* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download KAUSALITÄT UND MOTIVATION BEI EDITH STEIN
Business ethics wikipedia , lookup
Ethics of eating meat wikipedia , lookup
Individualism wikipedia , lookup
Internalism and externalism wikipedia , lookup
Kantian ethics wikipedia , lookup
Bernard Williams wikipedia , lookup
Alasdair MacIntyre wikipedia , lookup
Ethics of artificial intelligence wikipedia , lookup
Ethics in religion wikipedia , lookup
Morality and religion wikipedia , lookup
Lawrence Kohlberg wikipedia , lookup
Morality throughout the Life Span wikipedia , lookup
Phenomenology (philosophy) wikipedia , lookup
Consequentialism wikipedia , lookup
Lawrence Kohlberg's stages of moral development wikipedia , lookup
Moral disengagement wikipedia , lookup
Moral development wikipedia , lookup
Critique of Practical Reason wikipedia , lookup
Secular morality wikipedia , lookup
Moral relativism wikipedia , lookup
Moral responsibility wikipedia , lookup
1 ETHICS OF THE RENOVATION IN HUSSERL Urbano FERRER Husserl is a worried witness of a series of symptoms of acute spiritual crisis in Europa in the part of XX Century in which he lived: they are aproximately the same motives that had led Oswald Spengler to refer to the decline of the West or H. Arendt to delve into the origins and nature of the totalitarianisms or Ortega y Gasset to write The revolt of the masses. What ended in the bloodiest wars in history, had not escaped the sharp look of those thinkers with regard to the widespread antisemitism in Europe or the quick establishment of the Soviet and Nacionalsocialist totalitarianisms or the economic crash which followed the Great War after years of apparent prosperity or also the rupture of old social and polítical structures. What had this critical situation to do with the cultural lag –in the words of the norteamerican sociologist W. F. Ogburn– between natural-scientific advancements and their technological application, on the one hand, and the slow awakening of cultural factors, on the other? Was not the crisis in the same line with the failed attempts to found the Sciences of the Spirit –since undertaken by Dilthey–, in such a way that they were not behind in the accuracy and precision of the Sciences of Nature? At beginning of his article of 1911 Philosophy as strict Science, published in Logos, Husserl contrasts the stuttering situation of the Sciences of the Spirit with the firm progression of the Physico-mathematical Science since Euclidean Geometry, where even the foundational crises –specially significant in the contemporary Age–, far from being paralyzing, had offered new possibilities in Geometry and the Physical Sciences in general. However the search for parallelism between both forms of knowledge is flawed, if we thereby seek to confirm exact explanatory laws in the sphere of the Sciences of the Spirit. Already W. Dilthey had contrasted natural explanation to historical understanding, although later he tried to resolve the second one in final units of psycological character, that lost the specificity of human deeds. For Husserl what distinguishes the human is being under the sign of the normative judgement and hence the responsibility for what is judged by the agent. If one 2 disregards the valorative engagement, the judged subject is stagnated as if it were a dense fact, opaque to all rational penetration. In his words: “Doch auf geisteswissenschaftlicher Seite handelt es sich nicht wie bei der Natur um bloße rationale „Erklärung“. Hier tritt noch eine ganz eigentümliche Art der Rationalisierung des Empirischen auf: die normative Beurteilung nach allgemeinen Normen, die zum apriorischen Wesen der ‘vernünftigen’ Humanität gehören, und die Leitung der tatsächlichen Praxis selbst nach ebensolchen Normen, zu denen die Vernunftnormen praktischer Leitung selbst mitgehören”1. Or in other paragraph: “Doch wie immer, in dieser naturtechnischen Sphäre des menschlichen Handeln ermöglichte Wissenschaft eine wahre praktische Rationalität, und sie gab die vorbildliche Lehre, wie Wissenschaft überhaupt zur Leuchte der Praxis werde müsse. Aber an einer rationaler Wissenschaft vom Menschen und der menschlichen Gemeinschaft, welche eine Rationalität im sozialen, im politischen Handeln und eine tationale politische Technik begründen würde, fehlt es duchaus”2. All this brings to light the affirmative response to the question posed earlier: The contemporary human crises are seen by Husserl as crises of a humanistic knowledge at the level of this time, insofar as this knowledge includes responsibility for leading humanity according to a priori normative goals. Therefore it is not strange, if without an apriori normativity justice degenerates into mere ruled procedure, freedom subverts into emancipation with no bearings and Science becomes a routine technic, to give somes examples of the western crisis. Precisely Ethics appears in a frame of essencial considerations about man, such that bring into line the mentioned notions among others. 