Download Slide - Martin Sewell

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts

Investment fund wikipedia , lookup

Beta (finance) wikipedia , lookup

Business valuation wikipedia , lookup

Actuary wikipedia , lookup

Moral hazard wikipedia , lookup

Behavioral economics wikipedia , lookup

Financial economics wikipedia , lookup

Risk wikipedia , lookup

Systemic risk wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
Decision Making Under Risk:
A Prescriptive Approach
Martin Sewell
[email protected]
Behavioral Finance & Economics Research Symposium – 2009
23–25 September 2009
Chicago
The Cambridge Centre for Climate Change Mitigation Research (4CMR)
What is risk?
Risk is uncertainty
We can measure people’s risk tolerance by providing options of the following
form, and asking which option they would prefer.
A) $100
Prefer A
Risk averse
B) 50% chance of $0
Indifferent
towards A and B
Risk neutral
Prefer B
Risk seeking
50% chance of $200
How best to deal with uncertainty?
• A Dutch book is a gambling term for a set of odds and bets which
guarantees a profit, regardless of the outcome of the gamble.
• If an individual is not susceptible to a Dutch book, their previsions are said
to be coherent.
• A set of betting quotients is coherent if (Ramsey 1926; de Finetti 1937;
Shimony 1955) and only if (Kemeny 1955; Lehman 1955) they satisfy the
axioms of probability.
• Probability is necessary when dealing with uncertainty.
• Probability is sufficient when dealing with uncertainty.
• Everyone should be a Bayesian.
Philosophical terminology
• Normative – ‘ought’ (what we should do according to our model)
• Descriptive – ‘is’ (what we actually do in the real world)
• Prescriptive – ‘best compromise’ (what we should do in practice)
Evolution of risk aversion
• Evolution is essentially ‘survivorship bias’.
• Although it is the genes that have evolved to survive, and the individuals
that have evolved to reproduce, individuals must survive in order to
reproduce.
• The most fundamental bias is the status quo bias (also known as
conservatism).
• In general, we prefer to avoid uncertainty.
• We also exhibit a preference for known risks over unknown risks, that is,
we prefer probabilities that are easy to calculate. This is known as
ambiguity aversion.
Loss aversion
• The idea of loss aversion is that losses and disadvantages have a greater
impact on preferences than gains and advantages.
• Our ancestors lived in groups, which meant that respect for private
property would have likely evolved as a Nash equilibrium.
• It could be that apparent ‘loss aversion’ is actually due to a preference for
the status quo.
• Gal (2006) and Gintis (2007)
Growth optimal strategy
• A financial market is a multiplicative process
• loge(wealth) is additive
• Risk neutral in terms of loge(wealth)
• Implies a small degree of risk aversion regarding wealth
• Because the log utility function is concave
• To maximize growth of wealth, maximize the expected value of the
logarithm of wealth after each period (Kelly 1956; Breiman 1961).
Expected utility theory
• Also called von-Neumann Morgenstern utility
• Bernoulli (1738) and von Neumann and Morgenstern (1944)
• Four axioms define a rational decision maker: completeness, transitivity,
independence and continuity
• Let U(Oi) be the utility of outcome Oi, and P(Oi) be the probability of
occurrence of outcome Oi, then
Utility = ∑U(Oi)P(Oi).
• Expected utility theory states that one should choose the option with the
highest utility.
• In this instance, an outcome would be final wealth.
Prospect theory
• Kahneman and Tversky (1979)
• Investors don’t consider expected levels of final wealth, but gains and
losses relative to some reference point.
• Investors are loss averse.
• People tend to overreact to small probability events, but underreact to
medium and large probabilities.
• In cumulative prospect theory (Tversky and Kahneman 1992), cumulative
probabilities are transformed, rather than the probabilities.
• Fourfold pattern of risk attitudes: risk aversion for gains and risk seeking
for losses of moderate to high probability; risk seeking for gains and risk
aversion for losses of low probability.
(Cumulative) Prospect theory
Gains
Losses
Moderate to
high probability
risk aversion
low probability
risk seeking
low probability
risk aversion
Moderate to
high probability
risk seeking
Expected utility theory vs Prospect theory
There are two fundamental reasons why prospect theory (which calculates
value) is inconsistent with expected utility theory.
1. Whilst utility is necessarily linear in the probabilities, value is not.
2. Whereas utility is dependent on final wealth, value is defined in terms of
gains and losses (deviations from current wealth).
Sharpe ratio
• Most prevalent performance metric in use by the financial industry
• Sharpe ratio = E[rp – rf]/σ
• Sharpe ratio assumes either 1) normally distributed returns or 2) meanvariance preferences.
• Sharpe ratio ignores all moments higher than the second
• The third moment is skewness
• People like positive skew
Positive skew
A high Sharpe ratio strategy
• Goetzmann, et al. (2002)
Risk is a personal thing
• Risk preferences vary across individuals.
• Risk preferences vary across different groups of people.
• Barsky, et al. (1997) found that measured risk tolerance is related to risktaking behaviour, but also uncovered some perhaps surprising results.
Risk seeking
• the highly educated
• very wealthy
• heavy drinkers
• those without health insurance
• immigrants
• Jewish
• Hispanics
• (especially) Asians
Risk averse
• those with an average education
• average wealth
• average income
• employees with health insurance
• people in their sixties
Relative risk
• Is your risk profile absolute, or dependent on the risk profile of others
around you?
• For example, one is presumably more likely to gamble if taken to a
casino.
• We are competing with our peers, so it is our relative wealth that counts.
• Therefore, a relative risk profile makes sense for Homo sapiens, if not for
Homo economicus.
Risk and time
• The value of money in the future is determined by interest rates.
• But how do we determine the social discount rate?
• How much do you care about the future in 1, 10, 100 or 1000 years time?
• This is a moral judgement, and morality is a product of the gene-centred
evolutionary forces which shape human social psychology.
• We have evolved on a ‘need to know’ basis, that is, we are only required
to be aware of our proximal motivations (e.g. sex and caring for kin),
rather than our ultimate motivation (reproduction). So most people care
only about their living relatives, not the future of mankind.
Climate change
• Human-induced climate change is a classic case of Hardin’s tragedy of
the commons — the benefits of burning fossil fuels accrue to individuals,
companies and nations, whilst the costs accrue to the planet as a whole.
• Anthropogenic climate change is ‘unequivocal’ (over 90% certain).
• Global warming will largely affect other people’s genes in future
generations, so we need a risk profile that is global in nature, and
considers the present and discounts the future.
• We cannot transcend our genes, so policy makers must reconcile ‘is’ with
‘ought’.
Economics – the dismal science?
• Economics is amenable to quantitative techniques.
• Economics is an approximation of psychology.
• This is why economics suffers from physics envy.
• In economics, why are normative (‘ought’) and descriptive (‘is’) different?
• Humans have evolved ‘as if’ reproduction was the sole goal for which they
were ‘designed’ and everything they do is a means to that end (Williams
1966).
• The neoclassical economist’s canon that individuals are motivated to
maximize utility is accurate if and only if utility corresponds to the number
of their genes in future generations.
Martin Sewell
[email protected]