Download Class #8

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts

Problem of religious language wikipedia , lookup

Meaning of life wikipedia , lookup

Universalism wikipedia , lookup

Euthyphro dilemma wikipedia , lookup

Jewish existentialism wikipedia , lookup

Teleological argument wikipedia , lookup

Existence of God wikipedia , lookup

Misotheism wikipedia , lookup

Monism wikipedia , lookup

Presuppositional apologetics wikipedia , lookup

Existence wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
Philosophy 1010
Class 2/11/13
Title:
Instructor:
E-mail Address:
Introduction to Philosophy
Paul Dickey
[email protected]
Tonight: Turn in your Essay Argument Summary
Hand back your Pragmatism Essays.
Next Week Assignment:
Velasquez, Philosophy: A Text With Readings
Chapter 6, Sections 6.1 & 6.2.
Don’t procrastinate on your essays! If you have any
questions, please ask either now or by e-mail.
COURSE EVALUATION
Electronic/Online Course/Instructor
Feedback
13/WI Availability until February 20, 2013.
Instruction Sheet will be on Quia site.
Chapter 3
Reality and Being
(a Metaphysical Study)
Discussion
“Being Practical” vs. Pragmatism
A Thought Experiment:
How was Benjamin Franklin interested
in lightning? For its usefulness or for its
potential beauty? Thus, was he
practical? So, was he a philosophical
pragmatist? What if ol’ Ben suggests to
us that lightning is beautiful because it
can be harnessed as electricity?
•
Video:
What is Real?
The Problem of Free Will
The Prima Facie (or Self-evident)
Case for Free Will
•
From common sense:
•
I have a direct consciousness of being able to
do otherwise.
•
I have a direct consciousness of causing my
own behavior.
•
I accept responsibility for my decisions.
The Prima Facie (or Self-evident)
Case for Determinism
•
From common sense:
•
Everything appears to have a scientific
cause.
•
It is not understood by what mechanism a
mental state such as a will or an intention
can cause behavior in the physical world.
•
We seem to be think it quite appropriate to
explain the behavior of others (and they us)
simply in terms of behavior or reasons that
they are unaware of, even when the person
themselves would have said they chose to
do so.
Determinism
•
Determinists argue that previous events and the
laws of nature cause all human acts.
•
Human acts are predictable theoretically if we knew
all prior conditions and the laws governing those
conditions on the model of physics.
•
Sir Isaac Newton (1642 – 1727) argued that
all bodies in the universe both the smallest
atoms and the largest planets act in
accordance with the universal laws of nature.
Determinism
•
The Marquis de LaPlace (1749-1827) applied the
Newtonian conception and argued that humanity
is part of a causal chain, as is all phenomena.
•
For LaPlace, free will is an illusion that we have
since we are ignorant of the appropriate laws of
human nature.
•
John Hospers (1918 - ) argues that the
unconscious motivations for behaviors discovered
by Sigmund Freud determine all human action.
•
Subsequently in the view of hard line
determinists, humans are not responsible for their
acts.
Libertarianism
•
Libertarianism is the view that our choices are not
determined by the laws of nature. It is often referred
to as indeterminism.
•
One prevalent view of libertarianism is John Paul
Sartre’s existentialism. Sartre claims that humans can
be motivated by a future state, not a past state.
•
Thus, we can conceive and choose “what is not,” i.e.
negativity or non-being. (that is, what does not yet
exist). To be determined would mean that what is past
or present could determine the future (what does not
exist.)
•
Although man is radically free, most forms of
existentialism allow that man can also choose to sell
out his freedom and act as if he is determined by
desires and emotions. Yet, man is always responsible
for his actions.
Compatibilism
•
Compatibilism argues that free will can be made
compatible with determinism.
•
The general strategy of compatibilism is typically
to re-define freedom.
•
Thomas Hobbes said that freedom was only the
absence of physical restraints and causal
determinants do not act as physical restraints.
•
Although classical compatibilist views such as
Hobbes’ appeal to our need to explain the paradox
of free will and determinism, most philosophers
find it unconvincing and ignores the real issue that
cannot be “defined away.”
Compatibilism
•
Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) gives us a compatibilist
proposal that does not merely redefine freedom. It
suggests that whether we have free will or not is not
absolute, but contextual.
•
Kant says that when we act, we have to assume we
are free and when we try to explain our acts
scientifically we have to assume that those same acts
are causally determined.
•
Even as determinists, when we go to a
restaurant we still must take upon ourselves to
order from the menu. We cannot sit back and
just let our desires and tastes take care of it for
us.
Chapter 4
Philosophy and God
(a Metaphysical Study)
Does God Exist?
•
Theism is the belief in a personal God who
is creator of the world and present in its
processes and who is actively engaged in
the affairs of humans.
•
Pantheism is the belief that God is the universe
and its phenomena (taken or conceived of as a
whole). God exists but is not personally involved
in the lives of men.
•
Atheism is the denial of Theism. (Metaphysical
View) It states that there is no God.
•
Agnosticism is the view that it cannot be known
whether God exists or not. (Epistemological
View)
•
According to Logical Positivism, the question
Does God Exist? is meaningless.
First, Can We Even Make Sense
of the Question?
•
•
Surely before trying to answer the question, one
