* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Chance and Natural Selection
Deoxyribozyme wikipedia , lookup
History of genetic engineering wikipedia , lookup
Adaptive evolution in the human genome wikipedia , lookup
Designer baby wikipedia , lookup
Human genetic variation wikipedia , lookup
Dual inheritance theory wikipedia , lookup
Hardy–Weinberg principle wikipedia , lookup
Gene expression programming wikipedia , lookup
The Selfish Gene wikipedia , lookup
Polymorphism (biology) wikipedia , lookup
Koinophilia wikipedia , lookup
Group selection wikipedia , lookup
Genetic drift wikipedia , lookup
Chance and Natural Selection Author(s): John Beatty Reviewed work(s): Source: Philosophy of Science, Vol. 51, No. 2 (Jun., 1984), pp. 183-211 Published by: The University of Chicago Press on behalf of the Philosophy of Science Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/187421 . Accessed: 04/01/2013 16:36 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. . The University of Chicago Press and Philosophy of Science Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy of Science. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded on Fri, 4 Jan 2013 16:36:51 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Philosophy of Science June, 1984 CHANCE AND NATURAL SELECTION* JOHN BEATTYt Department of Philosophy Arizona State University Amongthe liveliest disputesin evolutionarybiology today are disputesconcerningthe role of chancein evolution-more specifically,disputesconcerning the relativeevolutionaryimportanceof naturalselectionvs. so-called "random drift".Thefollowingdiscussionis an attemptto sortout some of thebroadissues involvedin those disputes.In the first half of this paper,I try to explain the differencesbetweenevolutionby naturalselectionandevolutionby randomdrift. On some commonconstrualsof "naturalselection",those two modes of evolutionare completelyindistinguishable.Even on a properconstrualof "natural selection",it is difficultto distinguishbetweenthe "improbable resultsof natural selection"and evolutionby randomdrift. In the second half of this paper,I discuss the varietyof positionstaken by evolutionistswith respectto the evolutionaryimportanceof randomdrift vs. naturalselection. I will then considerthe varietyof issues in questionin terms of a conceptualdistinctionoften used to describethe rise of probabilisticthinking in the sciences. I will argue,in particular,thatwhatis going on hereis not, as mightappearat firstsight,just anotherdisputeaboutthe desirabilityof "stochastic"vs. "deterministic" theories.Modernevolutionistsdo notargueso much aboutwhetherevolutionis stochastic,but abouthow stochasticit is. *ReceivedJune 1983;revisedFebruary1984. tThis articlewas writtenduringthe academicyear 1982-1983, while I was a fellow at the Centerfor Interdisciplinary Researchat the Universityof Bielefeld, in Bielefeld, West Germany.I was part of a group researchproject, organizedby Lorenz Kruger,which studiedthe rise and role of probabilisticthinkingin the sciences since 1800. I am very gratefulto the staff of the Center,the facultyof the Universityof Bielefeld, and of course my fellow probabilistsfor theirthoughtsand for theirfriendship. RobertBrandon,LorenzKruger,Elliott Sober, KennethWaters, and the referees of Philosophyof Science all helped me to clarify the issues discussedhere. The residual unclaritydistinguishesmy contributionsfromtheirs. Some of the residualunclaritymust be attributedto JonathanHodge's and AlexanderRosenberg'scritiquesof the notion of "fitness"used here. Theirthoughtfulcritiqueshave, I must admit,left me a bit confused aboutmy position. Philosophyof Science, 51 (1984) pp. 183-211. CopyrightC 1984 by the Philosophyof ScienceAssociation. 183 This content downloaded on Fri, 4 Jan 2013 16:36:51 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 184 JOHNBEATTY 1. Introduction. CharlesDarwin'saccountof organicform appealedto chancein a way that did not settle well with his critics. As DarwinunJohnHerhappilyreportedthe opinionof the greatscientist-philosopher, schel, "I have heard,by a round-aboutchannel, that Herschelsays my book 'is the law of higgledy-piggledy.'Whatexactly this meansI do not know, butit is evidentlyvery contemptuous"(Darwinto Lyell, Dec. 12, 1859, in F. Darwin 1887, Vol. 2, p. 37). In time, though, Darwinwas praisedratherthanscornedfor his appealto chance.Forinstance,looking C. S. backat the turnof the century,anothergreatscientist-philosopher, Peirce, assessedDarwin'scontributionin this regardmore favorably: The Origin of Species was publishedtowardthe end of the year 1859. The precedingyearssince 1846 had been one of the most productiveseasons-or if extendedso as to cover the greatbook we are considering,the most productiveperiodof equal length in the entire historyof science from its beginningsuntil now. [For]the idea that chance begets order . . . was at that time put into its clearest light. (Peirce 1893, p. 183) Sincethe turnof the century,however,andespeciallysince the thirties, evolutionistshavefurtherappealedto chancein ways thatDarwinhimself might contemptuouslyhave regardedas higgledy-piggledyviews of nature.Indeed,proponentsof one such appealhave coined the term "nonDarwinianevolution"to distancetheirviews fromhis. Actually,the new appealsto chancehave been mattersof considerabledispute. And today those disputesare amongthe liveliest in the alreadylively field of evolutionarybiology. The following discussionis an attemptto sort out some of the broad issuesinvolvedin these disputes.The most generalquestionat issue concernsthe relativeevolutionaryimportanceof "randomdrift"vs. natural selection.But what does that mean?In the first half of this paper(Sections 2-3), I will try to make sense of that question. That will involve explainingthe sense in which evolution by randomdrift is, properly to evolutionby naturalselection. Darwindid speaking,an "alternative" not conceiveof chanceas anythinglike an alternativeto naturalselection, butratheras "complimentary" to naturalselection.Modernevolutionists, on the otherhand, recognizealternativeas well as complimentaryroles of chanceandnaturalselection.And yet, on some commonconstrualsof "naturalselection",it is difficult (if not impossible)even to distinguish evolutionby randomdrift from evolutionby naturalselection. Thus, in orderto construeevolutionby randomdrift and evolutionby naturalselectionas properalternatives,the conceptof naturalselectionitself must first be properlyinterpreted.Unfortunately,though, even on a proper interpretation of "naturalselection",it is difficultto distinguishbetween This content downloaded on Fri, 4 Jan 2013 16:36:51 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions CHANCEAND NATURALSELECTION 185 whatI call the "improbable resultsof naturalselection"andevolutionby randomdrift. In the secondhalf of this paper(Section4-5), I discuss the varietyof positionstakenby evolutionistswith respectto the evolutionaryimportanceof randomdriftvs. naturalselection.I will thenconsiderthe variety of issues in questionin terms of a conceptualdistinctionoften used to describethe rise of probabilisticthinkingin the sciences. I will argue, in particular,thatwhatis going on hereis not, as mightappearat first sight, just anotherdisputeaboutthe desirabilityof "stochastic"vs. "deterministic"theories.Modemevolutionistsdo not argueso muchaboutwhether evolutionis stochastic,but abouthow stochasticit is. 2. Chance in Darwinian Evolutionary Theory. Darwin usually invoked "chance"(or "accident")in the contextof discussionsabouthow variations,the materialsof evolution, arise. His notion of "chancevariation"was especiallyimportantfor the purposeof distinguishinghis own theoryof evolutionfrom the older "use and disuse"theory (Hodge and Kohnforthcoming).So a briefdiscussionof the differencesbetweenthose theoriesmightbe helpful. The paradigmapplicationof the theoryof use anddisuseis the accountof the evolutionof giraffesfromshorter-necked, four-footedgrazers.As the accountgoes, the ancestorsof giraffesfound in whichtheyhadlittleuponwhichto graze, themselvesin an environment otherthanleaves of trees. They stretchedtheir necks to reachmore and moreleaves, andwerephysicallymodifiedin the process.Theiroffspring inheritedthe modification-i.e., having longer necks as juveniles than theirparentshad as juveniles. The offspringalso stretchedto reachmore and more leaves, lengtheningtheir necks even beyond the length inherited. The thirdgenerationinheritedthe furthermodification.And so on, until all the descendantsof the originalgroup were quite long-necked. Theimportantpointhereconcernshow the variationsthataid the survival of theirpossessorsfirstarose-namely, in responseto the survivalneeds of theirpossessors.Thatis, the chanceof such a variationoccurringwas increasedby the very fact thatthe organismneededit to survive. On the Darwinianaccount,we are askedto considerwhat would have happenedif, amongthe shorter-neckedancestors,some slightly longerneckedoffspringhappened"by chance"to be born.Thosewho happened to have the slightly longer necks would be able to reach slightly more food, and hence would slightly outsurviveand outreproducethe others. Assumingthat neck lengthwas inheritable,then, a slightly greaterproportionof the next generationthan of the previousgenerationwould be longer-necked.This processalone wouldresultin an ever-increasingfrequencyof the slightlylonger-neckedindividuals.But now considerwhat would happenif, among those slightly longer-neckedorganisms, some This content downloaded on Fri, 4 Jan 2013 16:36:51 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions JOHNBEATTY 186 slightly even longer-neckedoffspringhappenedby chance to be born. the others.Thus, Thesein turnwouldslightlyoutsurviveandoutreproduce the proportionsof longer-and longer-neckedindividualswould increase fromgenerationto generation,untilthe presentproportionswere