* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download The Logical Argument is not Bankrupt
Meaning of life wikipedia , lookup
Problem of evil wikipedia , lookup
Universalism wikipedia , lookup
Existence of God wikipedia , lookup
Euthyphro dilemma wikipedia , lookup
Evolutionary argument against naturalism wikipedia , lookup
Jewish existentialism wikipedia , lookup
Irenaean theodicy wikipedia , lookup
Page |1 The Logical Argument is not Bankrupt Evil, Freedom, and Divine Foreknowledge Abstract. The Logical Argument from Evil argues that the existence of evil is logically incompatible with the existence of God, assuming that by ‘God’ we mean a being that is necessarily omnipotent, omniscient, and omnibenevolent. Any being with these three attributes would eliminate evil in its entirety, and given that evil exists it therefore follows that no being endowed with these attributes exists; that is, God does not exist. With his Free-Will Defence, Alvin Plantinga is commonly held to have refuted the Logical Argument. In this paper I argue that his alleged refutation fails: the sort of free-will which figures centrally in his argument is itself incompatible with another divine attribute, namely divine foreknowledge. If this is correct then the Logical Argument has not been successfully refuted. KEYWORDS: evil, God, free-will, foreknowledge, omniscience Introduction: Setting the Stage “Is God willing to prevent evil, but not able? Then he is not omnipotent. Is he able, but not willing? Then he is malevolent. Is he both willing and able? Then whence cometh evil? Is he neither able nor willing? Then why call him God?” The above riddle, attributed to the ancient Greek philosopher Epicurus, is a pithy outline of an argument which is simple, intuitively appealing, and according to almost all contemporary philosophers of religion, incorrect.1 In his 1974 God, Freedom, and Evil, Alvin Plantinga is thought to have refuted Epicurus’ riddle, which nowadays is known as the Logical Argument from Evil, or simply, the Logical Argument. As a result of his refutation, more atheologicallyinclined philosophers of religion have increasingly turned to evidential and probabilistic formulations of the Problem of Evil, with the existence of evil merely making the existence of God improbable and not impossible outright. My goal in this essay is to go some way towards disabusing the reader of this notion – the Logical Argument still presents a problem for the theist. In the first section I outline J.L Mackie’s modern formulation of the Logical Argument. This sets the stage for Section II where I examine Alvin Plantinga’s formidable 1 “It is now acknowledged on (almost) all sides that the logical problem is bankrupt.” (Alston, 1996: 97) Page |2 rejoinder to Mackie. Lastly, drawing on the work of Nelson Pike, I argue that Plantinga’s sophisticated rebuttal does not succeed. The sort of free-will which he needs in order to make the existence of evil compatible with the existence of God is itself incompatible with divine foreknowledge, and so the Logical Argument presents itself anew. Before getting to the meat of the matter, however, some preliminary remarks are in order. The Logical Argument attempts to show that, if evil exists, God could not possibly exist.2 But this may sound strange – surely it’s possible that God exists? And who or what do I mean by ‘God’ here anyway? Answering this latter question will make it clear why our argument answers the former question in the negative, thus explaining why the existence of evil logically precludes the existence of God. By ‘God’, I mean a being with the following three attributes: (i) omnipotence, (ii) omniscience, and (iii) omnibenevolence. In other words, God is all-powerful, all-knowing, and wholly good. For the purposes of this essay, these three attributes are non-negotiable: “God is omnipotent, omniscient, and omnibenevolent” is seen as a priori true. If some being has (i) and (ii) but lacks (iii) then, by definition, it’s not God. Some may see this as my way of stipulating the terms of the Logical Argument’s victory, as mere semantic skulduggery that serves to constrain and tighten the logical space within which the theist can move to defend her belief in God. Let me be clear: you are of course free to call any being lacking one or more of these three attributes ‘God’, if so inclined. You’re also free to call your favourite footballer or your next-door neighbour or your pet hamster ‘God’. Defining ‘God’ as ‘all that exists’ is one way to successfully counter the Logical Argument, as is defining ‘omniscient’ as ‘knowing the truth-value of every proposition except for those propositions that make reference to or imply the existence of evil.’ I ask that the reader forgive my definitional inflexibility. We can always split hairs another time. In my defence, the particular conception of God I attack here is both the subject of widespread contemporary belief as well as being historically motivated – and so it is not a mere fiction which the Logical Argument seeks to call into question.3 Now, the Logical Argument works by claiming that the existence of any being endowed with attributes (i) – (iii) is not logically consistent with the existence of evil in the world. Being 2 A more precise way of putting this might be to say that there are no possible worlds where both God and evil exist. Of course, there could still be possible worlds where God exists. 3 Of course, it would be an open question as to whether some being with one or two of our attributes exists. I merely deny that this being is God. God 2.0 perhaps, or God Lite – but not God. Page |3 omnibenevolent, it has the desire to eliminate all evil, and being omniscient, it has the power to satisfy its desires. Add omniscience to the mix and it has sufficient knowledge to take unbounded action towards the satisfaction of its benevolent will. So why is there is still evil? Given some plausible initial assumptions regarding our three attributes, the Logical Argument readily suggests itself, and the existence of evil becomes a big problem for anyone wishing to defend their belief in God. Our argument enjoys considerable prima facie credence, and it will take some work to refute it. One last question remains before getting to the fun stuff: What is evil? ‘Evil’ can be anything from disease, famine, or natural disasters, to decidedly human evils like war, murder, or undergraduate philosophy students loudly insisting that God doesn’t exist. We typically speak of evil persons, places, events, and so on, but in this essay we are always dealing with evil simpliciter.4 Now that we’re clear on what exactly we’re discussing, let us move on to Mackie’s modern re-casting of an argument so elegantly captured by Epicurus and his riddle. Section I: Mackie and the Problem of Evil We now move on to Mackie’s formulation, found in his 1955 article ‘Evil and Omnipotence’.5 As noted above, there is an apparent inconsistency between the existence of a being with the traditional divine attributes of omnipotence, omniscience, and omnibenevolence on the one hand, and the existence of evil on the other. We can say that the set S containing the propositions “God exists”, “God is omnipotent, omnibenevolent, and omniscient”, and “Evil exists” as members is inconsistent, where a set is inconsistent just in case all of its members cannot simultaneously be true.6 However, the non-theist may wish to cover her bases here, so Mackie adds the further propositions p (“A good thing always eliminates evil as far as it can”) and q. (“There are no limits to what an omnipotent being can do”.) (Mackie, 300) These additional propositions merely make explicit uncontroversial assumptions about the concepts of ‘goodness’ and ‘omnipotence’. Proposition p isn’t 4 Note that it is common to formulate the Logical Argument using highly specific examples of evil. Cf. Tooley (2012) 5 His essay, as well as Plantinga’s and Pike’s, are re-printed in Pojman and Rea’s Philosophy of Religion: An Anthology. (2012) 6 Note that Plantinga takes inconsistency to be equivalent to formally contradictory, where a formally contradictory set is one “from whose members an explicit contradiction can be deduced by the laws of logic”. (Plantinga, 330) Our less refined understanding of inconsistency will suffice for our purposes. Nothing in the argument presented turns on the use of one over the other. Page |4 necessarily true: there are plenty of good people who, for whatever reason, choose not to eliminate evil even though they could. Perhaps they are uncertain about the correctness of their actions, or perhaps they are afraid to act, or some other reason. Unfortunately for the theist, though, p seems likely to be true in God’s case. God isn’t just good, he’s wholly good; and we usually don’t think of God as labouring under the weight of moral uncertainty or fear with respect to his actions. Furthermore, when we’re asking to what extent God can eliminate evil, we should expect that he could eliminate it completely! After all, he is omnipotent and, being omniscient, he certainly knows about its existence. So Mackie seems to be on firm ground with respect to p. What about q? Well, that will depend on what we mean by “omnipotent”? Presumably he does not think that an omnipotent being can do what is logically impossible. I think we can quite reasonably take that possibility to be incoherent, although there are some philosophers willing to endorse it.7 So we shall assume that an omnipotent being is one who can do anything but the logically impossible. Like p, q appears to be such that a theist could easily accept it. With the addition of p and q, S becomes an inconsistent set, or so Mackie will argue. A wholly good and omnipotent being will eliminate evil as far as it can. God could eliminate evil entirely. So