needs to ask the following questions:
•
What does one mean by the word or
concept of “God?”
•
What is the sense of existence that is
being asserted when one says God exists.
Without being clear about these issues, the
argument often becomes mostly subjective.
What Do We Mean by “God?”
•
If we say that God is the “creator of the universe,” do we
mean:
•
1) that there is a Being that is God that could or
could not be the one who created the universe,
but as a matter of fact is the creator of the
universe? Or
•
2) that by definition that God is the Being that
created the universe such that it would be a
logical error to say that God did not create the
universe.
•
Note that if we mean the first, we have still not said who
(or what) God is, apart from what he has done.
•
If we mean the second, of course given the inherent
assumptions, then God exists. But have we committed
the logical fallacy of “begging the question?”
What is the Meaning of Existence that is
Being Used to Say that God Exists?
•
Is existence a property of an entity? I say “This chair
is black.” Blackness is a property of the chair. So that
I would say that this chair has the property of
“existing” and thus there could be chairs some of
which have the property and some don’t. Then would
I say that some chairs exist and some do not like I
would say some chairs are black and some are not?
•
Or is existence of the chair identified in terms of its
relationship to a real world, say Hobbes’ material
world or Berkeley’s mental world? But then what
sense does it make to say that God’s existence is
dependent upon a world that He created and itself
came into “existence” after Him?
•
If not, then what is this form of existence (or reality)
for God that we are asserting?
So, is Logical Positivism right after all?
•
Theism is so confused and the sentences in which 'God'
appears so incoherent and so incapable of verifiability or
falsifiability that to speak of belief or unbelief, faith or unfaith,
is logically impossible.
A. J. Ayer, Language, Truth, and Logic
•
Wikipedia suggests A. J. Ayer (1910-1989) was an atheist.
Ayer’s position on the existence of God should not be
confused with atheism. Of course, claiming that God does
not exist also lacks analytic or empirical verifiability and is
thus also meaningless.
•
Many (perhaps most?) mid to late 20th century philosophers
who abandoned strict logical positivism (including Russell
and Wittgenstein) still found Ayer’s response to this issue
quite credible.
•
On the other hand, maybe the question is too obvious and
important to give up on, so let’s stumble on ….
The Traditional “Proofs”
The Ontological Argument
1.
Saint Anselm (c. 1033-1109) provided the classical
ontological argument (”proof”) for the existence of God:
•
First of all, Anselm argues, God is that Being for
which “none greater can be conceived.”
•
But if God did not exist, then we could conceive a
greater Being, namely a God that does exist.
•
Thus, God must exist.
Note: This argument does not give evidence of God’s
existence. It attempts to prove it.
2.
Unfortunately, the argument seems to suppose that
1.
Existence is a property of a thing, and
2.
Non-existence is an imperfection.
The Ontological Argument:
Kant’s Objection
•
Immanuel Kant argued against Anselm’s
Ontological Argument that it defines God into
existence, that is, Anselm has formed a concept of
God that itself requires existence as a property.
•
Nonexistence was an imperfection, thus God
could not have that property since he by definition
is perfect.
•
And thus, Anselm is begging the question.
•
Few philosophers or theologians today accept
Anselm’s Ontological Argument.
The Traditional “Proofs”
The Cosmological Argument
•
Saint Thomas Aquinas (1225-1274) provided several
cosmological arguments (”proofs”) for the existence of
God that were of the following form:
•
•
•
•
•
First of all, Aquinas argues, “Some things
move.”
What moves must be moved (caused) by
something prior.
This movement (causation) can not have an
infinite regression for it must have an origin.
The origin of the movement (the cause) cannot
itself move (or be caused).
Thus, God (the original mover or first cause)
must exist.
The Traditional “Proofs”
The Cosmological Argument
•
After Newton, it is necessary to refine Aquinas’ first argument
to refer to acceleration rather than motion.
•
More damaging to his argument however is an objection that
questions the assumption that there can be no infinite regress
in the causal sequences of the universe. How do we know
that the universe is not infinite?
•
The “Big Bang” theory seems potentially to counter this
objection. The universe (along with space and time) does
appear to have had a beginning.
•
But the argument still does not preclude alternatives. Could
our universe have come into existence from events in another
universe and thus we could still have an infinity of events in
multiple universes?
The Traditional “Proofs”
The Cosmological Argument
•
Aquinas believed that even if the universe existed
forever, then there would still need to be a First Cause
which would be God.
•
David Hume (1711-1776) disagreed. He claimed that
if one had an explanation for all the parts of a thing (in
particular, all individual causal links in the universe), it
did not require an additional explanation for the
whole.
•
Many analysts, most notably Arthur Schopenhauer
(1788-1860), have argued that the argument’s
premise that every event must have a cause is
actually inconsistent with his conclusion that God
does not have a cause.
The Traditional “Proofs”
The Argument From Design
•
The Argument From Design, also known as the teleological
argument (thus being traced back to Aristotle) states that the
order and purpose manifest in the working of nature, and