reached. The importantpointfor now concernshow, accordingto the Darwinian account,the variationsthataid the survivalandreproductionof theirpossessorsfirst arise. They do not, as on the use-and-disuseaccount, arise in responseto the survivaland reproductiveneeds of their possessors. Onthe otherhand,whetheror not they furtherincreasein frequencydoes dependon whetherthey serve those needs. But the probabilityof a particularvariationoccurringin an individualis not increasedby the fact that that variationwould promotethe survivaland reproductionof that individual.In that sense, it is a matterof "chance"that an organism would be bornwith a variationthatpromotesits survivaland reproduction, though, again, not a matterof chance that that variationfurther increasesin frequencyin subsequentgenerations.As Darwinthus distinguishedhis accountfrom the use-and-disuseaccount,the latterexplains the evolutionof adaptationin a way "analogousto a blacksmithhaving childrenwith strongarms",while the formerrelies on "theotherprinciple of those childrenwhich chanceproducedwith strongarms,outlivingthe weakerones" (Darwin 1839, passage 42). As Darwin elsewhere more eloquentlyexplainedthe notionof chancevariation, [Evolutionby naturalselection] absolutelydependson what we in our ignorancecall spontaneousor accidentalvariability.Let an architectbe compelledto buildan edificewith uncutstones, fallen from a precipice.The shape of each fragmentmay be called accidental. Yet the shape of each has been determined . . . by events and cir- cumstances,all of which dependon naturallaws; but there is no relationbetweenthese laws and the purposefor which each fragment is used by the builder. In the same mannerthe variationsof each creatureare determinedby fixed and immutablelaws; but these bear no relationto the living structurewhich is slowly built up through the power of selection. . . . (Darwin 1887, Vol. 2, p. 236) Thereare several, more generalnotions of chance in terms of which one mighttry to understandthe notionof chancevariation.Thereis, for instance, the naturaltheological notion of chance vs. intelligently intendedoccurrences.There is also the old Aristoteliannotion of chance as coincidence.Or we mightinvokethe Laplaceannotionof chance, not in orderto say anythingaboutthe event in questionitself, butjust as an admissionof ignoranceconcerningthe causalchainof eventsthatresulted in thatevent.It seemsto me possibleto makea case for construingchance variationin each of these ways-Darwin sometimesseems to have fa- This content downloaded on Fri, 4 Jan 2013 16:36:51 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions CHANCE AND NATURAL SELECTION 187 voredone, andthen at othertimes anothermoregeneralmeaning.Sometimes he spoke of chance variationsin contrastwith benevolently intended, useful variations.Sometimeshe meant that it was a matterof coincidencethata usefulvariationshouldarise. And sometimeshe seems only to have wantedto leave entirelyopen the questionof how variations arise-thus makingclearthathis theoryof evolutiondid not rely on the are suguse and disuse accountof thatprocess. All threeinterpretations gested, for instance, by the quotationabove! (See also Ghiselin 1969, Schweber1982, and Sheynin 1980 with regardto these more general conceptsof chance variation.)But perhapsthe most importantthing to consideris whatis distinguishablyDarwinianaboutthe notionof chance variation.And thatis, I think,best broughtout simply in contrastto the use and disuse theoriesof evolution,from which Darwinwantedto distancehimself. 3. Chance in Modern Evolutionary Theory: Distinctions. 3.1 The disputeconcerningthe relativeevolutionaryimportanceof naturalselection vs. randomdriftraises genuinelynew issues concerningthe role of chancein evolution.Whatis not at issue is the role of chancein evolution as Darwinconceivedit (exceptinsofaras he too narrowlyconceivedit). Modernevolutionistsassume,thatis, thatvariationsareindeed"random" in the sense intendedby Darwin.As one contemporaryevolutionistputs it, "Mutationis randomin [the sense] that the chance that a specific mutation will occur is not affected by how useful that mutation would be" (Futuyma1979, p. 249). ButwhileDarwinconsideredthe originof variationsa matterof chance, he did not considerthe possibilitythattheirevolutionaryfates might also be a matterof chance. In particular,he attributedtheirevolutionaryfates to naturalselectionin or againsttheirfavor. Naturalselectiontook over wherechancevariationleft off: those organismsthatwere by chancebetter equippedto survive and reproduceactually outsurvivedand outreproducedthe organismsthatwere by chanceless well equipped,andthus advantageousvariationsincreasedin frequencyfrom generationto generation.In Darwin'sscheme,in otherwords,chanceandnaturalselection were "consecutive"ratherthan "alternative"stages of the evolutionary process.With the introductionof the conceptof randomdrift, however, camethe notionthatthe fate of a chancevariationmightitself be a matter of chance-i.e., the conceptthat chance and naturalselection might be alternativeratherthanjust consecutivestagesof the evolutionaryprocess. But what does it meanto attributethe evolutionaryfate of a variation to naturalselection vs. randomdrift?The distinctionwill be easier to make if we confine our discussionto the fates of genetic variations.It will be useful,in otherwords,to thinkof evolutionarychangesas changes This content downloaded on Fri, 4 Jan 2013 16:36:51 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 188 JOHNBEATTY in the gene andgenotypefrequenciesof populations.(TheAppendixconsists of a review of genetic terminologythat some readersmight find useful at this point.) Thus, the kinds of evolutionarychangesthat I will be talkingaboutare changesof the following sort. Of the alleles (genes) at a particulargeneticlocus of membersof one generationof a particular population,50% are of type A and 50% are of type a. Of the genotypes with respectto that locus, 25% are of the type AA, 50% are of the type Aa, and 25% are of the type aa. Of the alleles at that locus of members of a later generationof thatpopulation,80% are of type A and 20% are of type a. And of the genotypeswith respectto that locus of members of the latergeneration,70% are of the type AA, 20% are of the type Aa, and 10%are of the type aa. Thoughdefinitionsof "evolution"in termsof suchgene- andgenotypefrequencychangesare common(e.g., Wilson and Bossert 1971, p. 20), I recognizethat we actuallyincludemore thanjust that kind of change underthe term "evolution"(see Brandon1978). This restriction,however, simplifiesthe following discussionenormously. 3.2 I will rely, for the time being, on your intuitionsabout what it meansto attributegene- and genotype-frequencychanges to naturalselection. Whatdoes it mean to attributethe same to randomdrift?Since as early as 1932 (Dubininand Romaschoff1932; see also Dobzhansky 1937, p. 129), a popularapproachto the expositionof randomdrift has been via a classic means of modelling chance processes-namely, the blinddrawingof beadsfrom an urn. The beads in this case are allelesthe differentalleles are differentcolors, but they are otherwiseindistinguishableby the blindfoldedsamplingagent. One urnof beadsrepresents one generationof alleles-a finite number,characterizedby particular allele frequencies.The next generationof alleles is determinedby a blind drawingof beads from an urn. This second generationof alleles fills a new urn, blinddrawingsfrom which determinethe frequenciesof alleles in the thirdgeneration.And so on. The frequenciesof alleles may differ from urn to urn-generation to generation-as a result of the fact that beads sampledby blind drawfrequenciesof otherwiseindistinguishable ings may not be representativeof the frequenciesin the urnsfrom which the samplesweredrawn.Theprobabilityof drawinga representativesample froma populationof a givenfinitesize is easy to calculate-the smaller the population,the smallerthatprobability. Such blind samplingcould take at least two forms in nature.The first formis whatmightbe called "indiscriminate parentsampling".By "parent sampling" I mean the process of determining which organisms of one generation will be parents of the next, and how many offspring each par- ent will have. This sort of samplingmight be "indiscriminate"in the This content downloaded on Fri, 4 Jan 2013 16:36:51 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions CHANCE AND NATURAL SELECTION 189 sense that any physical differencesbetween the organismsof one generationmightbe irrelevantto differencesin theiroffspringcontributions. A forestfire, for instance,might so sampleparents-killing some, sparing some-without regardto physical differencesbetween them. Such samplingis indiscriminatein the same sense in which the usualmodel of blinddrawingof beadsfrom an urnis indiscriminate-thatis, any physical differences(e.g., color)betweenthe entitiesin questionareirrelevant to whetheror not they are sampled. If a populationis so maintainedat a particularfinite size-i.e., by samplingparentsindiscriminately-itsgene and genotypefrequencieswill "drift"from generationto generation.The reason is that the genotype frequenciesof the parents,weightedaccordingto theirreproductivesuccess, may by chancenot be representativeof the genotypefrequenciesof the parents'generation.Thereis no formof discriminationto ensurethat the genotypefrequenciesare representative.To the extent that a parent sampleis unrepresentative, and to the extentthatthe gene and genotype frequenciesof the next generationreflectthe appropriately weightedgene andgenotypefrequenciesof theirparents,the next generation'sgene and genotypefrequenciesmay diverge from those of the previous generation-i.e., an evolutionarychangemay occur. Blind samplingin naturemight also take the form of "indiscriminate gametesampling".