the existence of evil means that God does not exist. (Ibid, 300) Mackie considers and rejects four theistic solutions to the Logical Argument. Ignoring the first two, (Ibid, 301-302) we can look at his treatment of (3) and (4). (3) states that the Universe is better with some evil in it than it would be if there were none at all. (4) appeals to human free-will as the source of evil. A conjunction of these two looks something like Plantinga’s eventual response. The world is better with some measure of evil in it because that evil is the result of some greater good. That greater good is human free-will. A world free of evil would be good, but a world where men and women receive the divine gift of freewill is better. But because we can act freely, we sometimes err on the side of evil. (Ibid, 304) There are two problems here. One is that although some evils could be the result of our freewill, there are others – so-called natural evils such as natural disasters, diseases, and so on that can’t be connected to our actions in any plausible way, at least not outside of the 7 Cf. Frankfurt. (1964) For what it’s worth, I think this notion of omnipotence would do nothing for the theist looking to refute the Logical Argument. Suppose the theist wants to argue that God, though omnipotent, could not create a world that was absolutely free of evil because evil is a necessary consequence of allowing some greater good to exist. It was not possible that this good exist without also bringing evil about. Well, this notion of omnipotence would undercut that line of thought: God can do anything, even what is impossible. Even though it is impossible to create the greatest possible world without thereby also creating evil, God could do it. So, in addition to being near-unintelligible, this conception of omnipotence actually makes the Problem of Evil even harder for the theist to answer. Page |5 Westboro Baptist Church. Another problem is that the theist would need to demonstrate just how a world with humans endowed with free-will is better than a world without any evil whatsoever. Why should it not be the case that an unfree world with no evil in it is better than a free world with some evil in it? The theist simply begs the question here. However, let’s suppose that the theist has some convincing responses ready for us. Mackie has an objection which seems more problematic for any theist looking to respond to the Logical Argument. He thinks that the theist sets up a false dichotomy in supposing that “free agents who sometimes commit evil acts” and “people as automata determined to do what is good” are the only two options. If it’s not logically impossible for a man or woman to freely choose the good on one or several occasions, then it’s not logically impossible that a man or woman freely choose the good on every occasion. (Ibid, 304) God could have created the universe so that we can act freely and yet always perform good acts; and in failing to realize this possibility, if God exists at all, then the existence of evil becomes inconsistent with God’s alleged omnipotence and omnibenevolence. Either God allows evil to exist even though he could have easily made it so that none exists, in which case God is not omnibenevolent, or else God wants to eliminate evil but couldn’t have realized Mackie’ possibility, in which case God is not omnipotent. But a being which lacks either or both of these attributes is not God. So can we conclude that God does not exist? Let us now turn to Plantinga’s response. Section II: Plantinga’s Free-Will Defence Before examining Plantinga’s argument8, I would first like to make a few brief points. Firstly, his argument is called the ‘Free Will Defence’, and the use of ‘defence’ here is not merely incidental. We can group responses to the Problem of Evil into two broad categories: (i) we could opt for a theodicy, wherein we provide a possible explanation of the presence of evil in a world created by God and try to show that, not only is it possibly true, but it is plausibly or even actually true; or (ii) we could provide a defence, where we simply try to show that the existence of evil is logically compatible with the existence of God. Plantinga restricts his argument to trying to show that it is logically possible that evil and God co-exist – but no more! The argument’s humble aim is its strength. Secondly, Plantinga makes heavy use of possible-world semantics in responding to the Logical Argument, and although his writing is admirably clear, the argumentation can appear quite daunting to those unfamiliar with the 8 Found in God, Freedom, and Evil (1974) Page |6 technical vocabulary taken for granted by those more conversant with modal logic and indeed analytic philosophy more broadly. As such, my treatment of his argument will sacrifice some attention to detail in exchange for ease of access. Luckily, the argument in the final section in which I argue