1. Conditioned imperatives and unconditioned moral imperative The diverse human activities and professions are specified by their corresponding guideline ends, which establish the difference between right and wrong, the suitable and the unsuitable… But it is a conditional or subordinate normativity, since one enters its area only with the condition that someone has 1 HUSSERL, E., Aufsätze und Vorträge (1922-1937), Nenon, Th, Sepp, H.R. (hrsg.), Husserliana XXVII, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, 1989, p. 7. 2 o.c., p. 6. 3 opted for such an activity and, once performed, it is allways possible to unfold other activities which fall under other normativities. It seems that such imperatives would have to be hypothetical in the Kantian sense, insofar as they depend on an end that is not absolutely adscribed to the human acting und wanting. However this first approach is not definitive in order to distinguish between conditioned imperatives and unconditioned moral imperative. This is what I seek to show below. Strictly we are not before two classes of yuxtaposed imperatives nor they are anyway extrinsecally related. It is sufficient for seeing it to realize that the laws of right and wrong already concern the acts of the will with their essential orientation to what is good, even in a restricted order. Thus the commands proper to a determinate sphere of behaviour are origin of responsibility or, in a negative way, it would be irresponsible to give them up once they have been assumed. In other words: without the ethical normativity of duty all other normativity would remain conventional or ficticious. In inverse terms: accepting an imperative for behaviour without inserting oneself simultaneously in the ethical normativity means assuming a normativity which is contrary to the ethical one and consists of turning the relative into the absolute, since the responsibility for leading a life according to reason is something constitutive for man. In the words of Husserl: “Alle als positiv zu bewertenden Lebensformen können für den Menschen, der sich auf die Stufe des ethischen erhoben hat, nur dadurch wertvoll bleiben, dass sie sich in die ethischen Lebensformen einordnen und in ihr nicht nur eine weitere Formgebung, sondern auch die Norm und Grenze ihres letzten Rechtes gewinnen”3. But before going on let us sheed light on the apparently paradoxical meaning of the expression “uncondicioned imperative”. Indeed as imperative, it could be applicable only to a conditioned being, who is at odds with that which is not in conformity with its dictates: it is only in this regard that the imperative appears; but as unconditional the imperative seems to designate what is already established or decided, without admiting additional modulation by virtue of new demands. If the Kantian categorical or unconditioned imperative succeds in reconciling both sides, it is because it limits itself to being the universal form of the will, repeatedly present in all volontary acts. But it is not the case in Husserlian Ethics, where the due act of the will is based on the differential axiological content and its later deliberative analysis, which lead it to adhere to the best in the situation, and not merely what is wanted according to an apriori 3 o.c., p. 29. 4 need of the wanting. The Husserl’s formula of the categorical imperative reflects it so: “act according to the best knowledge and conscience”. And as both the best knowing and the best conscience are something which is acquired with moral experience, the unconditioned means here an inalienable guideline for acting, since it involves reason, whose judgements strive towards truth, and it does not mean a merely formal universale law with which the maximes of acting had to be measured. But if Husserl’s categorical imperative is not an abstracte law, how can it be about an apriori of Reason, and as such unconditioned? Is it not contradicted by the fact that its commands need the sieve of experience, specially if affectivity has its part in this experience? It is time to bring in the phenomenological notion of fulfilment, which appears in diverse orders. Fulfilment applies to the promise, not as an additional eventuality, but as the satisfaction of a requirement, which is a priori implicit in the act of promise. It is also said in the sphere of knowledge of a meaning when this is satisfied or fulfilled by the corresponding intuition. Analogously, a feeling of joy gains fulfilment when the joyful state of things which justifies it enough is present. The opposite of fulfilment is disillusion, as that which from fair away seemed to be a waving lady becomes a dammy, as I