, D. J., Elffers, H., Robben, H. S. J., & Webley, P. (1993). Needy or greedy? The social psychology of individuals who fraudulently claim unemployment benefits. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 23, 226-243. Herrmann, B., Thöni, C., & Gächter, S. (2008). Antisocial punishment across societies. Science, 319, 1362-1367. Higgins, E. T. (1997). Beyond pleasure and pain. American Psychologist, 52, 1280-1300. REFERENCES 114 Higgins, E. T. (1998). Promotion and prevention: Regulatory focus as a motivational principle. In M. P. Zanna (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (pp. 1-46). San Diego, CA: Academic Press. Higgins, E. T. (2012a). Beyond pleasure and pain: How motivation works. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Higgins, E. T. (2012b). Regulatory focus theory. In P. A. van Lange, A. W. Kruglanski & E. T. Higgins (Eds.), Handbook of theories of social psychology (Vol. 1, pp. 483-504). London: Sage Publications. Higgins, E. T., Friedman, R., Harlow, R., Idson, L., Ayduk, O., & Taylor, A. (2001). Achievement orientations from subjective histories of success: Promotion pride versus prevention pride. European Journal of Social Psychology, 31, 3-23. Hilbe, C., & Traulsen, A. (2012). Emergence of responsible sanctions without second order free riders, antisocial punishment or spite. Scientific Reports, 2, 458-458. Hilbig, B. E., Zettler, I., & Heydasch, T. (2012). Personality, punishment and public goods: Strategic shifts towards cooperation as a matter of dispositional honestyhumility. European Journal of Personality, 26, 245-254. Hilton, N. Z., Harris, G. T., & Rice, M. E. (2000). The functions of aggression by male teenagers. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 79, 988-994. Hirsh, J. B., & Peterson, J. B. (2009). Extraversion, neuroticism, and the prisoner’s dilemma. Personality and Individual Differences, 46, 254-256. Hoffman, E., McCabe, K., & Smith, V. L. (1996). Social distance and other-regarding behavior in dictator games. The American Economic Review, 86, 653-660. Horne, C. (2001). The enforcement of norms: Group cohesion and meta-norms. Social Psychology Quarterly, 64, 253-266. REFERENCES 115 Hubbard, J. A., Dodge, K. A., Cillessen, A. H., Coie, J. D., & Schwartz, D. (2001). The dyadic nature of social information processing in boys’ reactive and proactive aggression. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 80, 268-280. Hull, C. L. (1943). Principles of behavior. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts. Hull, C. L. (1952). A behavior system: An introduction to behavior theory concerning the individual organism. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Isaac, R. M., & Walker, J. M. (1988). Communication and free‐riding behavior: The voluntary contribution mechanism. Economic Inquiry, 26, 585-608. Irwin, K., & Berigan, N. (2013). Trust, culture, and cooperation: A social dilemma analysis of pro‐environmental behaviors. The Sociological Quarterly, 54, 424-449. Izuma, K. (2012). The social neuroscience of reputation. Neuroscience Research, 72, 283-288. Jacoby, J., & Sassenberg, K. (2011). Interactions do not only tell us when, but can also tell us how: Testing process hypotheses by interaction. European Journal of Social Psychology, 41, 180-190. Jerdee, T. H., & Rosen, B. (1974). Effects of opportunity to communicate and visibility of individual decisions on behavior in the common interest. Journal of Applied Psychology, 59, 712-716. Jones, E. E., & Harris, V. A. (1967). The attribution of attitudes. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 3, 1-24. Josephs, R. A., Sellers, J. G., Newman, M. L., & Mehta, P. H. (2006). The mismatch effect: When testosterone and status are at odds. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 90, 999-1013. Kahneman, D., Knetsch, J. L., & Thaler, R. H. (1991). Anomalies: The endowment effect, loss aversion, and status quo bias. The Journal of Economic Perspectives, 5, 193-206. REFERENCES 116 Kavoussi, R., Armstead, P., & Coccaro, E. (1997). The neurobiology of impulsive aggression. Psychiatric Clinics of North America, 20, 395-403. Keller, J., & Pfattheicher, S. (2011). Vigilant self-regulation, cues of being watched and cooperativeness. European Journal of Personality, 25, 363-372. Keller, J., & Pfattheicher, S. (in press). The Compassion-Hostility-Paradox: The interplay of vigilant, prevention-focused self-regulation, compassion and hostility. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin. Kelley, H. H., & Grzelak, J. (1972). Conflict between individual and common interest in an n-person relationship. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 21, 190197. Kerr, B., Godfrey-Smith, P., & Feldman, M. W. (2004). What is altruism? Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 19, 135-140. Kerr, N. L., & Kaufman-Gilliland, C. M. (1994). Communication, commitment, and cooperation in social dilemma. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 66, 513-529. Kessler, T., & Cohrs, J. C. (2008). The evolution of authoritarian processes: Fostering cooperation in large-scale groups. Group Dynamics: Theory, Research, and Practice, 12, 73-84. Khalfa, S., Isabelle, P., Jean-Pierre, B., & Manon, R. (2002). Event-related skin conductance responses to musical emotions in humans. Neuroscience Letters, 328, 145-149. Kirschbaum, C., & Hellhammer, psychoneuroendocrine research: D. H. Recent Psychoneuroendocrinology, 19, 313-333. (1994). Salivary developments and cortisol in applications. REFERENCES 117 Kirschbaum, C., Pirke, K. M., & Hellhammer, D. H. (1993). The ‘Trier Social Stress Test’- A tool for investigating psychobiological stress responses in a laboratory setting. Neuropsychobiology, 28, 76-81. Klimesch, W. (1999). EEG alpha and theta oscillations reflect cognitive and memory performance: A review and analysis. Brain Research Reviews, 29, 169-195. Klinesmith, J., Kasser, T., & McAndrew, F. T. (2006). Guns, testosterone, and aggression: An experimental test of a mediational hypothesis. Psychological Science, 17, 568-571. Knetsch, J. L. (1989). The endowment effect and evidence of nonreversible indifference curves. The American Economic Review, 79, 1277-1284. Knobe, J., & Malle, B. F. (2002). Self and other in the explanation of behavior: 30 years later. Psychologica Belgica, 42, 113-130. Knoch, D., & Fehr, E. (2007). Resisting the power of temptations. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 1104, 123-134. Knoch, D., Gianotti, L. R., Baumgartner, T., & Fehr, E. (2010). A neural marker of costly punishment behavior. Psychological Science, 21, 337-342. Knoch, D., Pascual-Leone, A., Meyer, K., Treyer, V., & Fehr, E. (2006). Diminishing reciprocal fairness by disrupting the right prefrontal cortex. Science, 314, 829-832. Knutson, B. (2004). Sweet revenge. Science, 305, 1246-1247. Kollock, P. (1998). Social dilemmas: The anatomy of cooperation. Annual Review of Sociology, 24, 183-214. Krakowski, M. (2003). Violence and serotonin: Influence of impulse control, affect regulation, and social functioning. The Journal of Neuropsychiatry and Clinical Neurosciences, 15, 294-305. REFERENCES 118 Kroneberg, C., & Kalter, F. (2012). Rational choice theory and empirical research: Methodological and theoretical contributions in Europe. Annual Review of Sociology, 38, 73-92. Kruglanski, A. W., Shah, J. Y., Fishbach, A., Friedman, R., Chun, W. Y., & SleethKeppler, D. (2002). A theory of goal systems. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 34, 331-378. Kruk, M. R., Halasz, J., Meelis, W., & Haller, J. (2004). Fast positive feedback between the adrenocortical stress response and a brain mechanism involved in aggressive behavior. Behavioral Neuroscience, 118, 1062-1070. Kuhl, J., & Kazén, M. (1997). Persönlichkeits-Stil- und Störungs-Inventar (PSSI) [Personality styles and dysfunction inventory]. Göttingen: Hogrefe. Kuhlmann, S., & Wolf, O. T. (2006). A non-arousing test situation abolishes the impairing effects of cortisol on delayed memory retrieval in healthy women. Neuroscience Letters, 399, 268-272. Kurzban, R., & DeScioli, P. (2013). Adaptationist punishment in humans. Journal of Bioeconomics, 15, 269-279. Kurzban, R., & Houser, D. (2001). Individual differences in cooperation in a circular public goods game. European Journal of Personality, 15, 38-52. Kurzban, R., DeScioloi, P., & O’Brien, E. (2007). Audience effects on moralistic punishment. Evolution and Human Behavior, 28, 75-84. Krause, N. (2011). Neighborhood conditions and helping behavior in late life. Journal of Environmental Psychology, 31, 62-69. Lamba, S., & Mace, R. (2011). Demography and ecology drive variation in cooperation across human populations. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 108, 14426-14430. REFERENCES 119 Latané, B., & Nida, S. (1981). 10 Years of research on group-size and helping. Psychological Bulletin, 89, 308-324. Leary, M. R. (1995). Self-presentation: Impression management and interpersonal behavior. New York: Brown & Benchmark Publishers. Leary, M. R., & Kowalski, R. M. (1990). Impression management: A literature review and two-component model. Psychological Bulletin, 107, 34-47. Lewin, K. (1943). Forces behind food habits and methods of change. Bulletin of the National Resources Council, 108, 35-65. MacKinnon, D. P., Krull, J. L., & Lockwood, C. M. (2000). Equivalence of the mediation, confounding and suppression effect. Prevention Science, 1, 173-181. Malle, B. F. (1999). How people explain behavior: A new theoretical framework. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 3, 21-43. Malle, B. F. (2006). The actor-observer asymmetry in attribution: A (surprising) metaanalysis. Psychological Bulletin, 132, 895-919. Malle, B. F., & Knobe, J. (1997). The folk concept of intentionality. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 33, 101-121. Malle, B. F., & Knobe, J. (2001). The distinction between desire and intention: A folkconceptual analysis. In B. F. Malle, L. J. Moses & D. A. Baldwin (Eds.), Intentions and intentionality: Foundations of social cognition (pp. 45-67). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Malle, B. F., Knobe, J. M., & Nelson, S. E. (2007). Actor-observer asymmetries in explanations of behavior: New answers to an old question. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 93, 491-514. Markus, H. R., & Kitayama, S. (1991). Culture and the self: Implications for cognition, emotion, and motivation. Psychological Review, 98, 224-253. REFERENCES 120 Marlowe, F. W., Berbesque, J. C., Barr, A., Barrett, C., Bolyanatz, A., Cardenas, J. C., … & Tracer, D.(2008). More ‘altruistic’ punishment in larger societies. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 275, 587-592. Marx, K. (1847/2009). Das Elend der Philosophie [The poverty of philosophy]. Zittau: Bernd Müller Verlag. Matthews, B. A., & Norris, F. H. (2002). When is believing “seeing”? Hostile attribution bias as a function of self-reported aggression. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 32, 1-31. Mazur, A., & Booth, A. (1998). Testosterone and dominance in men. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 21, 353-397. McClelland, D. C., Atkinson, J. W., Clark, R. A., & Lowell, E. L. (1953). The achievement motive. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts. McCullough, M. (2008). Beyond revenge. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass. Mehta, P. H., & Beer, J. (2010). Neural mechanisms of the testosterone-aggression relation: The role of orbitofrontal cortex. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 22, 2357-2368. Mehta, P. H., Jones, A. C., & Josephs, R. A. (2008). The social endocrinology of dominance: Basal testosterone predicts cortisol changes and behavior following victory and defeat. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 94, 1078-1093. Mehta, P. H., & Josephs, R. A. (2010). Testosterone and cortisol jointly regulate dominance: Evidence for a dual-hormone hypothesis. Hormones and Behavior, 58, 898-906. Merton, R. K. (1968). Social theory and social structure. Glencoe, IL: Free Press. Mifune, N., Hashimoto, H., & Yamagishi, T. (2010). Altruism toward in-group members as a reputation mechanism. Evolution and Human Behavior, 31, 109-117. REFERENCES 121 Milinski, M., Semmann, D., & Krambeck, H. (2002). Reputation helps solve the tragedy of the commons. Nature, 415, 424-426. Milinski, M., Semmann, D., Krambeck, H., & Marotzke, J. (2006). Stabilizing the earth’s climate is not a losing game: Supporting evidence from public goods experiments. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 103, 3994-3998. Miller, E. K., & Cohen, J. D. (2001). An integrative theory of prefrontal cortex function. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 24, 167-202. Mischel, W. (1961). Delay of gratification, need for achievement and acquiescence in another culture. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 62, 543-552. Mischel, W. (2012). Self-control theory. In P. A. van Lange, A. W. Kruglanski & E. T. Higgins (Eds.), Handbook of theories of social psychology (Vol. 2, pp. 1-22). London: Sage Publications. Molden, D. C., Lee, A. Y., & Higgins, E. T. (2008). Motivations for promotion and prevention. In J. Y. Shah & W. L. Gardner (Eds.), Handbook of motivation science (pp. 169-187). New York: Guilford Press. Moller, A. C., Elliot, A. J. (2006). The 2 × 2 achievement goal framework: An overview of empirical research. In A. V. Mittel (Ed.), Focus on educational psychology (pp. 307-326). Hauppauge, NY: Nova Science Publishers. Montoya, E. R., Terburg, D., Bos, P. A., & van Honk, J. (2012). Testosterone, cortisol, and serotonin as key regulators of social aggression: A review and theoretical perspective. Motivation and Emotion, 36, 65-73. Mook, D. G. (1983). In defense of external invalidity. American Psychologist, 38, 379387. Nash, J. F. (1950). Equilibrium points in n-person games. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 36, 48-49. REFERENCES 122 Nava, F., Caldiroli, E., Premi, S., & Lucchini, A. (2006). Relationship between plasma cortisol levels, withdrawal symptoms and craving in abstinent and treated heroin addicts. Journal of Addictive Diseases, 25, 9-16. Nelissen, R. M. (2008). The price you pay: Cost-dependent reputation effects of altruistic punishment. Evolution and Human Behavior, 29, 242-248. Nettle, D., Harper, Z., Kidson, A., Stone, R., Penton-Voak, I. S., & Bateson, M. (2013). The watching eyes effect in the Dictator Game: It’s not how much you give, it’s being seen to give something. Evolution and Human Behavior, 43, 35-40. Nettle, D., Nott, K., & Bateson, M. (2012). ‘Cycle thieves, we are watching you’: Impact of a simple signage intervention against bicycle theft. PLOS ONE, 7, e51738. Nisbett, R., & Cohen, D. (1996). Culture of honour: The psychology of violence in the south. Boulder, CO: Westview Press. Nisbett, R. E., & Wilson, T. D. (1977). Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports on mental processes. Psychological Review, 84, 231-259. Nowak, M. A., & Sigmund, K. (1998). Evolution of indirect reciprocity by image scoring. Nature, 393, 573-577. Oda, R., Niwa, Y., Honma, A., & Hiraishi, K. (2011). An eye-like painting enhances the expectation of a good reputation. Evolution and Human Behavior, 32, 166-171. Olson, M. (1968). Die Logik des kollektiven Handelns [The logic of collective action]. Tübingen: Mohr. Orne, M. T. (1962). On the social psychology of the psychological experiment: With particular reference to demand characteristics and their implications. American Psychologist, 17, 776-783. Ostrom, E. (1990). Governing the commons. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press. REFERENCES 123 Osumi, T., Nakao, T., Kasuya, Y., Shinoda, J., Yamada, J., & Ohira, H. (2012). Amygdala dysfunction attenuates frustration-induced aggression in psychopathic individuals in a non-criminal population. Journal of Affective Disorders, 142, 311338. Panagopoulos, C. (2014). I’ve got my eyes on you: Implicit social-pressure cues and prosocial behavior. Political Psychology, 35, 23-33. Panagopoulos, C. (in press). Watchful eyes: Implicit observability cues and voting. Evolution and Human Behavior. Papies, E. K., Barsalou, L. W., & Custers, R. (2012). Mindful attention prevents mindless impulses. Social Psychological and Personality Science, 3, 291-299. Peacock, M. S. (2007). The conceptual construction of altruism Ernst Fehr’s experimental approach to human conduct. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 37, 323. Petrie, M., Halliday, T., & Sanders, C. (1991). Peahens prefer peacocks with elaborate trains. Animal Behaviour, 41, 323-331. Petty, R. E., Cacioppo, J. T., & Goldman, R. (1981). Personal involvement as a determinant of argument-based persuasion. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 41, 847-855. Pfattheicher, S., & Keller, J. (2013). Vigilant self-regulation and costly punishment in public goods situations. European Journal of Personality, 27, 346-354. Pfattheicher, S., & Keller, J. (2014). The eye cue manipulation as subtle induction of a sense of being watched: Empirical validation and theoretical integration. Manuscript under review. Pfattheicher, S., & Keller, J. (in press). Towards a biopsychological understanding of costly punishment: The role of basal cortisol. PLOS ONE. REFERENCES 124 Pfattheicher, S., Landhäußer, A., & Keller, J. (2014). Punishing for the sake of reputation? Effects of reputational concerns on costly punishment. Manuscript under review. Pfattheicher, S., Landhäußer, A., & Keller, J. (in press). Individual differences in antisocial punishment in public goods situations: The interplay of cortisol with testosterone and dominance. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making. Pfattheicher, S., Sassenrath, C., & Schindler, S. (2014). Feelings for the suffering of others and the environment: Compassion fosters proenvironmental tendencies. Manuscript under review. Piazza, J., & Bering, J. M. (2008). The effects of perceived anonymity on altruistic punishment. Evolutionary Psychology, 6, 487-501. Piff, P. K., Stancato, D. M., Côté, S., Mendoza-Denton, R., & Keltner, D. (2012). Higher social class predicts increased unethical behavior. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, 109, 4086-4091. Pillutla, M. M., & Murnighan, J. K. (1996). Unfairness, anger, and spite: Emotional rejections of ultimatum offers. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 68, 208-224. Popper, K. (2002). The logic of scientific discovery. London: Routledge. Poustka, L., Maras, A., Hohm, E., Fellinger, J., Holtmann, M., Banaschewski, T., ... & Laucht, M. (2010). Negative association between plasma cortisol levels and aggression in a high-risk community sample of adolescents. Journal of Neural Transmission, 117, 621-627. Powell, K. L., Roberts, G., & Nettle, D. (2012). Eye images increase charitable donations: Evidence from an opportunistic field experiment in a supermarket. Ethology, 118, 1096-1101. REFERENCES 125 Raihani, N. J., & Bshary, R. (2012). A positive effect of flowers rather than eye images in a large-scale, cross-cultural dictator game. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 279, 3556-3564. Raine, A., Dodge, K., Loeber, R., Gatzke‐Kopp, L., Lynam, D., Reynolds, C., ... & Liu, J. (2006). The Reactive-Proactive Aggression Questionnaire: Differential correlates of reactive and proactive aggression in adolescent boys. Aggressive Behavior, 32, 159-171. Rand, D. G., Greene, J. D., & Nowak, M. A. (2012). Spontaneous giving and calculated greed. Nature, 489, 427-430. Raney, A. A. (2009). Punishing media criminals and moral judgment: The impact on enjoyment. Media Psychology, 7, 145-163. Rege, M., & Telle, K. (2004). The impact of social approval and framing on cooperation in public good situations. Journal of Public Economics, 88, 1625-1644. Reuben, E., & Van Winden, F. (2008). Social ties and coordination on negative reciprocity: The role of affect. Journal of Public Economics, 92, 34-53. Richetin, J., & Richardson, D. S. (2008). Automatic processes and individual differences in aggressive behavior. Aggression and Violent Behavior, 13, 423-430. Rigdon, M., Ishii, K., Watabe, M., & Kitayama, S. (2009). Minimal social cues in the dictator game. Journal of Economic Psychology, 30, 358-367. Roberts, G. (1998). Competitive altruism: From reciprocity to the handicap principle. Proceeding of the Royal Society, 265, 427-431. Robinson, M. D., Schmeichel, B. J., & Inzlicht, M. (2010). A cognitive control perspective of self-control strength and its depletion. Social and Personality Psychology Compass, 4, 189-200. REFERENCES 126 Rockenbach, B., & Milinski, M. (2011). To qualify as a social partner, humans hide severe punishment, although their observed cooperativeness is decisive. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 108, 18307-18312. Rogers, R. W., & Ketchen, C. M. (1979). Effects of anonymity and arousal on aggression. The Journal of Psychology, 102, 13-19. Rosenthal, R., & Jacobson, L. (1968). Pygmalion in the classroom. The Urban Review, 3, 16-20. Ross, L., & Nisbett, R. E. (1991). The person and the situation: Perspectives of social psychology. New York: Mcgraw-Hill Book Company. Ross, L. D., Amabile, T. M., & Steinmetz, J. L. (1977). Social roles, social control, and biases in social-perception processes. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 35, 485-494. Rotemberg, J. J. (2008). Minimally acceptable altruism and the ultimatum game. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 66, 457-476. Rotter, J. B. (1954). Social learning and clinic psychology. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Rubinow, D. R., Roca, C. A., Schmidt, P. J., Danaceau, M. A., Putnam, K., Cizza, G., ... & Nieman, L. (2005). Testosterone suppression of CRH-stimulated cortisol in men. Neuropsychopharmacology, 30, 1906-1912. Rucker, D. D., Preacher, K. J., Tormala, Z. L., & Petty, R. E. (2011). Mediation analysis in social psychology: Current practices and new recommendations. Social and Personality Psychology Compass, 5, 359-371. Sanfey, A. G., Rilling, J. K., Aronson, J. A, Nystrom, L. E., & Cohen, J. D. (2003). The neural basis of economic decision-making in the Ultimatum Game. Science, 300, 1755-1758. REFERENCES 127 Scheier, M. F., Carver, C. S., & Bridges, M. W. (1994). Distinguishing optimism from neuroticism (and trait anxiety, self-mastery, and self-esteem): A reevaluation of the Life Orientation Test. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 67, 10631076. Schmidt, B., Mussel, P., & Hewig, J. (2013). I’m too calm – Let’s take a risk! On the impact of state and trait arousal on risk taking. Psychophysiology, 50, 498-503. Schmitt, M. J., Baumert, A., Fetchenhauer, D., Gollwitzer, M., Rothmund, T., & Schlösser, T. (2009). Sensibilität für Ungerechtigkeit [Sensitivity for injustice]. Psychologische Rundschau, 60, 8-22. Schmitt, M. J., Neumann, R., & Montada, L. (1995). Dispositional sensitivity to befallen injustice. Social Justice Research, 8, 385-407. Scholer, A. A., & Higgins, E. T. (2008). Distinguishing levels of approach and avoidance: An analysis using regulatory focus theory. In A. J. Elliot (Ed.), Handbook of approach and avoidance motivation (pp. 489-503). New York: Psychology Press. Scholer, A., & Higgins, E. T. (2011). Promotion and prevention systems: Regulatory focus dynamics within self-regulatory hierarchies. In K. D. Vohs & R. F. Baumeister (Eds.), Self-regulation: Research, theory, and applications (pp. 143161). New York: Guilford Press. Scholer, A. A., Zou, X., Fujita, K., Stroessner, S. J., & Higgins, E. T. (2010). When risk seeking becomes a motivational necessity. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 99, 215-231. Schulz, J. F., Fischbacher, U., Thöni, C., & Utikal, V. (in press). Affect and fairness: Dictator games under cognitive load. Journal of Economic Psychology. Schwartz, S. H., & Bilsky, W. (1990). Toward a theory of the universal content and structure of values: Extensions and cross-cultural replications. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 58, 878-891. REFERENCES 128 Schwartz, S. H., Cieciuch, J., Vecchione, M., Davidov, E., Fischer, R., Beierlein, C., ... & Konty, M. (2012). Refining the theory of basic individual values. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 103, 663-688. Sellers, J. G., Mehl, M. R., & Josephs, R. A. (2007). Hormones and personality: Testosterone as a marker of individual differences. Journal of Research in Personality, 41, 126-138. Selten, R. (1998). Features of experimentally observed bounded rationality. European Economic Review, 42, 413-436. Shaw, A., & Santos, L. (2012). Lab support for strong reciprocity is weak: Punishing for reputation rather than cooperation. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 35, 39-39. Shinada, M., & Yamagishi, T. (2007). Bringing back Leviathan in social dilemmas. In A. Biel, D. Eek, T. Gärling & M. Gustafsson (Eds.), New issues and paradigms in research on social dilemmas (pp. 93-123). New York: Springer. Shinada, M., Yamagishi, T., & Ohmura, Y. (2004). False friends are worse than bitter enemies: “Altruistic” punishment of in-group members. Evolution and Human Behavior, 25, 379-393. Simonsohn, U. (2013). Small telescopes: Detectability and the evaluation of replication results. The Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania. Retrieved December 18, 2013, from http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2259879. Small, D. A., & Loewenstein, G. (2005). The devil you know: The effects of identifiability on punishment. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 18, 311318. Smith, E. A., & Bliege Bird, R. (2000). Turtle hunting and tombstone opening: Public generosity as costly signaling. Evolution and Human Behavior, 21, 245-261. Smith, E. R., & Mackie, D. M. (2007). Social psychology (3rd ed.). Hove: Psychology Press/Taylor & Francis. REFERENCES 129 Smith, M., Edwards, R., & McCann, U. (2007). The effects of sleep deprivation on pain inhibition and spontaneous pain in women. Sleep, 30, 494-505. Sober, E., & Wilson, D. S. (1998). Unto others. The evolution and psychology of unselfish behavior. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Sparks, A., & Barclay, P. (2013). Eye images increase generosity, but not for long: The limited effect of a false cue. Evolution and Human Behavior, 5, 317-322. Spence, M. (1973). Job market signaling. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 87, 355374. Spencer, S. J., Zanna, M. P., & Fong, G. T. (2005). Establishing a causal chain: Why experiments are often more effective than mediational analyses in examining psychological processes. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 89, 845851. Srivastava, J., Espinoza, F., & Fedorikhin, A. (2009). Coupling and decoupling of unfairness and anger in ultimatum bargaining. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 22, 475-489. Stirrat, M., & Perrett, D. I. (2010). Valid facial cues to cooperation and trust male facial width and trustworthiness. Psychological Science, 21, 349-354. Strack, F., & Deutsch, R. (2004). Reflective and impulsive determinants of social behavior. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 8, 220-247. Strack, F., & Deutsch, R. (2012). A theory of impulse and reflection. In P. A. van Lange, A. W. Kruglanski & E. T. Higgins (Eds.), Handbook of theories of social psychology (Vol. 1, pp. 97-117). London: Sage Publications. Stucke, T. S., & Baumeister, R. F. (2006). Ego depletion and aggressive behavior: Is the inhibition of aggression a limited resource? European Journal of Social Psychology, 36, 1-13. REFERENCES 130 Sundie, J. M., Kenrick, D. T., Griskevicius, V., Tybur, J. M., Vohs, K. D., & Beal, D. J. (2011). Peacocks, Porsches, and Thorstein Veblen: Conspicuous consumption as a sexual signaling system. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 100, 664680. Sutter, M., Kocher, M., & Strauß, S. (2003). Bargaining under time pressure in an experimental ultimatum game. Economics Letters, 81, 341-347. Sylwester, K., Herrmann, B., & Bryson, J. J. (2013). Homo homini lupus? Explaining antisocial punishment. Journal of Neuroscience, Psychology, and Economics, 6, 167-188. Tabibnia, G., Satpute, A. B., & Lieberman, M. D. (2008). The sunny side of fairness preference for fairness activates reward circuitry (and disregarding unfairness activates self-control circuitry). Psychological Science, 19, 339-347. Tane, K., & Takezawa, M. (2011). Perception of human face does not induce cooperation in darkness. Letters on Evolutionary Behavioral Science, 2, 24-27. Tennie, C. (2012). Punishing for your own good: The case of reputation-based cooperation. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 35, 40-41. Thomas, W. I., & Thomas, D. S. (1928). The child in America. Behavior problems and programs. New York: Knopf. Tops, M., & Boksem, M. A. (2011). Cortisol involvement in mechanisms of behavioral inhibition. Psychophysiology, 48, 723-732. Torrubia, R., Avila, C., Moltó, J., & Caseras, X. (2001). The Sensitivity to Punishment and Sensitivity to Reward Questionnaire (SPSRQ) as a measure of Gray's anxiety and impulsivity dimensions. Personality and Individual Differences, 31, 837-862. Trivers, R. L. (1971). The evolution of reciprocal altruism. Quarterly Review of Biology, 46, 35-57. REFERENCES 131 van Bommel, M., van Prooijen, J. W., Elffers, H., & van Lange, P. A. (in press). Intervene to be seen: The power of a camera in attenuating the bystander effect. Social Psychological and Personality Science. van den Bos, W., Golka, P., Effelsberg, D., & McClure, S. (2013). Pyrrhic victories: The need for social status drives costly competitive behavior. Frontiers in Neuroscience, 7, 1-11. van Dijk, E., & Wilke, H. (2000). Decision-induced focusing in social dilemmas: Givesome, keep-some, take-some, and leave-some dilemmas. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 78, 92-104. van Goozen, S. H. (2005). Hormones and the developmental origins of aggression. New York: Guilford Press. van Goozen, S. H., Fairchild, G., & Harold, G. T. (2008). The role of neurobiological deficits in childhood antisocial behavior. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 17, 224-228. van Goozen, S. H., Fairchild, G., Snoek, H., & Harold, G. T. (2007). The evidence for a neurobiological model of childhood antisocial behavior. Psychological Bulletin, 133, 149-182. van Honk, J., Harmon‐Jones, E., Morgan, B. E., & Schutter, D. J. (2010). Socially explosive minds: The triple imbalance hypothesis of reactive aggression. Journal of Personality, 78, 67-94. van Honk, J., Tuiten, A., van den Hout, M., Koppeschaar, H., Thijssen, J., de Haan, E., & Verbaten, R. (1998). Baseline salivary cortisol levels and preconscious selective attention for threat: A pilot study. Psychoneuroendocrinology, 23, 741-747. van Honk, J., Tuiten, A., van den Hout, M., Koppeschaar, H., Thijssen, J., de Haan, E., & Verbaten, R. (2000). Conscious and preconscious selective attention to social REFERENCES 132 threat: Different neuroendocrine response patterns. Psychoneuroendocrinology, 25, 577-591. van Lange, P. A. M., Balliet, D. P., Parks, C. D., & van Vugt, M. (2014). Social dilemmas: Understanding human cooperation. Oxford: Oxford University Press. van Lange, P. A., De Bruin, E., Otten, W., & Joireman, J. A. (1997). Development of prosocial, individualistic, and competitive orientations: Theory and preliminary evidence. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 73, 733-746. van Lange, P. A. M., De Cremer, D., van Dijk, E., & van Vugt, M. (2007). Self-interest and beyond: Basic principles of social interaction. In A. W. Kruglanski & E. T. Higgins (Eds.), Social psychology: Handbook of basic principles (pp. 540-561). New York: Guilford Press. van Lange, P. A. M., Joireman, J., Parks, C. D., & van Dijk, E. (2013). The psychology of social dilemmas: A review. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 120, 125-141. van Vugt, M., Griskevicius, V., & Schultz, P. (2014). Naturally green: Harnessing stone age psychological biases to foster environmental behavior. Social Issues and Policy Review, 8, 1-32. van Vugt, M., Roberts, G., & Hardy, C. (2007). Competitive altruism: Development of reputation-based cooperation in groups. In R. Dunbar & L. Barrett (Eds.), Handbook of evolutionary psychology (pp. 531-540). Oxford: Oxford University Press. van’t Wout, M., Kahn, R. S., Sanfey, A. G., & Aleman, A. (2006). Affective state and decision-making in the ultimatum game. Experimental Brain Research, 169, 564568. Viau, V. (2002). Functional cross-talk between the hypothalamic-pituitary-gonadal and -adrenal axes. Journal of Neuroendocrinology, 14, 506-513. REFERENCES 133 Vinkers, C. H., Zorn, J. V., Cornelisse, S., Koot, S., Houtepen, L. C., Olivier, B., ... & Joëls, M. (2013). Time-dependent changes in altruistic punishment following stress. Psychoneuroendocrinology, 38, 1467-1475. Vohs, K. D., & Baumeister, R. F. (2004). Unterstanding self-regulation. In R. F. Baumeister & K. D. Vohs (Eds.), Handbook of self-regulation: Research, theory, and application (pp. 1-9). New York: Guilford Press. Vohs, K. D., & Schmeichel, B. J. (2003). Self-regulation and extended now: Controlling the self alters the subjective experience of time. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 85, 217-230. von Dawans, B., Kirschbaum, C., & Heinrichs, M. (2011). The Trier Social Stress Test for Groups (TSST-G): A new research tool for controlled simultaneous social stress exposure in a group format. Psychoneuroendocrinology, 36, 514-522. Vul, E., Harris, C., Winkielman, P., & Pashler, H. (2009). Puzzlingly high correlations in fMRI studies of emotion, personality, and social cognition. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 4, 274-290. Wang, C. S., Sivanathan, N., Narayanan, J., Ganegoda, D. B., Bauer, M., Bodenhausen, G. V., & Murnighan, K. (2011). Retribution and emotional regulation: The effects of time delay in angry economic interactions. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 116, 46-54. Weber, M. (1922/1972). Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft [Economy and society] (5th ed.). Tübingen: Mohr. Wedekind, C., & Braithwaite, V. A. (2002). The long-term benefits of human generosity in indirect reciprocity. Current Biology, 12, 1012-1015. Weesie, J. (1993). Asymmetry and timing in the volunteers dilemma. Journal of Conflict Resolution, 37, 569-590. REFERENCES 134 West, S. A., El Mouden, C., & Gardner, A. (2011). Sixteen common misconceptions about the evolution of cooperation in humans. Evolution and Human Behavior, 32, 231-262. Wilkowski, B. M., & Robinson, M. D. (2008). The cognitive basis of trait anger and reactive aggression: An integrative analysis. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 12, 3-21. Williams, K. D. (1997). Social ostracism. In R. Kowalski (Ed.), Aversive interpersonal behaviors (pp. 133-170). New York: Plenum Press. Williams, K. D. (2007). Ostracism: The kiss of social death. Social and Personality Psychology Compass, 1, 236-247. Williams, K. D., Cheung, C. K., & Choi, W. (2000). Cyberostracism: Effects of being ignored over the internet. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 79, 748762. Windle, M. (1994). Temperamental inhibition and activation: Hormonal and psychosocial correlates and associated psychiatric disorders. Personality and Individual Differences, 17, 61-70. Yamagishi, T. (1986). The provision of a sanctioning system as a public good. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 51, 110-116. Yurdusev, A. N. (1993). ‘Level of Analysis’ and ‘Unit of Analysis’: A case for distinction. Millennium-Journal of International Studies, 22, 77-88. Zahavi, A. (1975). Mate selection: Selection for a handicap. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 53, 205-214. Zahavi, A., & Zahavi, A. (1997). The handicap principle: The missing piece of Darwin’s puzzle. Oxford: Oxford University Press. REFERENCES 135 Zak, P. J., Kurzban, R., Ahmadi, S., Swerdloff, R. S., Park, J., Efremidze, L., ... & Matzner, W. (2009). Testosterone administration decreases generosity in the ultimatum game. PLOS ONE, 4, e8330. Zaki, J., & Mitchell, J. P. (2013). Intuitive prosociality. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 22, 466-470. Zethraeus, N., Kocoska-Maras, L., Ellingsen, T., von Schoultz, B., Hirschberg, A. L., & Johannesson, M. (2009). A randomized trial of the effect of estrogen and testosterone on economic behavior. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 106, 6535-6538. Zillig, L. M. P., Hemenover, S. H., & Dienstbier, R. A. (2002). What do we assess when we assess a Big 5 trait? A content analysis of the affective, behavioral, and cognitive processes represented in Big 5 personality inventories. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 28, 847-858. Zimbardo, P. G. (1969). The human choice: Individuation, reason, and order versus deindividuation, impulse, and chaos. In W. J. Arnold & D. Levone (Eds.), Nebraska symposium on motivation (pp. 237-308). Lincoln, NM: University of Nebraska Press. ZUSAMMENFASSUNG 136 Zusammenfassung Negative Sanktionen, im Konkreten die Bestrafung anderer Personen im Gruppenkontext, fördert menschliches Kooperationsverhalten. Diese Dissertation hat das Ziel, negative Sanktionen im Kontext sozialer Dilemmasituationen zu verstehen und zu erklären. Im Speziellen wird aus biopsychologischer Sicht eine Analyse hinsichtlich kostspieliger Bestrafung im Kontext öffentlicher Güter vorgenommen. Dabei stellt diese Dissertation eine theoretische Einordnung sowie die Zusammenfassung und Diskussion fünf publizierter oder sich unter Begutachtung befindender Forschungsartikel dar. Aufbauend auf Befunden aus der Aggressionsforschung wird in einem ersten Artikel gezeigt, dass kostspieliges Bestrafen unkooperativer Personen positiv mit dem basalen Kortisol-Level zusammenhängt. Ein zweiter Artikel dokumentiert, dass ein subtiler sozialer Cue (stilisierte menschliche Augen) dazu führen kann, ein Gefühl des Beobachtetwerdens herzustellen. Diese Erkenntnis wird in einem dritten Artikel angewandt, um zu Reputationsbedingungen untersuchen, (d.h. unter wie sich kostspieliges Beobachtung und Bestrafen unter unter öffentlicher Selbstaufmerksamkeit) verändert. Dabei konnte eine Reduzierung kostspieligen Bestrafens dokumentiert werden. In einer vierten Forschungsarbeit wird kostspieliges Bestrafen unkooperativer Personen durch eine basale motivationale Orientierung, den Prevention-Fokus, vorhergesagt. Ein fünfter Forschungsartikel beschäftigt sich mit der Erklärung der Bestrafung kooperativer Personen. Es kann gezeigt werden, dass diese Art der Bestrafung positiv mit dem basalen Testosteron-Level und psychologischem Dominanzstreben zusammenhängt, wenn ein relativ niedriges Kortisol-Level gegeben ist. Zusammenfassend tragen diese Dissertation und die einzelnen Forschungsarbeiten zu einem besseren Verständnis kostspieligen Bestrafens bei. APPENDIX 137 Appendix Appendix A: Towards a biopsychological understanding of costly punishment: The role of basal cortisol (Pfattheicher & Keller, in press) Appendix B: The eye cue manipulation as subtle induction of a sense of being watched: Empirical validation and theoretical integration (Pfattheicher & Keller, 2014) Appendix C: Punishing for the sake of reputation? Effects of reputational concerns on costly punishment (Pfattheicher, Landhäußer, & Keller, 2014) Appendix D: Vigilant self-regulation and costly punishment in public goods situations (Pfattheicher & Keller, 2013) Appendix E: Individual differences in antisocial punishment in public goods situations: The interplay of cortisol with testosterone and dominance (Pfattheicher, Landhäußer, & Keller, in press) Appendix F: Vigilant self-regulation, cues of being watched and cooperativeness (Keller & Pfattheicher, 2011) Appendix G: The Compassion-Hostility-Paradox: The interplay of vigilant, preventionfocused self-regulation, compassion and hostility (Keller & Pfattheicher, in press) Appendix H: Feelings for the suffering of others and the environment: Compassion fosters proenvironmental tendencies (Pfattheicher, Sassenrath, & Schindler, 2014) Aus Urheberrechtsgründen sind die Artikel nicht dieser Fassung beigefügt.