that Plantinga fails to refute the Logical Argument works regardless of the level of complexity found in the Free-Will Defence. Where his defence derives strength from its humility, I hope that my response derives some from its simplicity; or so we shall see. For Mackie’s argument to succeed, it must be the case that: (i) there is no logically possible morally justifying reason for God to allow the existence of evil, and (ii) the set S given above is in fact inconsistent; that is, not all of its members can be simultaneously true. Plantinga needs to show that both (i) and (ii) are false, and displaying the falsity of (i) should suffice to ensure the consistency of S, so let’s begin with (i). Predictably enough, free-will provides the morally justifying reason for God allowing evil’s continued existence. We should begin by noting that Plantinga rejects Mackie’s contention that God could have created free agents who, while free with respect to every action they perform, nonetheless always choose good over evil. (Plantinga, 339) A person is said to free with respect to an action if she is free to perform or refrain from performing an action; there are no conditions or causal laws determining her choice here. (Ibid, 338) Mackie is a compatibilist regarding free-will: he thinks, perhaps counter-intuitively, that causal determinism and human freedom are compatible. So we can always be determined to do what is right while still retaining our freedom. Plantinga sees this position as “utterly implausible”, and although he barely argues for this claim, we will pretend that he’s correct here. This opens the door for his denial of (i) above: a world that contains beings who are significantly free - where significant freedom is understood as being free with respect to a morally significant action – is better, ceteris paribus, than a world where there are no free beings at all. (Ibid, 340) Of course, if a being is significantly free with respect to morally significant actions then it is significantly free to choose the wrong or evil course of action. A more pressing concern for Plantinga is the logical possibility that the world could have contained beings who only ever do what is right; and if it’s possible that such a world exist, then an omnipotent God could have created it. So either God does not exist, or else it was beyond his power to create such a world – in which case he’s not really God because he lacks omnipotence. Plantinga’s next move is to show that God, though omnipotent, could not have actualized such a world. To actualize a world – a possible world – is, roughly, to bring it about so that it is the case. A possible world is just a way things could have been. Why would Page |7 we think an omnipotent being could not actualize some possible worlds? Take the following example. We have a situation S* where Smith is significantly free to either lie to his wife about his speeding ticket or tell the truth about his ticket. Obviously, God would want Smith to tell his wife the truth, but depending on which of the following counterfactuals is true, he may not get to see Smith do the right thing: (a) If S* were to be actualized, then Smith would tell the truth. (b) If S* were to be actualized, then Smith would not tell the truth. Now, either (a) or (b) must be true. If (a) is true and God actualizes S*, then Smith will tell the truth; with (b)’s actualization, Smith will lie. Now: let W(a) be a possible world where God actualizes S* and Smith tells the truth, and let W(b) be a possible world where God actualizes S* and Smith lies. If (a) is true then God, though omnipotent, can’t actualize W(b); and if (b) is true then God can’t actualize W(a). In either case, there is a possible world which an omnipotent God can’t actualize. So, according to Plantinga, it is false to say that an omnipotent God can actualize any possible world! (Ibid, 344-345) In general, we can say that there is any number of possible worlds where it is partly up to the free agent performing the action whether or not God actualizes them. (Ibid, 345) We could scrutinize this last claim more closely, but let’s assume that this is correct. Plantinga still has a little bit more to do to show that it is possible that (ii) above is false. To accomplish this, he introduces the notion of Transworld Depravity. (TWD) For each possible person and for each situation in which that person might exist and be significantly free with respect to some action, there is a set of true propositions {A¹, A², ..., Aⁿ} concerning what that person would do in such situations: call this set her Counterfactuals of Freedom. We can now define someone suffering from TWD as a person who, in any possible world in which she is actualized, has a corresponding set of Counterfactuals of Freedom that always contains at least one morally wrong action. So it is possible that Smith suffers from TWD, which means that it is possible that