approche, or when the striving joy does not find confirmation in the adequate state of things. Thus fulfilment has a journey which ends in evidence, or, what is equivalent, comes out in the telos which brings to end expectation founded in it. There is no contradiction in general terms in that the a priori is reached with experience when this experience means the progressive fulfilment of a prescribed teleological demand. This is common to the given examples of the binding promise, of the presumption which needs sufficient basis for becoming evidence or of the qualitative feeling, which calls for a valuable adequate quality. What makes the terms acquired in the course of the experience apt for supplying fullness to the performative act, to the search for knowledge or to the affective stance, is that they guarantee the teleological fulfilment, demanded a priori in each one of the examples above. But how can we extend this notion to the field of moral praxis? I considere that here lies Husserl’s contribution to the Ethics. Teleological fulfilment prevents two opposite extremes. On the one hand, it is not about judging an isolate action –which is prevailing in classic approach–, but neither –at the opposite extreme – is it about avoiding the action as such by 5 ressorting to the underlying legal form or to the effects and consequences of the action; what mainly matters is to links the action with the motives, the stance and the intention, since the action fulfils them and confirms their truth. The moral judgement falls on the motivation, the stance or the guiding intention, but not as if these were the definitive, insofar as with them a impletive process is initiated and this in confirmated only once the motivated actions are reached. Moral is so inserted in the biography where the acting is inscribed, and in turn continues in the following biographical stages which give it fulfilment. Thus duty –formulable in uncondicional imperative –does not lie in a separate and ideal realm, alien to the experience, but by means of essential connection of the stances, motivations and intentions with their respectives correlates manages to link up a priori and normatively with the actions held as due. As Husserl says: “Ethische Gesetze sind keine Sachgesetze für das Handeln, sonst gäbe es ja kein anderes Handeln, als sie fordern; sie reichen vielmehr über bloß empirische oder apriorische Gesetze für wirkliche oder ideal mögliche Zusammenhänge der Natur hinaus, da sich nicht das Sein der Handlungen als Sachen regeln, sondern Normen eines Sollens abgeben”4. Notwithstanding, if the formula “uncondicional imperative” has some difficulties, it is because the term “imperative” in its application to morality is in some way imprecise. Indeed, if the first ethical funcion is the enjudgement by reason, then the performance of the action in itself or materially considered – which is the only thing that can be impered– is not moral, but only insofar as it conforms with the corresponding judgement and is guided by it. So language distinguishes between killing as physical action and murdering as intencional action or between taking away own possesions as description of an event and stealing as immoral action. Good, evil and analogous moral attributes appear in a preceptive act of judging and in this way can leave room for the subject to decide his acting freely, who turns moral judgement into directive of his behaviour. All –so called– moral imperative derives from the adequatness of the attribut “good” to certain typ of action and this entails responsibility of reason. But Husserl also draws some corollaries. First an approving (or disapproving) moral judgement can be ratified (or revised) in a later judgement, provided that there are sufficients motives supplied by the moral experience. What at one stage of the personal development and in certain context turned out appropiate, becomes at a wide vision of life unnecessary or even inconvenient, 4 ROTH, A., Edmund Husserls ethische Untersuchungen, Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, 1960, p. 34 (taken of Husserl’s Manuscripts). 6 in such a way that before it would still not have reached complete fulfilment. Thus we say sometimes “I ratify what I already stated” or on the contrary “today from my acquired perspective I don’t judge it so”. What is now called into question is not the highst ethical principles –in connection with synderesis–, but their material application, limited to variable external and psycological conditions. Another consequence of this approach is that the moral acompasses the whole life in its biographical trajectory and not only in one or another defined and in themselves concluded actions. As the ethical imperative is directed towards the best, the decided action is always open to its improvement, far from any stagnation in the will. But with this we are close to the central of his article, which is what Husserl understands by renovation as expression of moral growth for the individual and the community. What are the implicits of this notion? 