(This paragraphand the next can be skippedwithout much loss.) By "gametesampling"I mean the process of determining which of the two genetically different types of gametes produced by a heterozygoticparent is actually contributed to each of its offspring. This sort of samplingmight be indiscriminatein the sense that any physical differencebetweenthe two types of gametesproducedby a heterozygote mightbe irrelevantto whetherone or the otheris actuallycontributedto anyparticularoffspring.Accordingto Mendel'sLaw (see the Appendix), thereis no physicalbasis for a bias in the proportionsof the two genetically differenttypes of gametesproducedby a heterozygote.What we are now consideringis that there is also no physical basis for a bias in the proportionsof gametes that are actuallycontributedto a heterozygote's offspring. If a populationis so maintainedat a particularfinite size-i.e., by samplingthe gametes of heterozygotesindiscriminately-the gene and genotypefrequenciesof the populationwill driftfrom generationto generation.For the gene frequenciesof the gametes that are contributedto a generationof offspringmay by chancenot be representativeof the gene frequenciesof the parents'generation.Again, there is no form of discriminationto ensurethat they are representative.Thus, indiscriminate gametesampling,eithertogetherwith indiscriminateparentsampling,or alone, can result in an evolutionarychange, a so-called "randomdrift" of gene and genotypefrequencies. This content downloaded on Fri, 4 Jan 2013 16:36:51 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 190 JOHN BEATTY Some authorsconstruerandomdriftentirelyin termsof indiscriminate parentsampling(e.g., Sheppard1967, pp. 126-127). More often, randomdriftis construedentirelyin termsof indiscriminategametesampling (e.g., Wilson and Bossert 1971, p. 83). But these two processesare importantlysimilaragentsof change-both involvingelementsof randomin the same sense in both cases. Accordingto ness, and "randomness" this sense of "randomness", samplingfroma populationis randomwhen each memberof the populationhas the same chance of being sampled. Thisis a commonnotionof randomsampling-e.g., accordingto a philosophicalintroductionto probabilitytheory, a samplingproceduregives randomsamplesif: 1. Eachmemberof the populationhas an equalprobabilityof being selectedas the first memberof the sample. 2. Each memberof the population,excludingthose selected as previous membersof the sample, has an equal chance of being selected as the nth memberof the sample(Skyrms1966, pp. 146147; see also Hacking1965, pp. 118-132). Discussionsof randomdrift, pedagogicalor otherwise, generally do not includediscussionsof the conceptsof "randomness"and "chance". Rather,evolutionistshave, in general, simply relied on what is an exemplarymodel of randomsamplingin the literatureof probability,statistics, and philosophy-i.e., the blind drawingof beads from an urn. Evolutionistsare not, in general,inclinedto defend any particularinterpretationof "randomness". It is enough,for theirpurposes,to say of any processin naturethatis sufficientlysimilarto theirbead-drawingmodel of randomdrift,thatevolutionin this case is as mucha matterof "random sampling"and "chance"as are the exemplarycases of randomsampling uponwhich probabilists,statisticians,and philosophersrely. In whatfollows, in comparingrandomdriftto naturalselection, I will be discussingonly randomdrift via indiscriminateparentsampling,not via indiscriminategamete sampling.So, in effect, I will be contrasting naturalselectionof parentsand indiscriminateparentsampling.I could alsocontrastnaturalselectionof gameteswith indiscriminategametesampling, but thatwill not be necessaryin orderto makethe kinds of points thatI want to make. 3.3 Naturalselectionis not randomsamplingin the sense of "random" just discussed.Naturalselection is, as its name suggests, a discriminate form of sampling-a samplingprocess that discriminates,in particular, on the basis of fitness differences.The generalissue involvedin the disputesconcerningthe relativeevolutionaryimportanceof randomdriftvs. naturalselection, then, boils down to the questionof the relativeevolu- This content downloaded on Fri, 4 Jan 2013 16:36:51 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions CHANCE AND NATURAL SELECTION 191 tionary importance of sampling without regard to fitness differences vs. sampling with regard to fitness differences. But I cannot unpack this issue without first discussing briefly the notion of fitness. For according to the most common conception of fitness, the distinction between random drift and natural selection of the fittest dissolves, and along with it dissolves the issue of the relative evolutionary importance of the two supposedly different sorts of processes. According to the most common definition of "fitness", the fitness of an organism is a measure of its actual reproductive success. I. M. Lerner's definition of "fitness" is typical in this regard-according to Lerner, "the organismswho have more offspring are fitter in the Darwinian sense" (Lerner 1958, p. 10; see also Waddington 1968, p. 19; Mettler and Gregg 1969, p. 93; Crow and Kimura 1970, p. 5; Dobzhansky 1970, pp. 101102; Wilson 1975, p. 585; Grant 1977, p. 66). Along the same lines, the fitness of a genotype is the actual average offspring contribution of organisms of that type. For instance, to say that organisms of type AA are fitter than organisms of type aa is to say that organisms of the first type actually leave a higher average number of offspring. But if fitness is so construed, then it is not clear what the supposed distinction between natural selection of the fittest (i.e., sampling on the basis of fitness differences), and sampling without regard to fitness differences, amounts to. How could parent sampling be anything other than fitness discriminating, when the organisms that leave the most offspring are by definition the fittest? On this conception of fitness, all parent sampling processes are fitness discriminating. Consider, for instance, the proposed bead-drawing models of selection that are based on this notion of fitness-those models are indistinguishable from the bead-drawing models of random drift. Consider, in particular, the bead game called "Selection", described by Manfred Eigen and Ruth Schuster in their otherwise thoughtful book, Laws of the Game (Eigen and Schuster 1981, pp. 49-65). The game requires a checkerboard, the playing squares of which are identified by coordinates, and are occupied by colored beads, one bead per square. To begin, the beads that cover the board are of at least two colors-in whatever initial frequencies desired. The roll of two dice (each of which has the appropriatenumber of sides) picks out a square on the board. A bead of whatever color occupies that squareis used to replace whatever color is on the square picked out by the next roll of the dice. This is followed by another color-determining roll, followed by another color-replacing roll. And so on, until eventually one color fills the entire board. This is supposed to represent selection of the fittest color, where the fittest color is, as Eigen and Schuster put it, "the one that turns out to be the winner" (1981, p. 55). This is also, of course, just indiscriminate This content downloaded on Fri, 4 Jan 2013 16:36:51 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 192 JOHN BEATTY sampling.Indeed, Eigen and Schustersay of their model that "We are faced with the paradoxthat the selective process producesa winner in everygamethoughcompetitorsdo not differfromeachotherat all" (1981, p. 55). Unfortunately,Eigen and Schusterare not just calling this game "Selection",they actuallyintendto explicatethe concept of Darwinian selectionin termsof the game. But if this is a properexplicationof selection, then the problemof the relativeevolutionaryimportanceof random driftvs. naturalselectionis a pseudo-problem-thereis no difference betweenthem. Thereis, however, anotherconceptionof fitness that keeps the issue alive. To motivatethis conceptionbriefly, considerthe example of two geneticallyidenticaltwins, one of whomis struckby lightningandkilled, the otherof whom is spared.As a result, say, the formerleaves no offspring,while the lattergoes on to be a parent.We balk at the consequencesaccordingto our conceptionof fitness. That is, we hesitate to attributezero fitness to the formertwin and relativelyhigh fitness to his geneticallyidentical,but seeminglyluckierbrother. One way of accommodatingthese intuitionsis to identify the fitness of an organismnot with the actualnumberof offspringit contributes,but with the number of offspring that it is physically disposed to contribute (Brandon1978, Mills andBeatty 1979, Sober 1980, Burian1983). Along the same lines, we can talk aboutthe fitness of a genotypein terms of the averagenumberof offspringthatpossessorsof thatgenotypearephysically disposedto contribute. On this conceptionof fitness, the two physicallyidenticaltwins, who mustbe physicallydisposedto contributethe same numberof offspring, are equallyfit. Hence we can say of the lightningthat killed one and sparedthe other, that it did not sample the twins on the basis of their fitnesses-it was not an agent of naturalselection. It was clearly an indiscriminatesamplingagent-indiscriminate,thatis, withregardto physical fitness differencesbetweenthe organismssampled. 3.4 Thatis perhapsas muchaboutfitness as we reallyneed to discuss in orderto makemeaningfulthe issue concerningthe relativeevolutionary importanceof randomdriftvs. naturalselection. But I am afraidthat, as muchas I wouldlike the distinctionbetweennaturalselectionandrandom driftto be a clear-cutone, it is not as clear-cutas the precedingdiscussion suggests.