• Study Resource
  • Explore
    • Arts & Humanities
    • Business
    • Engineering & Technology
    • Foreign Language
    • History
    • Math
    • Science
    • Social Science

    Top subcategories

    • Advanced Math
    • Algebra
    • Basic Math
    • Calculus
    • Geometry
    • Linear Algebra
    • Pre-Algebra
    • Pre-Calculus
    • Statistics And Probability
    • Trigonometry
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Astronomy
    • Astrophysics
    • Biology
    • Chemistry
    • Earth Science
    • Environmental Science
    • Health Science
    • Physics
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Anthropology
    • Law
    • Political Science
    • Psychology
    • Sociology
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Accounting
    • Economics
    • Finance
    • Management
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Aerospace Engineering
    • Bioengineering
    • Chemical Engineering
    • Civil Engineering
    • Computer Science
    • Electrical Engineering
    • Industrial Engineering
    • Mechanical Engineering
    • Web Design
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Architecture
    • Communications
    • English
    • Gender Studies
    • Music
    • Performing Arts
    • Philosophy
    • Religious Studies
    • Writing
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Ancient History
    • European History
    • US History
    • World History
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Croatian
    • Czech
    • Finnish
    • Greek
    • Hindi
    • Japanese
    • Korean
    • Persian
    • Swedish
    • Turkish
    • other →
 
Profile Documents Logout
Upload
? A Unified Semantic Framework for Fully
? A Unified Semantic Framework for Fully

... family of basic systems. For example, this includes standard sequent calculi for modal logics, as well as the usual multiple-conclusion systems for intuitionistic logic, its dual, and bi-intuitionistic logic. On the semantic side, we consider a generalization of Kripke-style semantics for modal and ...
24(4)
24(4)

A LAW OF LARGE NUMBERS FOR RANDOM WALKS IN RANDOM
A LAW OF LARGE NUMBERS FOR RANDOM WALKS IN RANDOM

... The statement of our fundamental result, Theorem 3.4, involves certain modified regeneration times, which are introduced in Section 2. The basic condition in this theorem is a trade-off between moments for these “regeneration times” and rate of mixing for the environment. A corollary can be readily ...
the fundamentals of abstract mathematics
the fundamentals of abstract mathematics

Document
Document

15(1)
15(1)

a + b - faculty.ucmerced.edu
a + b - faculty.ucmerced.edu

Sample pages 1 PDF
Sample pages 1 PDF

3.1 Syntax - International Center for Computational Logic
3.1 Syntax - International Center for Computational Logic

pdf file
pdf file

... algebra) that a student encounters, in which one truly has to grapple with the subtleties of a truly rigourous mathematical proof. As such, the course offers an excellent chance to go back to the foundations of mathematics - and in particular, the construction of the real numbers - and do it properl ...
Boolean Expressions and Control Statements
Boolean Expressions and Control Statements

... • The for statements should be used when the number of iterations of the loop is known before entering the loop • The test expression is evaluated at each iteration. It is better to evaluate it once and for all before entering the loop • The index variable of the for statements may step increasingly ...
relevance logic - Consequently.org
relevance logic - Consequently.org

13(4)
13(4)

Chapter 4 square sum graphs
Chapter 4 square sum graphs

conclusion - Computer Engineering
conclusion - Computer Engineering

... In 1930, Herbrand proved an important theorem: A set S of clauses is unsatisfiable if and only if there is a finite unsatisfiable set S' of ground instances of clauses of S. These ground instances can be in any domain and unsatisfiability could be with respect to any interpretation. The important co ...
Hilbert`s Program Then and Now - Philsci
Hilbert`s Program Then and Now - Philsci

... In about 1920, Hilbert came to reject Russell’s logicist solution to the consistency problem for arithmetic, mainly for the reason that the axiom of reducibility cannot be accepted as a purely logical axiom. In lectures from the Summer term 1920, he concluded that “the aim of reducing set theory, an ...
Elements of Finite Model Theory
Elements of Finite Model Theory

Littlewood-Richardson rule
Littlewood-Richardson rule

Chapter 10 Number Theory and Cryptography
Chapter 10 Number Theory and Cryptography

17 Sums of two squares
17 Sums of two squares

A Survey On Euclidean Number Fields
A Survey On Euclidean Number Fields

Elements of Programming Languages Overview Values Evaluation
Elements of Programming Languages Overview Values Evaluation

The Congruent Number Problem -RE-S-O-N-A-N-C-E--I-A-U-9-U
The Congruent Number Problem -RE-S-O-N-A-N-C-E--I-A-U-9-U

A rational approach to π
A rational approach to π

1977 .27 - (76.38) Problems and results on combinatorial number
1977 .27 - (76.38) Problems and results on combinatorial number

< 1 ... 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 ... 170 >

Theorem



In mathematics, a theorem is a statement that has been proven on the basis of previously established statements, such as other theorems—and generally accepted statements, such as axioms. The proof of a mathematical theorem is a logical argument for the theorem statement given in accord with the rules of a deductive system. The proof of a theorem is often interpreted as justification of the truth of the theorem statement. In light of the requirement that theorems be proved, the concept of a theorem is fundamentally deductive, in contrast to the notion of a scientific theory, which is empirical.Many mathematical theorems are conditional statements. In this case, the proof deduces the conclusion from conditions called hypotheses or premises. In light of the interpretation of proof as justification of truth, the conclusion is often viewed as a necessary consequence of the hypotheses, namely, that the conclusion is true in case the hypotheses are true, without any further assumptions. However, the conditional could be interpreted differently in certain deductive systems, depending on the meanings assigned to the derivation rules and the conditional symbol.Although they can be written in a completely symbolic form, for example, within the propositional calculus, theorems are often expressed in a natural language such as English. The same is true of proofs, which are often expressed as logically organized and clearly worded informal arguments, intended to convince readers of the truth of the statement of the theorem beyond any doubt, and from which a formal symbolic proof can in principle be constructed. Such arguments are typically easier to check than purely symbolic ones—indeed, many mathematicians would express a preference for a proof that not only demonstrates the validity of a theorem, but also explains in some way why it is obviously true. In some cases, a picture alone may be sufficient to prove a theorem. Because theorems lie at the core of mathematics, they are also central to its aesthetics. Theorems are often described as being ""trivial"", or ""difficult"", or ""deep"", or even ""beautiful"". These subjective judgments vary not only from person to person, but also with time: for example, as a proof is simplified or better understood, a theorem that was once difficult may become trivial. On the other hand, a deep theorem may be simply stated, but its proof may involve surprising and subtle connections between disparate areas of mathematics. Fermat's Last Theorem is a particularly well-known example of such a theorem.
  • studyres.com © 2025
  • DMCA
  • Privacy
  • Terms
  • Report