2. Ethical and cultural renovation In a first sense renovation is to put something ex novo or, we can also say, renovation lies in every act of will, insofar as the will essentially adresses something which is to be done or, in the words of Husserl, insofar as volontary act means a creative fiat (this term was taken from Principles of Psychology of W. James). This implies that such act does not derive necessarily from the previous representative acts, but neither does it from a desire (Begehren) in which it were pre-contained, although the passive layer of the will has its part. Rather wanting as intencional act is fulfiled in the action, to which it points and in which is straightforwardly performed without representative or axiological mediation aside from the general idea of the wanted and its inclusion in the desiderable or in the channels leading to it. This wanting is renewing in the sense that it initiates itself the process of its performance and carries it out to end or stops it. Whereas desire is clairfied gradually until its fulfilment as desire, there is not an intentional correlate of the wanting which is clairfied beyond something desiderandum (wünschenswert), but the wanting is extended itself in the intencional or finaliste realization, which itself marks or gives unity. But how do we go from the innovation introduced by the act of the will to renovation? Indeed the term “renovation” is usually applied in the transitive sense of renewing something already given und expired. Without excluding this 7 meaning, here it is taken more radically, insofar as it refers to the subject who renews himself. This sense has certain analogy in the biological order with the living beings, which depend on the constant renovation of their celles and tissues for their survival. We can say that just as biological life is self-making, so biographical life is in active living. But what disitnguishes the second is that it is being driven by an identical personal I, whose renovation stems from singular free acts becoming habitual directions of his wanting, it is to say, actual and possible volitions, and so he modifies himself according to them. The propre ethical imperative includes the habituality in its formulation. “Also darauf kommt es an, dass nicht naiv, zufällig, ohne Normgewissheit, sondern eben im strengsten Sinn ‘nach bestem Wissen und Gewissen’ das Beste erwählt und getan ist, und dass dieses ‘nach bestem Wissen und Gewissen’ aus dem einen, das ethische Leben ein für alle Mal stiftenden Willen hervogegangen und zum habituell leitenden kategorischen Imperativ des ganzen Lebens geworden ist”5. Thus the moral is not a limited area of acting, but the whole biographical life is comprehended in the moral direction. In this way the more or less near ends of the acts link together in a teleological series until reaching the last end, which underlies and bestows them unity. In this regard renovation would mean the substitution of some ends by others within the common orientation to the unifying end; in contrast, the lack of renovation would lie in setting up immediate ends as the only express ones without mentioning the transcendent end, in which those are sustained and which is the only suitable one for completely satisfying the wanting (eine totale Befriedigung). As Husserl comments: “Er mag also als ethisch zentriertes Ich auf die Zweckidee habituell hingerichtet sein und bleiben –während es sich doch, sei es momentan oder in längeren Zeitstrecken, von ‘äußeren Affektionen’ fortreißen läßt und ‘sich an die Welt verliert’”6. Habitus obviously has here the active connotation of something that guides and reactivates the single acts, and not the passive sense of that which has settled in the consciousness after previous realizations, like a determinate style or a conviction proceeding from the adoption of certain judgements (Husserl calls these passive habitus “Habitualitäten”). But renovation also means man rising time and time again from the fallen or imperfect state from which he starts and to which drifts. “Sofern das ethische Leben seinem Wesen nach Kampf ist mit den ‘herabziehenden 5 HUSSERL, E., Einleitung in die Ethik. Vorlesungen Sommermester 1920 und 1924, Hus. XXXVII, Dordrecht/Boston/Londres: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2004, p. 253. 6 HUSSERL, Aufsätze und Vorträge…, p. 38. 