Smith, no matter what situation he is placed in, will freely perform at least one wrong action. Moreover, if it is possible that one person suffers from TWD, then it is possible that everyone suffers from TWD; and if it is possible that everyone suffers from TWD, then it follows that it is logically possible that God could not have actualized a world where people are significantly free with respect to their actions and always choose the morally correct ones. (Ibid, 347-348) If Plantinga is correct about this, then he is right to say that set S given above in Section I is not inconsistent. Page |8 Section III: Divine Foreknowledge and Human Free-Will9 In the last section we saw Plantinga argue that to be free with respect to any action A, a person must be free to either perform or refrain from performing A; no antecedent causal laws or pre-conditions could determine that she perform or refrain from performing A, otherwise she would not be significantly free, pace Mackie’s compatibilism. Further, we saw that it is possible that every possible person suffers from TWD, thus providing an explanation of the existence of evil that is logically compatible with God’s existence.10 A possible world containing beings with significant freedom and its resultant evil is better, all things being equal, than a world where beings lack free-will but always perform morally correct actions. It is our alleged free-will that provides the morally justifying reason for God allowing evil to exist. So, if we don’t really have free-will then God doesn’t really have a reason for allowing evil to exist. In this section, I try to show that one of God’s attributes – omniscience – is incompatible with human freedom. Either we’re not free and God allows evil to exist without a morally justifying reason, in which case he is not omnibenevolent, or God lacks divine foreknowledge, in which case he is not omniscient; whatever the case, once again, he’s not really God then. What is it to say a being is “omniscient”? A being is omniscient if, for every proposition p, it either knows p or knows that it is false. (Zagzebski, 2007, 262) An omniscient being knows every truth there is to be known, including such truths that are – whether temporarily or permanently – beyond our limited ability to grasp them. For example, God knows why Zinedine Zidane chose a World Cup final to unveil an interesting new way to head-butt people, even when us mere mortals can never know such things. In addition to knowing every truth there is to be known, God also holds no false beliefs. Further, we can add that God is infallible; that is, if God believes p then p is true. If God is omniscient in the way just outlined, then God knows absolutely everything, past, present, or future; from knowing what the world was like right up until this exact moment, to knowing what it will be like. This includes knowing what actions supposedly free agents will perform. This will become important. At this stage, the reader may be apprehensive. “Why”, you may reasonably be 9 This argument was inspired by Nelson Pike’s 1965 article ‘Divine Omniscience and Voluntary Action’. At this stage we could ask “what about natural evil?” Plantinga’s response here would be that the existence of natural evil is down to the free agency of demonic beings of some sort. Remember: to succeed his response only needs to be logically possible – plausibility here is an unnecessary extravagance. 10 Page |9 asking yourself, “would anyone’s knowledge of another’s actions be taken to constrain that person’s freedom?” Let’s say Smith is my best friend. I’ve known him for twenty years and I can predict his actions with perfect accuracy. We would not be inclined, I think, to say that Smith is somehow not free because of my knowledge. So to say that God’s foreknowledge of Smith’s future actions entails his non-freedom seems counter-intuitive at best. Let us press further into the argument. We’ve already assumed that if a being is omniscient, then any proposition p which that being knows must be true.11 Indeed, if there exists a being that fits the above description then if it so much as believes p then p must be true. 12So take any event E at time T2 at which it occurred; for any prior time T1, God knew at T1 that E would obtain at T2. (Pike, 98) An omniscient being has always known that E would obtain at T2: he knew it forty years ago, and he knew it one second after the Big Bang. What happens if we extend this sort of foreknowledge to human actions? Suppose, for example, that last Friday (T2) Smith was speeding along the motorway, well over the speed-limit. (E) If God exists, and is omniscient in the sense described above, then it follows that God knew, say, one hundred years ago (T1), that Smith would be speeding along the motorway last Friday. But then it follows that at T2, Smith was unable to refrain from speeding along the motorway, because if he could have