* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Morality and Justice Final Paper
Humanitarianism wikipedia , lookup
Divine command theory wikipedia , lookup
Antinomianism wikipedia , lookup
Immanuel Kant wikipedia , lookup
Lawrence Kohlberg wikipedia , lookup
Bernard Williams wikipedia , lookup
Morality and religion wikipedia , lookup
Alasdair MacIntyre wikipedia , lookup
The Morals of Chess wikipedia , lookup
Consequentialism wikipedia , lookup
Lawrence Kohlberg's stages of moral development wikipedia , lookup
Moral disengagement wikipedia , lookup
Moral development wikipedia , lookup
Ethical intuitionism wikipedia , lookup
Morality throughout the Life Span wikipedia , lookup
Moral relativism wikipedia , lookup
Secular morality wikipedia , lookup
Thomas Hill Green wikipedia , lookup
1 Morality and Justice “The Categorical Imperative” Final Paper: Topic #3 Brittany Yantis Due: Wednesday, April 25th 2 What makes something right versus wrong? For years, philosophers have strived to provide an answer to this question on how we should live. Immanuel Kant simply believed that there is a single fundamental principle of morality in which all moral duties are based. He calls this the categorical imperative, or the moral law. In his moral theory, he discusses two uses of the categorical imperative, universality and humans as ends, not means. He utilizes the autonomy of the will to describe the absolute moral rules all rational beings are bound by. According to Kant’s ethical theory, in the case of baby Theresa, it would be morally unjustifiable to harvest her organs because it is unable to be universalized and is using her as solely a means. For Kant, there are two types of imperatives we can choose to live by, hypothetical or categorical. Hypothetical imperatives provide a course of action that will help us get what we want. It relies solely on relevant desires to tell us what we “ought” to do. It simply states if you desire X then you should do Y. The categorical imperative, conversely, describes moral obligations that are independent from desires. All of our duties can be derived from this ultimate principle of you should do Z, no matter what you want. There are two ways Kant uses the categorical imperative to help identify whether something is morally permissible or not. First, humans should “act according to that maxim by which you can at the same time will that it should become a universal law” (Rachels 128). We should all act in accordance with a rule, or maxim, that can be consistently willed as a universal law. One must identify the maxim, and determine whether or not they can will for it to become a universal law to be followed by people at all times. If it can’t be universalized, the action is wrong and violates the imperative. Secondly, humans should “act so that you treat humanity, whether in your own person or in that of another, always as an end and never as means only” (Rachels 137). According to Kant, humans have an intrinsic worth, or dignity, that places them above all else. Humans aren’t 3 just driven by passions, but are rational beings driven by reason. It is wrong to use people to achieve our purposes, no matter how good the end may be. The ends never justify the means, but the means justify the ends. The autonomy of the good will explains how the categorical imperative is derived. If one has the utmost respect for the moral law, they possess the good will. It provides us with the ability to reason, the ultimate source of moral worth. To be autonomous means to be bound by the moral law and one’s good will. If something outside one’s will determines their actions, they are by no means free. To be truly free, one’s will is what gives reasons for their actions. Those reasons are universal and bind all rational beings to the moral law. Therefore, in order for one’s actions to be truly free, they must be governed by a maxim that can be universalized, which is essentially the first formulation of the categorical imperative. The authority of the good will lies in us, in our reasons, not in our feelings or inclinations. The good will is good not because of its effects, but because it is good in and of itself, something that only rational beings can possess (Ethics 317). Non-rational creatures are pushed and pulled by their inclinations. Rational agents, however, who possess good will are “free agents capable of making their own decisions, setting their own goals, and guiding their conduct by reason” absent from all desires (Rachels 137). In order to fulfill their moral duty, rational agents must act on that good will and be bound by it. The autonomy of the good will respects rational beings and recognizes them as valuable. Rational beings are the only reason value even exists at all; they are the standard by which everything else compares. Since humans are tied to this moral duty of the good will, they should never be treated as a means, but taken as a dignity worth in and of themselves. The two formulations of the categorical imperative clearly forbid two things; actions that involve maxims that can’t be universalized and treating people as means only. Based on 4 this, Kant would not think that harvesting baby Theresa’s organs would be morally justifiable. Theresa was born with anencephaly, commonly referred to as “babies without brains” (Rachels 1). Important parts of her brain were missing, but autonomic functions like breathing and heartbeat were possible. Theresa’s parents, knowing she would soon die, volunteered her organs for transplant to help other children. Theresa’s organs were never donated as Florida law prohibited taking organs before death. The case sparked a lot of debate over whether or not her parents should have been allowed to donate her organs, or more simply put, to use their child as a means to others ends. According to Kant this is in no way morally justifiable. It goes against his very belief that humans have an important dignity that should not be used purely as a means. Humans, like all rational agents, are a source of value. If your phone breaks, you can simply replace it. If your child dies, you cannot simply just find a new one. Humans have a dignity that all “things” lack. It doesn’t matter how good the ends might be, using Theresa’s organs to save other children’s lives is a manipulation to use her as a means to an end. Many may argue that Theresa had no dignity. She lacked the parts of the brains that would have allowed her to live a full cognitive life. However, according to the categorical imperative, this maxim cannot be universalized based upon a simple test. If we kill baby Theresa, other children’s lives will be saved. We will kill baby Theresa. So everyone should be allowed to kill to save other people’s lives. But if everyone kills, then lives are essentially not being saved at all. So, if we will to kill, then more people end up getting hurt than being saved. Therefore, the maxim of killing baby Theresa does not pass the test. Applying this universally creates a slippery slope. Where is the line? Can I murder an innocent being to take their organs to save my dying friends’ life? No, killing for other’s ends does not apply universally and therefore the action is unjustifiable according to Kantian ethics.