8 Neigungen’, kann es auch als eine kontinuierliche Erneuerung beschrieben werden. Im besonderen Sinn erneuert sich der in ‘ethische Knechtschaft’ verfallene Mensch durch radikale Besinnung und Inkraftsetzung des ursprünglichen und kraftlos gewordenen ethischen Lebenswillens bzw. durch Neuvollzug der inzwischen geltungslos gewordenen Urstiftung”7. From this angle renovation appears as a continuous and necessary fight, since as soon as it is abandoned the relapse to the initial state becomes unavoidable. Augustinus’ principle that fixation in moral life is not possible resounds: “Always move on. If you say it is enough, you are lost”8. It is certainly true that in Husserl this principle has a reformist bias of Lutherean origin, although it does not reach the excesses of irredeemed prostration in the original sin, as in Luther and Kant, which would go against the moral eagerness of renovation put forward by the Husserlian ethical imperative. In a more restrictiv sense the recapitulation of the will returns also to the partial goods pursues and straightens them according to higher ends than those proposed before. We could say that no intention is born already straight, insofar as it is set up on the passive impulses and the spontaneous tendencies, but it must straighten itself according to the universal good, to which the will is open through the mediation of the active I. The semantic active-passive ambiguity of the term want, apt to designate both mere inclination and affirmative wanting, is symptomatic. In Husserl’s words: “In der letzten Hinsicht erwachsen solche Entwertungen in der peinlichen Erkenntnis, das erzielte ‘Gute’ sei nur ein vermeintliches Gutes; die ihm gewidmete Arbeit sei also eine nutzlose, die Freude daran eine sinnlose gewesen, und danach eine solche, die hinfort nicht mehr zur Glücksummedes bisherigen Lebens gerechnet werden dürfe”9. Thus the aspiration to perfection is not reached in medias res, but by overcoming resistences and obstacles and by re-examinating oneself in the light of the principle that all partial goods attained have to be integrated in a higher good (law of summation), in correlation with the unique and lasting satisfaction which the voluntary I yearns for unitarily. In negative way: the maximum good for man is not the sum of individual and ephemeral pleasures, lived in disconnected moments, since it refers to life in its totality. It should be noted how in this approach the historicity of culture is surreptitiously introduced, to the extent that the renovation is also applicable to 7 o.c., p. 43. San Agustín, Sermon 169, 18. 9 o.c., p. 32. 8 9 it. Culture is integrated by the external works of man, which are elargeable limitelessly by virtue of the renewing effort, but also culture belongs the man propre, insofar as man is not defined naturally, as occurs in animal species. History of culture is the history of variable realizations of man in the horizontal sense that they are documentable in external results and they ride some on the top of others that have gone before. Culture is besides the primordial place of man’s insertion in the community. “Also wirkliches Menschheitsleben ist seinem Wesen nach Kulturleben, und soweit es das nicht ist, ist der Mensch noch Tier und seinem Wesen nach emporstrebend von niederen zu immer höheren Vernunftformen”10. This serves as our link with the communitary Ethics of the renovation. Let us see it. In the sistematic context of Husserl the culture, being open to the plurality of its forms, is inscribed in the teleological process striving for evidence. Thus it has a dynamic fonction, which is valide only in the sense that approaches through models and relevant institutionalizations the moral realization by means of rational and free behaviour. In this way pluriform expressions can find course in culture, so avoiding the uniformity of abstract reason. In contrast, if it gets stuck in standard forms against the ideal of renovation, it ceases to contribute to the crystallization of the universality of the ethical will and goes back to he isolation and incommunication of individuals and particular groups. As we saw above when talking of the specific jobs and techniques that cannot unfold if they are not impregnated by the moral ideal of perfection, which affords sense to the duty of the particular ends, so now the various cultural expressions are acknowledged as human solely in that they are penetrated by the humanizing process of reason and the forging of the ethical personality. In this sense the semantic relation of culture with “colere”, cultivate, grow is sympthomatic, since this verb can be applied to the moral germs too. With Husserl’s words: “Er selbst ist dann zugleich Kultursubjekt und Kulturobjekt; und wieder ist er zugleich Kulturobjekt und Prinzip aller Kulturobjekte. Denn alle echte Kultur ist nur durch echte Selbstkultur in ihrem normgebenden ethischen Rahmen möglich”11. What, specifically, are the moral attitudes that are opened culturally? Husserl lists some. Obviously the family is a universal institution, which is necessary for the moral growth of man. Therefore it is pervaded with culture and Ethics, for in it the cultural incorporation to a language and to some pattern of 10 11 o.c., p. 99. o.c., pp. 41-42. 