(ElliottSoberandKennethWatershelpedme considerablywith the following discussion.)In orderto complicatematterssomewhat,let me elaboratea bit upon the notionof "fitness". First,it is importantto recognizethatthe fitness of an organismis the numberof offspringit is physicallydisposedto contributein a particularlyspecifiedenvironment.For instance,the numberof offspringthat a This content downloaded on Fri, 4 Jan 2013 16:36:51 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions CHANCE AND NATURAL SELECTION 193 dark-coloredmoth is disposedto contributeis greaterin a darkenvironmentin which it is effectively camouflagedfrom its predators,thanin a light environmentin which it is more conspicuous.So all attributionsof levels of fitness mustbe relativeto particularlyspecifiedenvironments. The specificationof the environment,in turn, involves specifying a rangeof circumstances,each weightedaccordingto the likelihoodof its occurrence,or accordingto the likelihoodof the organism(s)in question experiencingit. So one changesthe environment,so to speak, by changing eitherthe qualityor the weightingof the componentenvironmental circumstances.The abilityof the darkmoth to surviveand reproducein a uniformlydarkenvironmentis presumablydifferentfrom its ability in a three-fourthsdarkenvironment,and that is presumablydifferentfrom its abilityin a half-darkenvironment,and so on. The environmentalcircumstancesrelativeto which fitness values are ascribedto membersof a populationare, ideally, all the environmental circumstancesrelevantto determiningdifferencesbetweenthe reproductive successesof those organisms.Some of these factorsdiscriminatebetween the organismson the basis of fitness differencesbetween them. For instance,the combinationof a darkbackgroundand color-sensitive birds favors the reproductivesuccess of dark moths over light moths, because of the difference in their color. Some other factors among the specifiedenvironmental circumstancesmay be responsiblefor differences in reproductivesuccess, butnot in connectionwith any fitnessdifferences betweenthe organismsin question.Forestfires, for instance,might kill and sparemothswithoutregardto any fitness differencesbetweenthem. Not only the formerfactors, but also the latterbelong in the environmentalspecificationsrelativeto which fitness values are ascribed.Dark mothsmay be able to leave more offspringthanlight moths in environmentsin whichthe backgroundis darkandthe majorpredatorsare color sensitive,andin whichforestfires arerare.But darkandlight mothsmay have roughlythe same offspring-contribution dispositionsin an environment in which forest fires are very frequent,even if the backgroundis otherwisedarkandthe majorpredatorsare color sensitive. Similarly,the darkand light moths might have roughlyequal fitnesses in an environment in which theirpredatorsare color insensitive. At any rate, relative to an environmentalspecificationin terms of weightedenvironmentalcircumstances,there is a range of numbersof offspringthat an organismis more or less disposed to contribute.For instance,in an environmentmadeup of 60%dark-coloredtrees and 40% light-coloredtrees, a darkmothhas a chanceof visitingmoreor less than 60%darktrees, andmoreor less tharn 40%light trees. Given its physical structure,it may leave somewhatmoreoffspringif it landson more dark trees and somewhatfewer if it lands on fewer darktrees. This content downloaded on Fri, 4 Jan 2013 16:36:51 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 194 JOHN BEATTY So for an organism in a particularly specified environment, there is a range of possible offspring contributions. And for each number within the range, there is a greater or lesser ability on the part of the organism to leave that number. Accordingly, we can talk about fitness distributions relative to specified environments. For instance, relative to a particularly specified environment, an organism might have a fitness distribution like the one in Diagram 1. Here the x-axis represents the range of offspring contributions, and the y-axis represents the strength of the organism's ability to leave the corresponding number on the x-axis. DIAGRAM1 Somewhat alternatively, we can view this distribution as a probability distributionof offspring contributions, where the x-axis again represents the range of offspring contributions, and the y-axis the probability that the organism will contribute the corresponding number on the x-axis. The probabilities should, however, be interpreted as strengths of the organism's physical ability to contribute various numbers of offspring, in line with a propensity interpretationof probability (Brandon 1978, Mills and Beatty 1979). We can also construct a fitness distribution for a genotype. The range of this distribution would consist of the union of the ranges of possible offspring contributions of the individual members of the genotype. The height of the distribution at any point along the extended range would represent the group's average probability of leaving that many offspring. Now the last thing I want to do in connection with this very general discussion of random drift, natural selection, and fitness, is to consider a possible scenario that requires that we give a bit more thought to the distinction between natural selection of the fittest and the indiscriminate sampling sources of random drift. How distinguishable are they, after all? Imagine again the case of the light and dark moths and their color-sensitive predators. Imagine too that they inhabit a forest in which 40% of the trees have light-colored bark and 60% have dark-colored bark. In this environment, we would say that the dark-colored moths are fitter, since the forest provides more camouflage for them than for the light moths. The fitness distributions of finite numbers of the two types might thus differ in the way shown in Diagram 2. This content downloaded on Fri, 4 Jan 2013 16:36:51 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions CHANCEAND NATURALSELECTION 195 Dark Light DIAGRAM2 But supposethatin one particulargeneration,we find, amongremains of the mothskilled by predators,a greaterproportionof darkmothsthan was characteristic of the populationas a whole, and a smallerproportion of light moths than was characteristicof the population.Say the actual averageoffspringcontributionsof the two types of mothsin the previous generation differed as in Diagram 3. And finally, let us say that we find the remains so distributedin the areas of dark and light trees that we have reason to believe that the dark moths were perched on light trees when attacked,and the light moths on dark trees. In other words, the dark mothschancedto land on light trees more frequentlythanon darktrees, even thoughthe frequencyof darktrees was greater. Xd XI Xd = Actualaveragenumberof offspringof darkmoths in E x= = Actualaveragenumberof offspringof light moths in E DIAGRAM 3 That's the scenario. The question it raises is this. Is the change in fre- quencyof genes and genotypesin questiona matterof naturalselection, or a matterof randomdrift?Thatis, is the changein questionthe result of samplingdiscriminatelyor indiscriminatelywith regardto fitness differences?It is not easy to maintainthatthe samplingwas entirelyindiscriminatewith regardto differencesin survivaland reproductiveability. At least it is difficult to maintain that the death by predation of conspicis indiscriminate sampling,whereas uously darkmothsin this environment the deathof conspicuously light mothsin the same environmentis selec- tion. On the otherhand,it is also difficultto maintainthatselectionalone This content downloaded on Fri, 4 Jan 2013 16:36:51 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 196 JOHN BEATTY is the basis of the change. At least, it is difficult to maintainthat the fittestwere selected. The problemhere, I think, is thatit is difficultto distinguishbetween random drift on the one hand, and the improbable results of natural se- lectionon the otherhand. Whereverthereare fitness distributionsassociatedwith differenttypesof organisms,therewill be rangesof outcomes of naturalselection-some of the outcomeswithin those rangeswill be moreprobablethanothers,but all of the outcomeswithinthe rangesare possibleoutcomesof naturalselection. And yet some outcomeswithin a fitnessdistribution(the outer-lyingoutcomesof a bell-shapedfitness distribution,for instance), are in a sense "less representative"of the offabilitiesof the organismsin question.Considera coinspring-contribution tossing analogy. "Fiftyheads: fifty tails" and "ninetyheads: ten tails" arebothpossibleoutcomesof one hundredflips of a fair coin, where by "faircoin" I meana coin equallydisposedto landheadsup and tails up. And yet "ninetyheads: ten tails" is in a sense less representativeof the fairnessof the coin. So too in the case of the light and darkmothsjust discussed,the actualaverageoffspringcontributionsshown in Diagram 3 are possibleresultsof naturalselection, but not very "representative" of the fitnesses of the light and dark moths. To the extent that those outcomesare less representativeof the physicalabilitiesof those organisms to surviveand reproducein the environmentin question, any evolutionarychange that results will be more a matterof randomdrift. In otherwords,it seems thatwe mustsay of some evolutionarychangesthat they are to some extent, or in some sense, a matterof naturalselection and to some extent, or in some sense, a matterof randomdrift. And the reason (one of the reasons)we must say this is that it is conceptually difficultto distinguishnaturalselectionfromrandomdrift,especiallywhere improbable results of natural selection are concerned. Even given these difficultiesof conceptualanalysis, though, the new conceptionof the role of chance in evolution clearly goes beyond Darwin's conceptions,and raises questionsthat did not arise for him. In Darwin'sscheme of things, recall, chance events and naturalselection were consecutiveratherthan alternativestages of the evolutionaryprocess. Therewas no questionas to which was more importantat a particularstage. But now thatwe have the conceptof randomdrifttakingover whererandomvariationleaves off, we arefacedwithjust such a question. Thatis, given chance variations,are furtherchanges in the frequencies of those variationsmore a matterof chance or more a matterof natural selection? 