particularly, human nature require that there be a logical
designer or God.
•
This argument is very popular today and is probably the most
prevalent and popular argument for the existence of God.
•
The best known early formulation of this argument was given
by the theologian William Paley (1743-1805).
•
Paley compared natural organisms to the mechanism of a
watch and by analogy argued that as the design of the watch
demonstrates the existence of a watchmaker, natural design
shows the work of a “Divine Agency.”
The Argument From Design
•
Relying on a multitude of examples including the
migration of birds, the adaptability of species, and the
human eye, Paley seemed to make a pretty convincing
argument given the science of the day,
•
David Hume did object however on the basis that as an
argument from analogy, the argument was weak.
Arguments from analogy are only as strong as our
knowledge of the relevant similarities. In this one, we do
not know how nature and living things are made and
thus that it is at all “like” a watch being made.
•
Hume was arguing against Paley’s assumption that
complex order can be produced only by an intelligent
being. That may or may not be the case, Hume would
say. Anticipating Darwin, he suggested that perhaps a
finite amount of particles in random motion might
achieve order.
The Argument from Design & Darwinism
•
Charles Darwin (1809-1882) filled in the missing
pieces of Hume’s argument by producing scientific
evidence for just what the mechanism could be in
nature to produce the order and appearance of design
that Hume was suggesting.
•
Darwin suggested that the process was one he called
natural selection. Over millions of years, Darwin
argued, random mechanical processes could produce
organisms that seemed perfectly designed.
•
Darwin contended that life forms exhibit inherited
“variations” that were gradually selected in a “struggle
for survival” to produce new characteristics of species
and even new species.
The Argument from Design & Darwinism
•
Others continue to defend the Argument From Design
while granting the possibility of natural selection
processes, rationalizing that it is then just the process by
which God produces living things.
•
But this later posture gives up a lot of theological
ground. It allows for God to act randomly and that He
allows harmful consequences to exist in his creation.
•
For many others, the Darwinian theory of evolution was
taken as a “threat” to the Argument From Design which
seemed to be the last bastion of a ultimate support for
the existence of God. Thus many theists to this day
resist the Darwinian view which meanwhile has become
the dominant scientific theory within Biology and has
also developed extended applications in other sciences
and our entire intellectual culture.
Do We “Prove” God Exists Because We
Can Talk Meaningfully about HIM?
•
We generally believe that only things that exist can have
properties. Thus, by referring to God with properties, I.e.
omnipotent, do we not “prove” that God exists?
•
•
Probably not of course. We refer to Santa Claus as
“having a white beard” and “living at the North Pole.”
Bertrand Russell proposed a Theory of Descriptions to
account for how we refer to things that may or may not exist.
•
•
Russell’s solution is to take names to be shorthand
for descriptions. For example, “Santa Claus” is a
person who goes by the description that he lives on
North Pole, and delivers toys to kids for Christmas”,
and the sentence “Santa doesn’t exist” should be
understood as “There is no X, such that X is a person
that lives on North Pole, etc., etc…”.
How is it Possible to Talk About God
without Affirming that He Exists?
•
For Russell to say “God does not exist” is to say
“There is no Being, such that the Being “existed” prior
to the creation of the universe, and then created the
universe, etc., etc…”.
•
Thus, Russell (as we mentioned last week) in using
philosophical analysis of language to clarify misguided
metaphysical constructions of supposed “reality.”
•
This seems reasonable enough, but Omaha native
and renowned philosopher of logic Saul Kripke has a
problem with Russell’s view. (Kripke graduated from
Central High.)
How is it Possible to Talk About God if We
are Not Asserting He Exists?
•
Kripke counters: But if Santa does exist, wouldn’t we
be able to imagine Santa not living on the North Pole?
Or wouldn’t we be able to imagine him not delivering
presents for Christmas? If that is so, then Santa can’t
be a shortened description of the type we presented,
because it would fail to refer to Santa in these cases.
•
And now we are back to Square One! Or are we?
•
Has what Kripke shown is that there are still difficulties
in Russell’s analysis, but NOT that the approach of
using language analysis by logic will not work!
•
Thus, as we discussed before, Russell’s theory though
technically perhaps in error has furthered the
clarification of the issue and has advanced our
knowledge, as has Kripke’s criticism of Russell.
Wrapping it up (perhaps) ….
•
If any of these arguments were successful, they still do
not demonstrate that God is necessarily personally
engaged in the affairs of you or I today.
•
Thus, they still may only be an argument for a form of
pantheism or panentheism, not Theism.
•
Baruch Spinoza (1632-1677) argued that if God is
omniscient (all knowing), omnipotent (all powerful), and
omnipresent (always present), then God must be
everything. There can be no world outside God (even
one he created).
•
Panentheism is an alternate view that all of the universe
is in God, but God is GREATER than the universe. God
is unchanging but also among all that HE is, HE is a unity
of all diversity, being and becoming. This is the view of
the Pragmatist Charles Peirce (1839-1914).