10 behaviour take place, as well as carrying out the sozialization at the first levels; but no less obviously individuals acquire therein the ethical esteem of themselves and learn moral virtues –solidarity, selfcontrol, sacrifice, neighbourly love–, which will have to be exerciced later and fitted in public framework. This is possible on account of its great proximity to the persons. But in other communities where there is no such proximity and so persons are mutually anonymous to a certain extent, we find also a differentiated cultural unit, through which moral virtues open up. Husserl shows it with regard to the consolidation of the nation, insofar as it substitutes initial mistrust and hostility towards neighbouring communities by ethical attitudes which are universally transfereable from the initial practice of the common national project. “Manche menschliche Tugenden der Freundlichkeit, Redlichkeit, Gerechtigkeit u.s.w. lösen sich aber von der heimischen Formung durch Sitte als ein menschliches Kern ab, der bei ganz verschiedenen Nationen sich immer wiederfindet, als ein allgemeinschliches ‘gesitteter’ Völker”12. However Husserl finds the synthesis between ethical universality and cultural differentiation in Europe from its origins in Classical Greece, where the ideal of a life according to Reason took shape, along with its later enshrinement in Roman Law and the new sap of Christianity with its unconditional respect for the dignity of the person. The European unity is not founded on any ethnic group or on any principle of cultural diferentiation, but on the universal will of de conducirse behaving according to the ideal of perfection in individuals and in particular communities, which even have the capacity of self-criticism with regard to the times when their behaviour has, in fact, fallen short of this ideal, and so they can practice moral renovation. With these assumptions one can understand what I have called in other papers universal vocation or European implantation in other continents, provided that the peculiarities of the indigenous cultures are respected and promoved equality, as has happened with the peoples that live within Europe (unfortunately, the European culture has not allways been up to its vocation). Husserl refers to it: “Das meint nichts minderes, als… dass wir in der europäischen Kultur die erste Verwirklichung einer absoluten Entwicklungsnorm sehen, die dazu berufen ist, jede andere sich entwickelnde Kultur zu revolutionieren. Denn eine jede in der Einheit einer Kultur lebende und sich entwickelnde Menschheit steht unter einem kategorischen Imperativ”13. 12 HUSSERL, E., Krisis II. Ergänzungsband. Texte aus dem Nachlass 1934-1937, Husserliana XXIX, Dordrecht/Boston/Londres: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1993, pp. 42-43. 13 Aufsätze und Vorträge 1922-1937, p. 73. 11 3. Renovation in communities as ethical subjects In the above it is implicit that the will of renovation is necessary not only in individuals or persons in a strict sense, but there are also collective subjects as moral persons in growth. “Das aber in wirklicher Analogie zum wirklichen Leben verstanden. Ebenso wie dieses wäre es also ein Leben der ‘Erneuerung’, aus dem eigenen Willen heraus geboren, sich selbst zu einer echten Menschheit im Sinne praktischer Vernunft, also ihre Kultur zu einer ‘echt humanen’ Kultur zu gestalten”14. More precisely: it is not about two typs of parallel renovations, but the collective renovation is founded in individual persons, deriving ethical features of the collectivities from individuals which comprise them. The reason is that only in these do they acquire consciousness of themselves and the sameness through their varying acts of knowledge, esteem and volitions. Some of these acts are performed not as individuals, but as members of the community they represent, in which they coincide with the other members. Therefore it makes sense to say that the community, as a project of life in common, is motivated to act in such a sense or that it has decided to do this or that, and we say that in the moral order one community or another has achieved this or that success, it is alive, that it has its own ethos... In no way are we before a simple sum or result of individual wills, but on these a collective will is built, in whose name the particular members act and uphold it. “(Sie) ist da keine Vielheit, sondern eine in der Vielheiten fundierte Einheit, und sie ist Substrat für Akte als Akteinzelheiten und für sie bleibende Akte, Akte, die selbst konstitutive Einheiten höherer Stufe sind, die ihre fundierenden Unterstufen in den betreffenden einzelpersonalen