4. Chance in Modern Evolutionary Theory: Issues. 4.1 As I suggestedearlier,thereare at least two versionsof this generalquestion.At This content downloaded on Fri, 4 Jan 2013 16:36:51 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions CHANCE AND NATURAL SELECTION 197 issue in the first version is the extent of so-called selectively "neutral" mutations.The mostlikely candidatesfor this title werediscoveredduring the molecular-biologyboom of the fifties and sixties. It was discovered then that differentpermutationsof the sequencesof bases that make up DNA code for differentaminoacids. But it was also discoveredthatthe sequenceof bases that codes for a particularamino acid can sometimes be changedin a certainway such thatthe same aminoacid is produced. These were called "synonymous"changes, in the informationlanguage of the field. It is certainlya plausibleenoughsuggestionthatsynonymous changeshave no effect on the numbersof offspringwhich organismsare physicallydisposedto contribute.Claimsfor neutralityhave, however, also been extendedto grosserphenotypicdifferences,from single aminoacid differencesbetweenproteinsof the same functionalfamily, to differencesbetweenbloodtypes(Wright1940),to differencesbetweenbanding patternson snail shells (Diver 1940). Manysuch changeshave not, upon firstthought,had any imaginableeffect on the numbersof offspringthat theirpossessorswere physicallydisposedto contribute. Samplingamongsuch alternativeswouldbe indiscriminatewith regard to fitnessdifferences,simplybecausetherewouldbe no such differences. As JackKing andThomasJukesexpressedthe basic idea in theirclassic positionpaper,"Naturalselectionis the editor,ratherthanthe composer, of the genetic message. One thing the editor does not do is to remove changeswhich it is unableto perceive"(King and Jukes 1969, p. 788). As a result of this sort of indiscriminatesampling, the frequenciesof neutralgeneticalternativesmay drift.In the wordsof the self-styled"neutralists",the "fates"of these geneticalternativesare mattersof "chance" (e.g., Nei 1975, p. 165). very sophisticated, Theneutralisttheoryof evolutionis mathematically thoughsome of its featurescan be discussed informally.The theory is in the sense that, given the gene "stochastic"ratherthan "deterministic", and genotypefrequenciesof one generation,and values for all the other variablesof the theory(like the size of the population),one can at best calculatethe probabilitiesof possible gene and genotypefrequenciesin successivegenerations.It is not possible to predictone specific gene or genotypefrequencyfor each successive generation. Diagram4 is an exampleof the sorts of calculationsthat the theory allows(fromRoughgarden1979, p. 62). In this case, we aretalkingabout an infinitenumberof populations,each of which has a constantsize of 8 individuals,and each of which starts off with gene frequenciesof 0.5 A and0.5 a-i.e., 8 A alleles and 8 a alleles. This is representedby the top distribution,a barthatsignifiesthat 100%of the populationshave 8 A genes at time t = 0. Accordingto the theory, over the course of generations,the distributionof populationsspreadsout with respect to This content downloaded on Fri, 4 Jan 2013 16:36:51 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 198 JOHN BEATTY 1.0 .8 t= 0 .6 i .2 l .8 .6 .4 .2 l Il t= ll 1 0 .8 t= 4 .6 _t= 4~ .4 0 _ C L VI4-----~-4--I-Li iiiii I .8 .o t= 7 .6 .4 ? .2 0 .8 t= 10 .6 .4.2 1 .8 t= 20 .6 .4 .2 0 . 0 l 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 Numberof A alleles in populationi DIAGRAM4 the frequency of A allels in each, until finally all of the populations have either no A alleles, or 100% A alleles (i.e., either 0 or 16 A alleles). We cannot predict whether or not a particularpopulation will have, say, 50% A and 50% a alleles after one generation, but we can predict the probability that it will be 50: 50, in terms of the proportion of populations that will still be 50: 50 after one generation. The probability is about 0.2. Diagram 5 is a somewhat more general way of representing what Diagram 4 represents. This is the first of such diagrams, from Sewall Wright's pioneering 1931 work on drift. According to the diagram, the frequencies of populations with all or none of a particular allele increase faster, the smaller the population size N. That is, of course, just a glimpse of the general theory of the random This content downloaded on Fri, 4 Jan 2013 16:36:51 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 199 CHANCE AND NATURAL SELECTION "Rateof decay"of variability 1/2N I 4 0 0 0.25 0.5 0.75 1.0 Allele frequency DIAGRAM 5 drift of frequencies of selectively neutral genetic alternatives. But even that glimpse is important for our purposes. It is important, too, that we consider the sorts of issues that divide investigators in this area. There are more specific as well as more general issues. The more specific issues concern whether or not a change in frequency of a specific set of genetic alternatives can be ascribed to their selective neutrality and the consequent random drift of their frequencies. Complementarily, one might expect that the more general issues concern whether all or no evolutionary changes-or whether all of a certain kind or none of a certain kind of evolutionary change-are due to random drift alone. It is important to recognize, however, that even the most general issues surrounding this version of the importance of random drift do not boil down to questions of all or none, but to questions of more or less. I cannot improve on This content downloaded on Fri, 4 Jan 2013 16:36:51 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 200 JOHNBEATTY DouglasFutuyma'sassessmentof this situation,so I will simply quote it. (I especiallylike this quotationbecause it is from a textbookin evolutionarybiology, and communicatesto studentsof evolutiona valuable lessonconcerningthe natureof evolutionarytheorizing,and of the nature of disputesin thatfield.) The answerto the question,Is enzymepolymorphismdue to selection or drift?will, of course,be: Both. But this is reallyno answerat all. No neutralistwould deny that some few enzymepolymorphismsare maintainedby selection, and even the staunchestselectionistwould not deny that some amino acid substitutionsmust have such trivial effectsthatthey have vanishinglysmalleffects on fitness andso fluctuate in gene frequencyby drift alone. The real question is, What to each factor . . .? (Futuyma fractionof the variationis attributable 1979, p. 340) Similarly,MasatoshiNei, a principlefigure in the neutralistdisputes, characterizesthe strongestneutralistposition as only "a majorityrule" (1975, p. 165). As he explains,even the strongestneutralistpositiondoes not rule out selectionwith regardto some sets of genetic alternatives.It assertsinsteadthat the majorityof gene-frequencychanges involve selectivelyneutralalternatives.Motoo Kimura,perhapsthe principalneutralist,has emphasizedover andover againthe slackin his relativelyvery strongposition.As he recentlyreported,along these lines, . . .in one of my paperson the neutraltheory (Kimura1968), I wrote: "the recent findings of 'degeneracy'of DNA code, that is, existence of two or more base tripletscoding for the same amino acid, seem to suggest that neutralmutationsmay not be as rare as previouslyconsidered."However,I also addeda note of caution:"It is importantto note thatprobablynot all synonymousmutationsare neutral,even if most of them are nearlyso.'"Perhapsthis was a pertinentstatementin lightof the recentfindingthatsynonymouscodons or unequalfashion (Kimura1981). are often used in "non-random" (Kimura1982, p. 8) 4.2 Theproponentsof the secondversionof the importanceof random driftdiscouragedividingevolutionarychangesinto those due entirelyto naturalselectionandthose due to randomdriftwith no role for selection. They encourage,instead, analysisof the evolutionaryeffects of natural selectionand indiscriminatesamplingacting concurrently.That is, they ratherencouragedividingevolutionarychangesinto those due predominantlyto naturalselection,those duepredominantlyto randomdrift, and those in which naturalselection and randomdrift both play important This content downloaded on Fri, 4 Jan 2013 16:36:51 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions CHANCE AND NATURAL SELECTION 201 roles. Consider, for instance, Wright's criticism of the evolutionary perspective of R. A. Fisher and E. B. Ford-that they misconstrued the importance-of-driftproblem: They hold that fluctuations of gene frequencies of evolutionary significance must be supposed to be due either wholly to variations in selection (which they accept) or to accidents of sampling. The antithesis is to be rejected. The fluctuations of some genes are undoubtedly governed largely by violently shifting conditions of selection. But for others in the same populations, accidents of sampling should be much more important and for still others both may play significant roles. It is a question of the relative values of certain coefficients (Wright 1948, p. 291, emphases added). Wright's criticism was twofold. First, he was warning against reducing the importance-of-driftquestion to an all-or-none neutralism issue-i.e., to an issue concerning whether all or no evolutionary changes are due to randomdrift with no role for selection. This is an issue that I just claimed was not really an issue with regard to the neutralist version of the importance of drift. And Fisher and Ford also denied being concerned with it (Fisher and Ford 1950, p. 175). But Wright was also warning against reducing the importance-of-drift question to even a more-or-less neutralism issue-i.e., to