refrained from doing so then it would have been the case that God’s belief turn out false; that is, the belief that “E will obtain at T2” would have been false. But if God is omniscient and infallible, then this is actually impossible. God necessarily cannot form false beliefs and so Smith could not have refrained from speeding at all; his freedom with respect to performing this action is illusory. Given the existence of a God who is necessarily omniscient, then it seems to follow that at the time of his actions, Smith did not have the power to refrain from speeding. Pike provides a similar example. (Ibid, 99) After Plantinga’s Free-Will Defence this argument can seem simplistic, but I think it is on to something. Free-will was supposed to be God’s morally justifying reason for allowing the existence of evil in the world, but we can now see that one of God’s attributes – the non-negotiable attribute of omniscience – raises severe problems for any theist looking to claim that we are significantly free with respect to our actions, both 11 Strictly speaking, we might say that any proposition known by anybody is necessarily true. If it turns out to be false then it was never really known in the first place – unless, that is, we subscribe to some non-factive analysis of knowledge. Such a discussion goes beyond the scope of this essay. 12 This is where the analogy between God’s foreknowledge of Smith’s actions and my foreknowledge of Smith’s actions falls apart. With an infallible and omniscient being, the wiggle-room between belief and truth disappears. I may believe that Smith will do such-and-such at some time in the future, but I could always be wrong. If God believes that Smith will do such-and-such, then that’s what Smith will do and that’s what Smith must do. P a g e | 10 morally significant actions and relatively trivial ones. God has always known exactly what we will do at each and every moment of our lives, and it is not possible that we could have done otherwise because to do so would entail God’s having held false beliefs – an impossibility given God’s necessary omniscience and infallibility. How could the theist respond to this argument? Let’s say that the theist insists that Smith can freely choose to either speed or not speed at T2 even though he is in a sense determined to be unable to refrain from speeding on pain of engendering a logically impossible state of affairs, namely, bringing it about that an infallible being held a false belief. Well, this just sounds like Mackie’s compatibilism again, and Plantinga has already rejected it. If determinism and freewill are not incompatible, then it is possible that we could be free with respect to every action while being determined to perform it one way or the other. But if this is possible then, contra Plantinga’s claims, it is possible after all that God could have actualized a possible world where people always freely choose to perform morally correct actions; and this means that God, in actualizing our world, is not omnibenevolent because he no longer has a morally justifying reason for evil’s existence. If God could have actualized the possible world of Mackie’s but didn’t, then he is not omnibenevolent. If we are to be free – free in Plantinga’s required sense of having libertarian free-will and not Mackie’s compatibilist free-will – then it can’t be the case that God is omniscient, because God’s foreknowledge of future events prevents our being free with respect to our actions. So either way the theist and Plantinga have to reject one of the three divine attributes (i) – (iii) outlined in the introduction; and as we’ve already said, any being that lacks any of these attributes is not really God. Such a being may exist, but it’s not God. If our argument is correct, then – contrary to received views in the philosophy of religion – the Logical Argument is not yet bankrupt. P a g e | 11 Bibliography: Alston, W.P. (1996) ‘The Inductive Argument from Evil and the Human Cognitive Condition’, In Daniel Howard-Snyder (ed.) The Evidential Argument from Evil. Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, pp. 97-125 Frankfurt, H. (1964) ‘The Logic of Omnipotence’, The Philosophical Review, 73, 262-263 Mackie, J.L. (1955) ‘Evil and Omnipotence’, Mind, 64, 200-212 Pike, N. (1965) ‘Divine Omniscience and Voluntary Action’, The Philosophical Review, 74, 27-46 Plantinga, A. (1974) God, Freedom, and Evil. London: George Allen and Unwin Ltd. Pojman, L. & Rea, M. (2012) Philosophy of Religion: An Anthology, 6th ed. Wadsworth Cengage Learning Tooley, M. (2013) ‘The Problem of Evil’, The Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy. (Summer 2013 Edition) Edward N. Zalta (ed.) URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2013/entries/evil/ Zagzebski, L. (2007) ‘Omniscience’, The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Religion, C. Meister & P. Copans (eds.) NY: Routledge, 261-269