Akten haben… (Sie) hat Überzeugungen, Wünsche, Willensentschlüße, sie vollzieht Handlungen, ebenso ein Verein, ein Volk, ein Staat. Und auch von Vermögen, von Charakter, von Gesinung usw. können wir in strengen, aber entsprechend höherstufigen Sinn reden”15. The acts in which community is constituted and thrives are the so called social acts, not only directed to the other, but are also two-way on the basis of the world of life, perceived in common; these social acts are also called performative acts. Thus the acts of the community never prevent or invade the personal acts in which they are founded, but rather their weight falls finally and wholly on individuals. In words of Husserl, “eine universale Willensverbindung 14 15 O.c., p. 22. ZPhI, II, p. 201. 12 da, die Willenseinheit herstellt, ohne daß eine imperialistische Willensorganisation da ist, ein zentraler Wille, in dem sich alle Einzelwillen zentrieren, dem sie sich alle willig unterordnen und als dessen Funktionäre die einzelnen sich wissen”16. In another order of considerations Charles Taylor distinguishes between individual, socially convergent (e.g. wellfare or public safety), and common goods, exceeding zero-sum games because they are essentially communitary. And just as the latter do not cancel out the individuals, but include them as beneficiaries from a broader radius, neither is it apropiate to say that collective wills displace individual wills for their resting on them. Rather, these individual wills are the sole effective subjects of acts, however much those representative of the community may be included among them. Mediante la comunidad se abren a los individuos unas posibilidades de perfeccionamiento de las que por sí solos eran incapaces. Y cada una de las comunidades se caracteriza por unos fines diferenciales en orden a la realización de los individuos, desde aquellas en las que estos originariamente están hasta aquellas otras en las que ingresan por adscripción voluntaria. En su obra Metaphisik der Gemeinschaft emprendió Hildebrand una tipología de las comunidades que amplía las consideraciones husserlianas. En su alcance más alto se encuentra la comunidad omniabarcante de la Humanidad en general, no entendida como una totalidad abstracta o como un género lógico, sino como integrada realmente por todos los seres humanos sobre la base de un ideal común de perfección, al que no es ajeno ninguno de los logros alcanzados por las distintas actividades humanas parciales ni por otras comunidades más restringidas. Esta noción tiene su antecedente más próximo en el ideal de la Ilustración, tal como lo hace valer, por ejemplo, Kant en La paz perpetua refiriéndose al orden jurídico, pero en Husserl representa ante todo un programa de superación moral para los sujetos individuales y colectivos pertenecientes a la Humanidad. Así lo refleja en textos como el siguiente: “Es gehört also zu meinem echt menschlichen Leben, dass ich nicht nur mich als Guten, sondern die gesamte Gemeinschaft als eine Gemeinschaft Guter wünschen und, soweit ich kann, in meinen praktischen Willens–, Zweckkreis nehmen muß. Ein wahrer Mensch sein ist ein wahrer Mensch wollen und beschließt in sich, Glied einer ‘wahren’ Menschheit sein wollen oder die Gemeinschaft, der man angehört, als eine wahre wollen, in den Grenzen praktischer Möglichkeit”17. 16 17 Aufsätze und…, p. 53. O.c., p. 46. 13 Queda la cuestión del término de referencia hacia el que se encamina y por el que se orienta la perfección moral. Ha de ser, sí, un ideal de perfección moral, pero a la vez estando más allá de las personas que pugnan por llegar a él, quedándoles fuera de su alcance. Así es como se incoa desde la argumentación moral la noción de Persona divina, como la de aquel Ser que desborda infinitamente las posibilidades humanas sin por ello dejar estas de aproximarse crecientemente a él. Pensemos, por ejemplo, en la síntesis entre justicia y misericordia, que sólo imperfectamente puede ser realizada por el hombre en su avance moral. En este aspecto el símil geométrico de la hipérbola, que se acerca asintóticamente al límite sin llegar nunca a él, le sirve a Husserl de ilustración. “Gehen wir hier bis an die ideale Grenzen, mathematisch gesprochen an den ‘Limes’, so hebt sich von einem relativen Vollkommenheitsideal ein absolutes ab. Es ist nichts anderes als das Ideal personaler absoluter Vollkommenheit: absoluter theoretischer, axiotischer und in jedem Sinn praktischer Vernunft… Der absolute Limes, der über alle Endlichkeit hinausliegende Pol, auf den alles echt humane Streben gerichtet ist, ist die Gottesidee”18. Este ideal infinitamente distante tiene su eco finito en la conciencia moral humana, desde el momento que está puesta ante la tarea moral inagotable de lo óptimo, al tener que actuar según el mejor saber y la mejor conciencia. o.c o.c., p. 33-34.