an issue concerning whether more or fewer evolutionary changes are due to random drift with no role for selection. Wright considered that the proper version of the importance of random drift relative to natural selection was one that concerned the concurrent relative roles of indiscriminate and selective sampling in accounting for evolutionary change with regard to each set of genetic alternatives. As Theodosius Dobzhansky, following Wright, also expressed this version, An evolutionary change need not be due either to directed or to random processes [for example, either to natural selection or to indiscriminate sampling]; quite probably it is the result of a combination of both types. The theoretically desirable and rarely achieved aim of investigation is to quantify the respective contributions of the different factors of gene frequency change, as well as their interactions. (Dobzhansky 1970, p. 231) As for the various ways in which selective and indiscriminate sampling can act concurrently, several possibilities come to mind. The change in frequencies of A and a genes, and AA, Aa, and aa genotypes over the course of generations may be due predominantly to natural selection during some generations, and to indiscriminate sampling during others. Indiscriminate and selective sampling are only loosely "concurrent"in this case. Or the changes in frequencies of those genes and genotypes may This content downloaded on Fri, 4 Jan 2013 16:36:51 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 202 JOHN BEATTY be due to a combination of discriminate parent sampling and indiscriminate gamete sampling, or vice versa. Or the changes may be due to sampling in some geographical subpopulations by entirely indiscriminate sampling agents, like forest fires, while the rest of the population is sampled selectively. Or the changes may be due to the sort of more-or-less selective and more-or-less indiscriminate samplings that I discussed in Section 3.4. The general theory that describes the concurrent roles of random drift and natural selection is, like the neutralist theory, stochastic rather than deterministic-again in the sense that, given the gene and genotype frequencies of one generation, and values for all the other variables of the theory (including, again, size of the population, and in this case fitness values as well), one can at best calculate the probabilities of possible gene and genotype frequencies in successive generations. The general theory includes, among many other things, variations on the U-shaped curves that describe the effects of random drift without selection. For example, Diagrams 6(a) and 6(b), again from Wright's pioneering 1931 work, show the effects of the same variety of selection pressures in small (6a), and then in large (6b) populations. As in Diagrams 4 and 5, we are dealing with proportions of populations and their gene frequencies. So all we can predict about a population with the help of these diagrams is the probability that it will have a particular combination of gene frequencies. Also, as in Diagram 4, all the populations in question had 50: 50 gene frequencies at time t = 0. Diagrams 6(a) and I' O ~ ~~ 0.5 ~ I~S . 1.1005 s= 2/N' 0 0.5 1.0 0 6(a): Population size N 0.5 6(b): Population size N' DIAGRAM6 This content downloaded on Fri, 4 Jan 2013 16:36:51 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 1.0 = 4N CHANCE AND NATURAL SELECTION 203 6(b) show the distributions at some much later time. When there is no selection-represented by the case where the selection coefficient, s, equals zero-the characteristicU-shaped distributionresults, althoughit "squeezes out" more populations with intermediate gene frequencies in the case of the smaller populations. For both the large and small populations, greater selection results in a greater skewing of the curve-that is, more and more of those populations have greater and greater frequencies of the gene whose frequency is represented on the x-axis. But this shows up more clearly in the case of the larger population, where in the case of strong selection for the allele in question (i.e., where s = 2/N), almost all of the populations have between 70% and 100% of that allele; whereas in the case of weaker selection (i.e., where s = 1/2N), many more of the populations have less than 70% of the allele in question. There again you have only a glimpse of a theory, but hopefully a glimpse that will be of some use. Again, somewhat aside from the theory, there are more or less specific and more or less general issues that divide investigators in this area. Specific issues with regard to this version of the importance of drift are those that concern the relative, concurrent importancesof selective and indiscriminatesampling in accountingfor changes in frequency of a specific set of genetic or genotypic frequencies (e.g., Kerr and Wright 1954, Dobzhansky and Pavlovsky 1957, Lamotte 1959). The general issues are, as in the case of the neutralism version of the importance of random drift, more or less issues rather than all or none issues. In other words, the issues do not simply boil down to whether indiscriminate sampling has a certain relative importance in every evolutionarychange, but whether it has a certain relative importance in many evolutionary changes. For instance, Wright, who comes as close as anyone to defending a general position on the relative importance of random drift, nevertheless warns, "There is no theoretical necessity for supposing that evolution has proceeded in the same way in all groups. In some it may proceed largely under direct selection pressure following change of conditions, in other cases it may be determined by random differentiation . . ., with or without selection" (Wright 1940, p. 181). And as Dobzhansky so nicely summed up this version of the importance of random drift, and the general issues associated with it, Since evolution as a biogenic process obviously involves an interaction of all of the [agents of evolutionary change, including natural selection and indiscriminate sampling], the problem of the relative importanceof the different agents presents itself. For years this problem has been the subject of discussion. The results of this discussion so far are notoriously inconclusive. . . . One of the possible sources of the situation may be that a theory which would fit the entire living This content downloaded on Fri, 4 Jan 2013 16:36:51 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 204 JOHN BEATTY world is in general unattainable, since the evolution of the different groups may be guided by different agents. To a certain extent this possibility is undoubtedly correct. In species that occur in great abundance in a fairly continuous area of distribution, the population size factor is bound to be less importantthan in species that are subdivided into numerous local colonies each having a small effective breeding population. [For] organisms whose environment is in the throes of a cataclysmic change, natural selection and mutation pressure are more important than [for] organisms living in a relatively constant environment. Nevertheless, one can hardly eschew trying to sketch some sort of a general picture of evolution. (Dobzhansky 1937, p. 186) I have tried, so far, to distinguish two versions, and two sets of issues, concerning the evolutionary importance of random drift. But, of course, the distinction can be collapsed. As one investigates smaller and smaller fitness differences, one moves from an investigation of the second version of the importance of drift, to the first. Whether-or to the extent thatresearchprogramsinto the two versions of the importance of random drift have maintained separate identities in spite of this sort of conceptual continuity, or whether this continuity has, at times, favored a unified program, is something that I can only say that I would like to know more about. 5. Chance in Nature. At any rate, given a suitable interpretationof fitness and natural selection, there are two more or less distinguishable versions of the evolutionary importance of indiscriminate vs. selective sampling. Now if we step back from these positions and do not concentrate so much on the variety of issues involved, we see in the development of evolutionary biology what we see in the development of so many scientific disciplines in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, namely the rise of stochastic theories. We have already discussed, very briefly, the respects in which evolutionary theories that encompass genetic drift are stochastic vs. deterministic. It might also be helpful to discuss the stochasticity of evolutionary theory by comparing the stochastic "version" of evolutionary theory with the effectively deterministic version that is presented in the opening chapters of most textbooks (prior to the introduction of the stochastic version). The deterministic version, like the stochastic version, is based on the so-called "Hardy-WeinbergLaw". According to that principle, in an infinitely large population in which individuals mate randomly with respect to their geneotypes, and in which there is no selection, mutation, or migration, the gene and genotype frequencies remain at equilibrium. More specifically, if the only alleles at a locus are A and a, and if we represent the proportion of A genes by p and the proportion of a genes by q, the This content downloaded on Fri, 4 Jan 2013 16:36:51 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions CHANCE AND NATURAL SELECTION 205 genotypicfrequenciesof the populationwill remainin the equilibrium frequencies, p2AA 2pqAa: q2aa. Now assumefor the momentthatpopulationsize is not a variableof the theory-that the theoryonly applies to populationsof infinite size. of gene and geIn an infinitepopulation,any "local"misrepresentations notypefrequenciesdue to indiscriminatesamplingwouldbalanceout. So by insistingthat the populationbe infinitelylarge, evolutionby genetic driftis effectivelyruledout. Law, given valuesfor p and Giventhis versionof the Hardy-Weinberg q in one generation,and given 1) magnitudesof selectionfor or against the variousgenotypes, 2) rates of mutationwith respectto the various alleles, 3) magnitudesof preferentialmating between the differentgenotypes,and 4) magnitudesof migrationof the differentgenotypes, we can calculatethe exact gene and genotypefrequenciesin the succeeding generations.For instance,if the frequenciesof A and a are p and q respectively,andif the relativeaveragefitnessesof the genotypesAA, Aa, andaa are 1, 1, and 1 - s respectively,then the changein frequencyof A (tip) in one generationis, Ap = (spq2)/(1 - sq2). Thetheoryof evolution,thusconstrued,wouldbe neatlydeterministic, but would be grossly incompletewith respectto the many finite populationsthatsupposedlyalso undergoevolutionarychange!To coverthese, populationsize mustbe consideredas a variable.We can then formulate the sortsof stochasticextensionsof the theorythatwe have alreadydiscussed. Withoutthem, the theoryof evolutionwould be awfully incomplete. andquantummechanics,stochastic As in the cases of thermodynamics theoriesplay a very importantrole in evolutionarybiology. In spite of all the disputesconcerningthe evolutionaryimportanceof randomdrift, no one denies that evolutionarytheory shouldbe stochastic.But just to say thatevolutionarytheoryis stochastic,and thatis that, is to overlook an importantrespect in which stochasticitycontinuesto be an issue in evolutionarybiology. I do not meanthatthe issue has been transformed into the sort of stochasticity vs. in-principle stochasticity issue charac- teristicof quantummechanics.I have in mindyet anotherrespectin which the stochasticityissue in evolutionarybiology is far from being settled. It is kept alive by the varietyof issues and disputesconcerningthe importanceof randomdrift.In orderto see the connection,it will be useful to considerthe disputesconcerningthe importanceof randomdriftin the contextof other, somewhatsimilardisputesin evolutionarybiology. This content downloaded on Fri, 4 Jan 2013 16:36:51 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 206 JOHN BEATTY Evolutionistsrecognizea varietyof modes of evolution-a varietyof ways in which the gene and genotypefrequenciesof a populationmay be changed(basically,any of the ways in which Hardy-Weinbergequilibriummight be upset). There is evolutionvia the genetic mutationof one allele to another,evolutionvia the migrationof geneticallydifferent types of organismsinto or out of the population,evolutionvia the preferentialmating of organismswith particulargenotypes, and of course evolutionvia randomdrift, and evolutionvia naturalselection. Evolutionarytheorydescribesthe separateand concurrentoutcomes of these variousprocesses,dependingon the values of the relevantvariables.So, for instance,evolutionarytheorydescribeswhat happensin a large populationwhen thereis no migration,no mutation,andmoderateselection; what happensin a small populationwhen there is moderatemigration, moderatemutation,and no selection;etc. Agreementwithregardto the theoryas describedstill leaves open some veryimportantquestions-namely, questionsconcerningthe relativeevoof the variousmodesof evolutionin nature-hence, lutionaryimportances the magnitudesof the relevantvariablesin nature. It is remarkablehow many modernevolutionistshave been of the opinion that the work that "remainsto be done" in evolutionarybiology is just that of measuring these magnitudes.Timofeef-Ressovsky's1940 assessmentof the workto-be-doneis representativeof this opinion, and has been echoed often since then. As Timofeefexplainedthe situation,evolutionarytheoristsof the likes of R. A. Fisher, J. B. S. Haldane,Sergei Tschetverikov,and Sewall Wrighthad succeededin . . .showing us the relativeefficacy of variousevolutionaryfactors underthe differentconditionspossiblewithinthe populations(Wright 1932). It does not, however,tell us anythingaboutthe real conditions in nature,or the actualempiricalvalues of the coefficients of mutation,selection, or isolation[limitationof populationsize]. It is the task of the immediatefutureto discover the orderof magnitudeof the coefficientsin free-livingpopulationsof differentplants and animals; this should form the aim and content of an empiricalpopulation genetics (Buzzati-Traverso,Jucci, and Timofeef-Ressovsky 1938). (Timofeef-Ressovsky1940, p. 104) And as A. J. Cain expressedthe same positionmuch more recently, The researchesof R. A. Fisher,J. B. S. Haldane,andSewall Wright laid the foundationsof the mathematicsof populationgenetics. ... What they did was to provide a mathematicaltheory covering all possible contingencies,from which quantitativepredictionsof both deterministicand stochasticprocesses could be made. That was a greatgain, but it does not tell us what of all these possibilities are This content downloaded on Fri, 4 Jan 2013 16:36:51 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions CHANCE AND NATURAL SELECTION 207 actually exemplified in the wild-what, in short, are relevant to the actual process of evolution. (Cain 1979, pp. 599-600) So evolutionists can agree on theory-on what are the possible modes of evolution, and how evolution occurs given various possible magnitudes of the relevant variables-and at the same time disagree vehemently as to the actual magnitudes of these variables and thus the relative importances of these modes of evolution in nature. Since Darwin, evolutionists have continually haggled over such matters. Neo-Lamarckians concerned themselves for a long time with the relative evolutionary importance of an evolutionary factor that is no longer included in evolutionary theorynamely, the inheritance of acquired characters. Darwin and Moritz Wagner argued about the importance of migration relative to selection (see Sulloway 1979). In the early twentieth century, William Bateson and W. F. R. Weldon argued over the importance of mutation size and pressure relative to selection (see Provine 1971). There are even disputes as to which is the most important kind of selection. For instance, there was a long, complicated, and even bitter controversy between Dobzhansky and H. J. Muller as to the relative evolutionary importance of selection in favor of heterozygotes vs. selection in favor of homozygotes (see Lewontin 1974). Representative of this interest of evolutionary biologists in ranking the modes of evolution according to their importance is the title of a book by A. L. and A. C. Hagedoorn, published in 1921: The Relative Value of the Processes Causing Evolution. These are rarely all-or-none issues. The disputants defend the importance of their favorite modes of evolution without ruling the others entirely out of the question. As Stephen Gould and Richard Lewontin characterize such issues, "In natural history, all possible things happen sometimes; you generally do not support your favoured phenomenon by declaringrivals impossible in theory" (Gould and Lewontin 1979, p. 151). The neo-Lamarckians recognized selection, though their neo-Darwinian opponents did not reciprocate. Darwin did not altogether deny the evolutionary effects of migration, nor did Wagner completely rule out selection. Bateson certainly did not ignore selection, nor did Weldon ignore mutation. Dobzhansky always admitted cases of selection in favor of homozygotes, and Muller always admitted cases of selection in favor of heterozygotes. The structure of these disputes thus has the important effect of not rendering entirely fruitless those parts of evolutionary theory that deal with the supposedly less importantmodes of evolution. So those parts of the theory are rarely threatened by elimination. These disputes can take place, in other words, without bringing any part of evolutionary theory into question, either for reasons of incorrectness or lack of fruitfulness. The issues concerning the relative evolutionary importance of random This content downloaded on Fri, 4 Jan 2013 16:36:51 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 208 JOHN BEATTY drift are very similar:What is more importantin accountingfor evolutionarychange,indiscriminatesamplingin finite populations,or discriminatesampling?As has been discussed,these issues are not all-or-none, but more-or-lessissues. As Gouldcharacterizesthe randomdrift issues, "Thequestion,as with so manyissues in the complexsciences of natural history,becomesone of relativefrequency"(Gould1980, p. 122). Thus, no neutralistdenies selection. No selectionistdenies neutralmutations. No one who investigatesthe concurrentaction of naturalselection and randomdriftbelievesthateitherof those factorsis alwaysoverwhelming. The stochastictheorythatdescribesthe evolutionof neutralalternatives, and that describesthe concurrenteffects of differentdegrees of indiscriminatesamplingand naturalselection, is thus not at issue. But preciselybecausethe actualrelativemagnitudesof populationsize and indiscriminatesamplingon the one hand, and selectionpressureon the otherhand,are at issue, stochasticityis still an issue in evolutionary biology. Evolutionarybiologists are contentto have a stochastictheory of evolution,but are not at all in agreementconcerninghow importanta role to attributeto chancein accountingfor actualevolutionarychange. The stochasticityissue in evolutionarybiology is decidedlynot whether chanceplays a role in evolutionarybiology, but to what extent. I will close with reference,once more, to the long-standingdispute betweenWrightand Fisherconcerningthe relativeevolutionaryimportanceof randomdriftvs. naturalselection. In his forthcomingbiography of Wright,WilliamProvinethoughtfullyanalyzesthe developmentof their agreementsanddisagreements.As Provinepointsout, WrightandFisher wereultimatelyable, in publishedworkand correspondence,to workout differencesconcerningthe mathematicaltheory involved. For instance, Wrightsucceededin convincingFisherthat the rate of decay of neutral variabilitywas 1/2N (Diagram5) ratherthan 1/4N as Fisher originally thought. As Wrightacknowledgedin his review of Fisher'slandmark,The Genetical Theory of Natural Selection (Fisher 1930), "our mathematical re- sults on the distributionof gene frequenciesare now in completeagreement, as far as comparable"(Wright1930, p. 352). But as Wrightalso madeclear, agreementwith regardto mathematicaltheorystill left room for considerabledisagreement.And the most importantsource of disagreementwas Fisher's assumptionof large populationsizes in nature, whicheffectivelyruledout the actualimportanceof evolutionby random drift. Again, this issue was somewhatdetachablefrom the mathematical theory.As for the real disagreement,as Wrightlaterput it, "Itis a question of the relativevalues of certaincoefficients"(1948, p. 291). Thus, evolutionistslike WrightandFishercouldagreethatsmallpopulationsize andchanceareimportantin theory,all the while disagreeingconsiderably This content downloaded on Fri, 4 Jan 2013 16:36:51 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions CHANCE AND NATURAL SELECTION 209 as to theirimportancein nature.It is in this sense that the stochasticity issues in evolutionarybiology are still far from being resolved. REFERENCES Brandon,R. (1978), "AdaptationandEvolutionaryTheory",Studiesin Historyand Philosophy of Science 9: 181-200. Brandon,R. (1978), "Evolution",Philosophyof Science45: 96-109. Burian,R. (1983), "Adaptation",in M. Grene (ed.), Dimensionsof Darwinism. Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress. A., Jucci, C. and Timofeef-Ressovsky,N. W. (1938), "Geneticsof Buzzati-Traverso, Populations", Ricerca Scientifica, Year 9, Vol. 1. to GeneralDiscussion",Proceedingsof theRoyalSociety Cain,A. J. (1979), "Introduction of London B205: 599-604. Crow, J. F. and Kimura, M. (1970), An Introduction to Population Genetics Theory. New York:Harperand Row. Darwin,C. (1839), "N Notebook",in H. E. Gruberand P. H. Barrett,Darwin on Man. New York:Dutton, 1974. Darwin, C. (1859), On the Origin of Species. London: Murray. Cambridge: Harvard Uni- versityPress(facsimileedition), 1959. Darwin, C. (1887), The Variation of Animals and Plants under Domestication, 2nd ed. (2 vols.). New York:Appleton. Darwin, F. (ed.) (1887), The Life and Letters of Charles Darwin (3 vols.). London: Murray. Diver, C. (1940), "TheProblemof Closely RelatedSnailsLiving in the Same Area", in J. S. Huxley (ed.), TheNew Systematics.Oxford:Clarendon. Dobzhansky, T. (1937), Genetics and the Origin of Species. New York: Columbia Uni- versityPress. Dobzhansky, T. (1970), Genetics of the Evolutionary Process. New York: Columbia Uni- versityPress. Dobzhansky,T. and Pavlovsky,0. (1957), "An ExperimentalStudy of InteractionBetween GeneticDrift and NaturalSelection",Evolution11: 311-319. Dubinin,N. P. and Romaschoff,D. D. (1932), "The GeneticStructureof Species and their Evolution" (in Russian). Biologichesky Zhurnal 1: 52-95. Eigen, M. and Winkler,R. (1981), Laws of the Game. New York:Knopf. Fisher, R. A. (1930), The Genetical Theory of Natural Selection. Oxford: Oxford Uni- versityPress. Fisher,R. A. and Ford, E. B. (1950), "The 'Sewall WrightEffect"', Heredity4: 117119. Futuyma,D. J. (1979), EvolutionaryBiology. Sunderland,Massachusetts:Sinauer. Ghiselin, M. T. (1969), The Triumph of the Darwinian Method. Berkeley: University of CaliforniaPress. Gould,S. J. (1980), "Isa New andGeneralTheoryof EvolutionEmerging?"Paleobiology 6: 119-130. Gould, S. J. and Lewontin,R. C. (1979), "The Spandrelsof San Marcoand the Panglossian Paradigm: A Critique of the Adaptationist Programme", Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B205: 581-598. Hacking, I. (1965), Logic of Statistical Inference. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press. Hagedoorn, A. L. and A. C. (1921), The Relative Value of the Processes Causing Evo- lution.The Hague:Nijoff. Hodge,J. andKohn,D. (Forthcoming),"TheImmediateOriginsof the Theoryof Natural Selection", in D. Kohn (ed.), The Darwinian Heritage: A Centennial Retrospect. Princeton:PrincetonUniversityPress. Studiesof the Distributionof Gene Kerr,W. E. and Wright,S. (1954), "Experimental Frequencies in Very Small Populations of Drosophila melanogaster", Evolution 8: 172-177. This content downloaded on Fri, 4 Jan 2013 16:36:51 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 210 JOHN BEATTY Kimura, M. (1981), "Possibility of Extensive Neutral Evolution under Stabilizing Selection with Special Reference to Non-Random Usage of Synonymous Codons", Journal of Molecular Evolution 17: 121-122. Kimura, M. (1982), "The Neutral Theory as a Basis for Understanding the Mechanism of Evolution and Variation at the Molecular Level", in M. Kimura (ed.), Molecular Evolution, Protein Polymorphism, and the Neutral Theory. New York: Springer. King, J. L. and Jukes, T. H. (1969), "Non-Darwinian Evolution", Science 164: 788-798. Lamotte, M. (1959), "Polymorphism of Natural Populations of Cepaea nemoralis", Cold Spring Harbor Symposia on Quantitative Biology 24: 65-84. Lerner, I. M. (1958), The Genetic Basis of Selection. New York: Wiley. Lewontin, R. C. (1974), The Genetic Basis of Evolutionary Change. New York: Columbia University Press. Mettler, L. E. and Gregg, T. G. (1969), Population Genetics and Evolution. Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice Hall. Mills, S. K. and Beatty, J. (1979), "A Propensity Interpretation of Fitness", Philosophy of Science 46: 263-286. Nei, M. (1975), Molecular Population Genetics and Evolution. New York: Elsevier. Peirce, C. (1893), "Evolutionary Love", Monist 3: 176-200. Provine, W. B. (1971), The Origins of Theoretical Population Genetics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Provine, W. B. (Forthcoming), Sewall Wright: Geneticist and Evolutionist. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Roughgarden, J. (1979), Theory of Population Genetics and Evolutionary Ecology: An Introduction. New York: Macmillan. Schweber, S. (1982), "Aspects of Probabilistic Thought in Great Britain During the Nineteenth Century: Darwin and Maxwell", in A. Shimony and H. Feshback (eds.), Physics and Natural Philosophy. Cambridge: MIT Press. Sheppard, P. M. (1967), Natural Selection and Heredity. London: Hutchinson. Sheynin, 0. B. (1980), "On the History of the Statistical Method in Biology", Archive for History of the Exact Sciences 22: 323-371. Skyrms, B. (1966), Choice and Chance. Belmont, California: Dickenson. Sober, E. (1980), "Evolutionary Theory and the Ontological Status of Properties", Philosophical Studies 40: 147-161. Sulloway, F. J. (1979), "Geographical Isolation in Darwin's Thinking: The Vicissitudes of a Crucial Idea", Studies in the History of Biology 3: 23-65. Timofeef-Ressovsky, N. W. (1940), "Mutations and Geographical Variation", in J. S. Huxley (ed.), The New Systematics. Oxford: Clarendon. Waddington, C. H. (1968), "The Basic Ideas of Biology", Towards a Theoretical Biology 1. Chicago: Aldine Publishing Company, pp. 1-41. Wilson, E. 0. and Bossert, W. H. (1971), A Primer of Population Biology. Sunderland, Massachusetts: Sinauer. Wilson, E. 0. (1975), Sociobiology. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Wright, S. (1930), "The Genetical Theory of Natural Selection: A Review", Journal of Heredity 21: 349-356. Wright, S. (1931), "Evolution in Mendelian Populations", Genetics 16: 97-159. Wright, S. (1932), "The Roles of Mutation, Inbreeding, Crossbreeding, and Selection in Evolution", Proceedings of the Sixth International Congress of Genetics ]: 356-366. Wright, S. (1940), "The Statistical Consequences of Mendelian Heredity in Relation to Speciation", in J. S. Huxley (ed.), The New Systematics. Oxford: Clarendon. Wright, S. (1948), "On the Roles of Directed and Random Changes in Gene Frequency in the Genetics of Populations", Evolution 2: 279-294. APPENDIX Recallthatthe hereditarymaterialof sexualorganismscomes in pairsof morphologically similar,or homologous,chromosomes.The genes residelinearlyalong the chromosomes; This content downloaded on Fri, 4 Jan 2013 16:36:51 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions CHANCE AND NATURAL SELECTION 211 A a the two genes that lie opposite one another on homologous chromosomes are said to occupy the same chromosomal location, or "locus", and are said to be "alleles" with respect to that locus. In the diagram, A and a are alleles at a particular locus. The two alleles at a locus may be materially different, as in the case of A and a (as the different symbols are supposed to represent), or they may be materially identical. Different combinations of alleles may result in alternative states of the same general character, like blue eye color vs. brown eye color. The particular combination of alleles that an organism has is called its genotype. We can speak of the genotype at a particular locus-for instance, we can speak of the Aa genotype in the case at hand-or we can speak of the entire genotype. If the two alleles at a locus are different, the organism is said to have a "heterozygotic" genotype with respect to that locus. Otherwise, it would be said to have a "homozygotic" genotype with respect to that locus. Finally, the gametes that a sexual organism produces (i.e., the sperm/pollen or egg cells that it produces) each appropriatelycontain one allele from each locus. According to "Mendel's Law", there is no physical basis for a bias in the number of gametes containing one or the other allele of a heterozygotic organism. In other words, in the long run, a heterozygotic organism should produce gametes, half of which contain one allele, and the other half of which contain the other allele. This content downloaded on Fri, 4 Jan 2013 16:36:51 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions