* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Mutual Aid Theory and Human Development
Natural selection wikipedia , lookup
Sociocultural evolution wikipedia , lookup
Evolutionary mismatch wikipedia , lookup
Saltation (biology) wikipedia , lookup
Inclusive fitness wikipedia , lookup
Social Bonding and Nurture Kinship wikipedia , lookup
Genetics and the Origin of Species wikipedia , lookup
The Descent of Man, and Selection in Relation to Sex wikipedia , lookup
Hologenome theory of evolution wikipedia , lookup
Unilineal evolution wikipedia , lookup
Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour Mutual 30:4 Aid Theory and Human Development 0021–8308 391 Mutual Aid Theory and Human Development: Sociability as Primary MICHAEL GLASSMAN A question raised again and again in human development is, does the individual create the social organization, or does the social organization develop the individual. Too often this argument is relegated to the over used, too general, nature/ nurture argument. There are other, possibly more useful, approaches to this dilemma. Among them is the theoretical differentiation between understanding human activity as co-operative joint ventures emanating from egoistic concerns, and seeing human activity as true cooperation. This differentiation has not, for the most part, been carefully analyzed. Too often discussions in this area involve superficial qualities of interaction, learning, and social relationships. The core idea of an absolute difference between cooperation and egoistically driven cooperative activities is rarely touched. One reason for this may be the domination of the egoistic model in the West. The egoistic model of development in many ways reflects a vision of human development originally set forth by Darwin (1859). T.H. Huxley (1908/1955), possibly the most influential interpreter and disseminator of Darwin’s ideas on evolution (Todes 1989, Bowler 1988), strongly pushed this vision of development in scientific circles. In spite of the theoretical domination of egoistic based models of evolution, and the subsequent use of such models in the biological and social sciences, an alternative orientation did emerge roughly in parallel to the Darwin/Huxley paradigm. Mutual aid, a competing theory of evolution, emerged in pre-revolutionary Russia, and reached its apotheosis at the beginning of the 20th century in the work of the sociobiologist Petr Kropotkin. This mature and compelling theory of evolution and socially generated development could potentially force the field to re-think, or at least re-evaluate, some basic precepts concerning development. © The Executive Management Management Committee/Blackwell Committee/Blackwell Publishers Publishers Ltd. Ltd.2000. 2000 Published by Blackwell Publishers, 108 Cowley Road, Oxford, OX4 1JF, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA. 392 Michael Glassman THE BIRTH OF MUTUAL AID Mutual aid theory began to emerge in Russia during approximately the same period that population theory, and the mainstream evolutionary theories that were its progeny, was gaining credence in industrialized England. These two qualitatively different orientations towards evolutionary theory were, at least partially, the result of the disparate social and ecological contexts in which they emerged (Kropotkin 1902, Todes 1989). Industrialized England was obsessed with issues of overpopulation, and trying to beat back questions of class differentiation brought about by the French revolution (Bowler 1988). Pre-revolutionary Russia was largely a vast, untamed wilderness where one could travel for days without seeing another human being. The economy was, for the most part, agrarian, with many peasants meeting their obligations to landlords through farming cooperatives known as mirs. The greatest general threats were the weather and a hostile ecology. Russian biologists such as Andrei Beketov and K.F. Kessler came to embrace many of Darwin’s notions concering evolution, but found the Malthusian inspired idea of an egoistic struggle for survival to be counter-intuitive (Todes 1989). In their experience species did not survive because of intra-specific competition (with the most adaptable organisms emerging as a template for the species). While scarce resources certainly did lead to intra-specific competition, such behavior is ultimately detrimental to species survival in a hostile environment. The only way a species can survive in a hostile environment over time is through extraordinary cooperation (Kropotkin 1902). Three general principles emerges from this orientation, 1) The struggle for existence is a struggle with the general ecology (e.g., natural disasters, harsh environment, predatory species); 2) Successful species are those that engage in cooperation to overcome a hostile ecology; and 3) The fact that cooperation is so essential to species survival makes egoistic behavior detrimental, rather than beneficial, to species survival and development. KROPOTKIN AND SOCIOBIOLOGY (PAST) The most influential mutual aid theorist, and one of the most important evolutionary theorists and sociobiologists of his time, was Petr Kropotkin (Montague 1955). Kropotkin continues to exert influence in the areas of political philosophy, anthropology, and to a lesser extent evolutionary theory. However, even though Kropotkin’s chief concern was with human development, broadly defined, he is rarely referenced in the field. The fact that Kropotkin is remembered at © The Executive Management Committee/Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000 Mutual Aid Theory and Human Development 393 all might be considered extraordinary. As one of the leaders of the anarchist/ communist movement of pre-revolutionary Russia he was exiled early in his career, and spent a good deal of his life as an ex-patriot, moving from country to country in an attempt to support his young family as a news writer and essayist. He depended on his scientific writings as a means of support, with many of the articles anonymous or written under pseudonyms. To this day it is difficult to trace Kropotkin’s writing during the tumultuous period in which Huxley battled for supremacy of Darwin’s theory among the scientific intelligentsia (Woodcock 1993). After the revolution Kropotkin made a triumphant return to the new Soviet Union. However, he quickly became a critic of the Bolsheviks, penning open letters to Lennin chastising him and his movement for their tactics. Kropotkin died soon after his return to the Soviet Union. Kropotkin developed his vision of evolution as dependent on mutual aid as a young naturalist whose early expeditions coincided with the first Russian edition of Origins of the Species. The combined influence of Origins and his first hand expeditionary observations convinced Kropotkin that struggle for survival was best understood as the struggle between organisms and a brutal, variable environment. Kropotkin was able to identify a number of species in the Siberian wilderness that survived because of their ability to put community needs before individual competition for resources.1 His two major named works, Mutual Aid and Ethics, were written primarily while Kropotkin was in exile in England. Mutual Aid outlines how weaker species very often survive in the face of stronger, and at times seemingly insurmountable, opposition through sociability. For example equine species, which have few natural defenses against common predators such as wolves or lions, survive through their ability to stay together and in cooperation in a herd. By staying together in the herd the cooperating equines can repulse almost any predator. Kropotkin’s definition of sociability is the animal’s need for associating with its like. The animal loves its community for community’s sake; and it is within this community of peers that the animal finds its true “joy of life.” In lower life forms, such as bees or ants, this sociability is imposed physiologically. In higher order animals sociability is cultivated for the benefits of mutual aid, and for the sheer pleasure of being part of a community. Mutual Aid as a Response of Huxley Mutual Aid (1902) was originally a series of essays written in response to T.H. Huxley’s movement to use evolutionary theory in general, and Darwinism in particular as a sociological and political tool. Huxley’s major original statement on Darwinism, “Struggle for Existence”, was actually an economic/sociological treatise. His thinking in this work followed a logic extracted from Darwin (1859) © The Executive Management Committee/Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000 394 Michael Glassman and Malthus (1817). This is not to say that Huxley engaged in any type of radical reinterpretation of Darwin. Malthus’ strong influence on Darwin is apparent in many of his writings, and especially in his seminal work Origin of the Species (Kropotkin would later argue that other works such as The Descent of Man were more important precisely because of Malthus’ influence on Origin of the Species). The argument over how important Malthus was to Darwin’s thinking is belied by the fact that Darwin remained very close the Huxley throughout his later life. It is questionable whether Huxley would have argued so vehemently for a Malthusian interpretation of Darwin in scientific circles without Darwin’s open and/or tacit acceptance of that position. A complicating issue is that Kropotkin argued against the Malthusian position while at the same time recognizing Darwin as the most important thinker in evolutionary theory (Montague 1955). Kropotkin was always careful to couch his critiques to the Malthusian position as responses to Huxley. Huxley suggested in his writings that the general task of humans is multiplication of the species, as it is with all species. This is a task with two faces. The darker face of the task involves the necessities for survival when multiplication of species leads to limited resources and one member of the species is pitted against the other. The natural, and logical, denouement of this task is that members of the same species will battle each other without consideration, where “the strongest, the swiftest, the cunningest live to fight another day.” The nature of existence promotes brutality. Huxley believed that humans were the only species to escape this brutality through the creation of society. Society is unique to the human condition, and allows humans to transcend the base conditions of nature and escape this cycle of brutality. The earliest humans, who developed only primitive societies, were still slaves to a base nature that promotes brutality. Only societies that reach a certain level of complexity are able to develop moral ideals and the accompanying social and ecological milieus that allow humans to come together in peace. Ideas such as morality and charity are the residue of a well developed human society. We learn to help others because it helps us to avoid our baser natures, and to learn to survive in cooperation. There is however a caveat to the development of society. Any time that the multiplicative task pushes even the most highly developed social communities beyond their limits in terms of resources, ethical considerations and cooperation crumbles and humans return to their baser natures. There are three basic points in Huxley’s thesis that deserve special consideration in relation to Kropotkin, 1) That humanity, at its most basic level, is a collection of individuals who are concerned with their own survival. 2) That society is created by humans as a complex method of meeting individual needs. Many of the general qualities of society, such as cooperation and charity, exist primarily to maintain peace and security for the individual. © The Executive Management Committee/Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000 Mutual Aid Theory and Human Development 395 Therefore individuals should engage in pro-social activities because it is in their best interests. 3) Society is basically an artificial creation of humans. The individual struggle for survival is still the natural state for humans, as it is for all animals. Society will eventually break down, and when it does it will take attributes such as cooperation and charity with it. Huxley’s focus, and his use of Darwin’s theory in that focus was especially important because of his role as “Darwin’s bulldog” in the long fight to replace theological theories with Darwin’s theory of evolution in England’s scientific circles (Bowler 1988). Darwin considered Huxley his most important proponent and greatest ally in a brutal intellectual fight for which he himself was ill-suited. I bring up this point because I believe it gave Huxley’s treatise extraordinary moment in scientific circles, and it helped to mold the way we think about the convergence between evolution and human development. The essays comprising Kropotkin’s Mutual Aid are a response to Huxley’s thesis; a response that Huxley did not answer. Kropotkin took evolutionary theory and applied it to the human condition in much the same way that Huxley did. However, Kropotkin disdained both Huxley’s individualism and his view of base nature as featuring intraspecific brutality. Kropotkin countered Huxley with the concept of sociability and a vision of base nature as species based communities working together to meet common ends. Kropotkin saw the development of complex human society as being at odds with ethical and cooperative behavior. Complex states set up barriers between everyday human activity and how that activity promotes the commonweal. The more complex the society, the more complex the barriers, the more opaque the connections between activity and community. Kropotkin used the same starting point for his argument as Huxley: the general task of the species is multiplication. But Kropotkin did not see multiplication as a “two-faced” task. Multipication is the result of a single, common quality shared, to one degree or another, by all surviving species. This means that the struggle of individual against individual should not, and could not, be considered a base law of nature. According to Kropotkin the antagonist of multiplication of species is not limited resources, but an unforgiving ecology. The basic aspect of nature leading to multiplication of species is social groups of organisms working together to battle this unmerciful ecology. Society then is the natural state of surviving species. Central to Kropotkin’s thesis is the idea that animals in general, and humans in particular, do not create social systems to meet their needs. Social systems, or more particularly sociability, serves as a maintenance system for humanity ( just as sociability, to one degree or another, serves as a maintenance systems for every species). This is in direct contradiction to Huxley’s argument, which claimed that evolutionary forces developed organisms (humans) capable to creating (social) structures that circumvent the natural forces of evolution. © The Executive Management Committee/Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000 396 Michael Glassman The development of sociability through a process of natural selection Both Huxley and Kropotkin use Darwin’s theory of natural selection as a central theme in their arguments. It would be a mistake to assume that simply because Kropotkin does not reflect the more popular Malthusian based view of natural selection that the concept is not integral to his theory of mutual aid (Montague 1955). It might even be argued that Kropotkin’s view is the more parsimonious and more elegant model of natural selection. The Malthusian inspired natural selection that Huxley adopted from Darwin promotes intraspecific competition as the chief engine of evolutionary change. This view stresses the desires of the individual, and the preservation of individual gene pools, over the needs of the species based group. Huxley is very open about his belief in the individual, and individualism, as the driving force in development. This perspective has been manifested in sociobiology as the organism desires to preserve its own gene line, whether through competition (e.g., Wilson 1975) or altruistic behavior (e.g., Trivers 1971). The natural assumption is that those organisms best able to survive in a competitive atmosphere are those that are best able to preserve their gene lines. The surviving gene lines are thought to be the strongest/most adaptable. Within this Malthusian framework, the human ability to develop social structures that enhance human development is an evolutionary anomaly. That is Huxley (and many of the individualist evolutionary theorists who followed) believed that humans reached the point in their evolutionary history (whether by accident or design) where they developed intellectual and communicative capabilities that enabled creation of rudimentary social structures. These rudimentary social structures served as a buffer against the brutal competition that is the chief engine of evolutionary development. Human society took on a separate trajectory, developing more complex structures of ethics, morality, and industry that would better allow human relationships to (temporarily) transcend the brutality of nature. Eventually however, the forces of nature will pull humans back into the cycle of brutality. Theoretically, this cycle should lead to the development of stronger human gene lines, or a stronger species. Kropotkin does not try to argue that brutality does not exist in nature. But he does make the argument that it has little to do with natural selection in the evolutionary process. He claims that society based life is the most essential ingredient for species survival. It is society that “enable the feeblest insects, the feeblest birds, and the feeblest mammals to resist or to protect themselves from the most terrible birds and beasts of prey; it permits longevity, it enables the species to rear its progeny with the least waste of energy and to maintain its numbers albeit a very slow birth rate” (p. 57, 1902). Kropotkin uses this observation to claim that while different types of qualities allow for greater maintenance of the species in certain circumstances, sociability allows for greater maintenance of the species “under any circumstances.” “Sociability is the greatest advantage in the struggle for life” (p. 57). © The Executive Management Committee/Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000 Mutual Aid Theory and Human Development 397 Kropotkin’s argument for natural selection is based on the fact that ecologies change continuously, often in dramatic and erratic fashions. Change in food sources is only one of a number of possible changes. It is folly to assume that under these circumstances, species are primarily dependent on slow moving genetic variation for survival. It is those organisms that tend towards the formation and maintenance of social organizations that have the greater chance for survival. Those species that find it more difficult to form and maintain social organizations are doomed to decay and eventual extinction. The discovery and adoption of new territories through migration is one of Kropotkin’s strongest arguments of adaptation through sociability. He offers the example of squirrels, which roam over vast areas and change eating habits to adapt to changing conditions. A group of squirrels may find one region so abundant that they become relatively sedentary. As circumstances become more harsh (as they invariably will), a better organized sub-group of squirrels may travel to find a more hospitable environment. While the main group remains in their primary region, the subgroup that migrates may develop into an “incipient” new species. This new species comes into existence without competition or extermination of the original squirrels. It is possible, within Kropotkin’s framework, for different species, one descended from the other, to exist simultaneously for long periods of time. Eventually, the migrating squirrels will survive their sedentary forebears, both because their range of movement creates food sources more easily, and the lifestyle will engender the formation of new habits. This is not to say that genetic variation cannot have an impact, or that genetic variation does not occur through the migration process. Darwin’s (1859) example of wolves becoming slimmer and faster to deal with a changing food population still holds. However, the ability to migrate provides a much more powerful tool for species survival because it can overcome the pure chance qualities of genetic variation. Kropotkin makes the case that the type of mass migration described above demands a higher level of sociability. Migration demands enormous trust and caring between members of the group. Thus a pattern for natural selection of squirrels (and species in general) begins to emerge. The migrating species, based on a population with greater sociability, outlives the older species. There is a natural selection; those that are more capable of migration patterns through mutual aid survive those that are less capable. Kropotkin follows this with the argument that natural selection based on mutual aid makes a good deal more sense than natural selection based on competition. The simplest case for natural selection through competition is the “arithmetical Malthusian argument.” It is an argument that Darwin incorporated into his evolutionary theory and that Huxley extended into a general discussion of the human condition. That is, without competition there would be terrible overpopulation. Kropotkin uses Huxley’s own thesis against him here: natural disasters, diseases, and a continuously changing environment easily keeps populations down. But there is a very important difference between the two theories in the © The Executive Management Committee/Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000 398 Michael Glassman way these natural population checks are understood and treated. Huxley’s brand of Darwinism, while recognizing these natural checks as immediately repugnant, sees them as being “species friendly.” They ultimately work to the advantage of the species by both thinning the population and forcing the types of individual competitions that will strengthen the species through natural selection. It is for this reason that Malthus and Huxley made the political argument that human society should not interfere in any way with these natural checks. One of the advantages of human relations is that they can actually supplement this process through “developed checks” such as poverty, class distinctions, and war. Kropotkin’s mutual aid theory sees these natural checks as “species hostile.” Natural disasters and changes in ecology certainly serve the function of thinning out the population, but ultimately they work against the interests of the species. These natural checks have two main evolutionary effects. First, without some type of cooperative responsive actions these natural checks are strong enough to eventually destroy any species. The purpose of sociability is to protect the reproductive integrity of the species in the face of hostile forces. This means sociability is the most important attribute for the survival of any species. Second, because these checks are such powerful forces, and (because of variability) species are reactive rather than proactive to them, there is little reason to worry about overpopulation. This does not mean that the natural checks are ultimately positive (it is impossible to know what a world would be like without them), they are simply a fact of nature. A more complex argument for competition as the engine of natural selection is that those organisms that do survive natural calamities survive through competition. The natural extension of this line of thinking is that those who do survive, do so because they are stronger (more adaptable) and therefore make the species stronger. Kropotkin responds that those species members that survive calamities such as famine and illness are usually weaker rather than stronger. The only ability survivors have is greater endurance of particular privations; but such endurance does not necessarily engender abilities to escape further privations through adaptation. Natural selection leading to sociability Humans survive and prosper as a species because of their evolutionarily developed abilities of sociability. The most extraordinary quality of this developed sociability in humans is their ability to cultivate, and maintain, unique, complex social organizations. Kropotkin sees sociability as a species wide characteristic, and therefore suggests it is impossible to discern qualitative differences between species wide social organizations. There are differences in complexity, but this is basically a quantitative, and not necessarily productive difference. Increased complexity of social relationships can often lead to deterioration of mutual aid. © The Executive Management Committee/Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000 Mutual Aid Theory and Human Development 399 Human social communities are created naturally, out of the inherent desire for what Kropotkin defines as sociability; and humans then survive and prosper because of these cultivated social organizations. Individuals will knowingly engage in almost any type of activity, including those leading to their own mutilation and/or death, in order to preserve the larger social organization (Kropotkin 1924). This is a function of not only humans and their social communities, but of all animal communities (though it is more of a conscious choice among humans). Kropotkin offers examples of animals that will run recklessly, at great individual risk, simply to maintain the social herd. The same is true of humans who will tolerate the seemingly intolerable (e.g., infanticide, female genital mutilation) in order to maintain the social organization as a whole. Kropotkin believes that many of these intolerable practices must have emerged through sheer necessity, but over history slowly became intertwined within the larger society. Individuals fear the pulling of the single thread might cause the entire social fabric to unravel. The social affiliation offered by the community supercedes individual fear, or pain, or despair. The destruction of the community means the destruction of any joy of life. There is an important distinction to be made here between sacrifice for the community and self sacrifice as it is usually perceived. The sacrifice here is made out of the natural understanding that preservation of community supercedes preservation of self. KROPOTKIN AND SOCIOBIOLOGY (PRESENT) Kropotkin’s thesis seemed to be lost for a number of historical and political reasons. Some of the reasons include the fact that Huxley died without responding to Kropotkin. Kropotkin continued to support his family through a hand to mouth existence. Kropotkin continued to be a political pariah in Western Europe, being jailed a number of times. After the Russian revolution he quickly returned to the Soviet Union, leaving behind any support he had built up in Western Europe. He died before he was able to complete and publish his follow up writings to Mutual Aid. This is not to say that Kropotkin was alone in his view of evolution and the human conditions. By chance or design ideas that resonate with mutual aid theory have emerged, prospered, and in some cases gained great credence, over the last century. Similar ideas have been especially powerful in cellular level discussions of evolution (most social science discussions of evolution have taken place at the species/post-Cambian level). Lynn Margulis (1970) offers a compelling argument for cellular evolution through symbiosis rather than natural selection through mutation (in the process raising the question as to why there are so few interconnections between cellular based and species based discussions of evolution). Margulis’s theory is rich, complex, and highly technical and it is impossible to do it justice in this venue. Her general argument is that by steadfastly claiming © The Executive Management Committee/Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000 400 Michael Glassman that cellular evolution is driven by natural selection through mutation scientists have left themselves defending a difficult, if not impossible, evolutionary progression from prokaryotes cell based organisms (e.g., blue green algae) to eukaryotes cell based organisms (e.g., higher green plants and eventually animals). So determined are scientists to adhere to this “classical” view (which I would argue is symptomatic of the Darwin/Huxley paradigm) that they are willing to depend on an organism that has never been found, and very probably never existed (“uralgae”) as the lynchpin of their theory for the evolution of plants. Margulis counters this inexplicable attachment to natural selection through mutation with the theory of symbiosis. Emphasis is not placed on mutations that better situate an organism to survive in a particular environment, but on cooperation between different types of cellular organisms. In symbiotic theory cells with different attributes merge together (through a form of ingestion), and in the process merge qualities of the two organisms so that they are better able to handle the changes in the ecology. This cellular theory echoes two of Kropotkin’s most important points. 1) That the major threat to organisms are not other organisms but a highly variable ecology, and 2) that it is difficult to make the argument that species survive primarily through genetic mutations (because of the small chances that these mutations will meet the demands of the changing ecology). Margulis (1970) points out that there are three major phenomena that serve as “prerequisites for the organic evolution process: faithful reproduction, mutations, and environmental selective pressures (p. 51).” Malthusian Darwinism tends to focus on the interrelationship between mutations and environmental selective pressures. Both Kropotkin and Margulis emphasize the importance of faithful reproduction, what Margulis refers to as the “sine qua non” of evolution. This is not to say that mutations are unimportant. But mutations have little meaning without reproductive validity and precision. Kropotkin’s thesis that community attributes of cooperation protect faithful reproduction better than any possible individual qualities is a powerful argument. An individual organism attempting to protect its own DNA poses two problems. First, it splits the community, and therefore the greatest asset to faithful reproduction. Second, it actually limits the amount and type of possible mutations. Margulis’ theory makes the important point that, at least on the cellular level, important mutations/changes that meet ecological needs occur when organisms (that under the classical perspective should be in competition) come together and merge attributes. Kropotkin’s ideas continue to have resonance not only in cellular evolution. Some of the core issues raised in the theoretical war Kropotkin waged with Huxley in the early part of the century re-emerged five decades later in arguments over the uses and abuses of sociobiology. The new sociobiology, as represented by theorists such as E.O. Wilson (1975) and Robin Trivers (1971), was, in one essential way, a throw back to the Malthus/Darwin/Huxley paradigm. It promotes the idea that individual organisms act out of individual needs and through these activities create social systems that engender species maintenance. For © The Executive Management Committee/Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000 Mutual Aid Theory and Human Development 401 example Trivers (1971), in his theory of reciprocal altruism, suggests that like members of species develop reciprocal helping systems (rudimentary social organization), because the helping animal supports its own survival, or the survival of its progeny, by engaging in such activities. It is tempting to equate reciprocal altruism with mutual aid theory because of their superficial similarities; but at a basic theoretical level they are diametrically opposed. Trivers sees social organization as emerging out of the needs of individual organisms. Kropotkin sees incipient species as emerging out of the societies animals develop through sociability. The social organizations themselves are primary; the fact that they also act as species maintenance organizations is providential, but secondary. Trivers, in his theory of reciprocal altruism, is promoting a basically egoistic orientation. Marshall Sahlins (1976) played Kropotkin’s role in the second debate, but without the evolutionary/biological overtones. Sahlins made the argument that biology cannot be used to explain culture. Human social systems, as represented by culture, are basically arbitrary. For instance, it is very difficult to make the argument that kinship systems are organized for maintenance of the “gene pool.” Kinship systems are some times the result of acts of birth (reflecting the new sociobiological orientation), but could also just as easily be the result of acts of exchange, or residence. Sahlins buttresses his argument in much the same way that Kropotkin did; by describing the structures of actual diverse societies. Sahlins makes the compelling argument that, in general, culture reflects the pragmatic cooperation that is essential for human species survival much more than it does egoistically conceived natural selection. Sahlins makes four judgments concerning the development of human society that are very sympathetic to Kropotkin’s general outline for mutual aid theory. The first judgment is that human kinship relations are not the result of any genetic coefficients (i.e., egoistic models where organisms attempt to promote their own DNA), but are arbitrary. There are always rules of marriage, residence, and descent, but the rules are created through the history of the social organizations themselves. This reflects Kropotkin’s basic premise that it is the social organization itself which is the constant, and that individuals then develop out of this organization. Sahlin’s second judgment, closely related to the first, is that “as the culturally constituted kinship relations govern the real processes of cooperation in production, property, mutual aid, and marital exchange, the human systems ordering reproductive success have an entirely different calculus than that predicted by kind selection and, sequitir est, an eogoistically conceived natural selection” (Sahlins 1977, p. 57). In this quote Sahlins makes almost exactly the same point to the modern sociobiolgists that Kropotkin made to Huxley and his followers 70 years earlier. The social structures of human societies around the world simply do not support the thesis of egoistically driven models of natural selection. The most “primitive” societies very often find a manner of social existence based almost solely on cooperation for the sake of cooperation. These societies are at least as ethical as the more complex societies that judge them. © The Executive Management Committee/Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000 402 Michael Glassman Sahlins third judgment is that “kinship is a unique characteristic of human societies, distinguishable precisely by its freedom from natural relationships” (p. 58). While Kropotkin would have agreed with the sentiment behind this statement, including the idea that kinship is a unique characteristic of human societies, he almost certainly would have disagreed with the idea that all other animal societies are based solely on natural relationships (i.e., blood connections). All species are dependent on sociability in the struggle for survival. Organisms must care about members of their societal group rather than members of their direct genetic group (granting that they are often one in the same) in order to face the dangers of a brutal ecology. The migrating squirrels come together to form a subgroup not because they share specific DNA, but because they share the ability and the desire to form a social organization capable of engaging in more advanced migratory activities. However, it is obvious to Kropotkin that humans have reached an extraordinary level of sociability; one that allows them to come together and protect each other based on socially determined abstract rule systems. As rule systems become more abstract, connections between members of social organizations become more abstract. Sahlins’ fourth judgment is that what human societies reproduce “is not human beings qua human beings, but the system of social groups, categories, and relations in which they live” (p. 60). Here Sahlins comes close to restating Kropotkin’s major thesis (although he limits it to humans). Organisms, including humans, come into the world as part of a social organization. When they reproduce, they do not reproduce themselves as much as the social organization they are part of. The higher the level of species sociability, the more apparent this becomes. Sahlins argument for pragmatic cooperation as the primary force in human relations is, in many ways, a close replication of Kropotkin’s thesis of mutual aid. The main difference between the two is that while Sahlins simply minimizes the Malthus/Darwin/Huxley orientation of biology and evolution, Kropotkin actually offers a legitimate and compelling alternative. Sahlins’ arguments have not, to this point, had the same resonance in the field of human development as those of Wilson and Trivers. Kropotkin however, offers an important biological counterpart to Sahlins’ theory of culture, and together they force a number of developmental issues to the forefront. The idea of sociability as primary suggests some perplexing problems for theorists at a very basic level, and an avenue for re-evaluation of a number of developmental issues.2 Kropotkin’s theory as group selection In modern parlance Kropotkin’s theory is one of group selection. It is, as a matter of fact, about as strong a group selection theory as one can imagine. This creates difficulties because of the emphasis that has been put on individual selection models in evolutionary biology. Since the 1960s group selection models © The Executive Management Committee/Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000 Mutual Aid Theory and Human Development 403 have not only been castigated as having little merit, but as not even being worthy of discussion (Sober & Wilson 1998). This despite the fact that individual selection theorists may not have as quite as strong an argument as they believe. It would be impossible to present the entire history of the individual selection/ group selection debate here (see Sober & Wilson 1998 for an extensive review), even as it relates only to Kropotkin. Instead I will concentrate on two ideas, 1) Why Kropotkin sees group selection as far more important than individual selection in evolution of species; and 2) Why Kropotkin’s theory of sociability does not fall into the natural selection trap that theories promoting the development of altruism often do. The idea of individual selection is often promoted as the driving force in evolutionary development. This argument generally comes from Darwin’s Origin of the Species (1865) and it based on the idea that certain individual organisms within groups develop qualities that better allow them to succeed and prosper in the current environment. There is the already mentioned famous example of the development of sleek wolves that are better at catching deer. There is Williams’ (1966) point that a fleet herd of deer is fleet because being fleet benefits each individual deer. The faster deer survive while the slower deer fall prey (presumably to the sleek wolves). In a nutshell this is the argument for individual selection as the primary force in evolutionary change (I will not go into the relationship between individual selection and Malthusian population dynamics). The group selection model also stems from Darwin, but primarily his writings in The Descent of Man (1871). Some theorists suggest that Darwin simply mentioned ideas underpinning group selection in this book, but never really fleshed them out (Sober & Wilson 1998). Kropotkin however quotes heavily from this book (1924) and makes the claim that it contains the stronger of Darwin’s theses. In any case group selection is based on the idea that it is the development of group qualities, rather than the development of individual qualities, which allow for long term survival of the species. Kropotkin interprets these group qualities as being far more adaptive than the development of individual qualities. They are based on intraspecies relationships and the way these relationships work towards survival under any number of circumstances (both Kropotkin and Darwin saw in this the roots of morality/ethics). Herein lies Kropotkin’s argument against individual selection as a long term force in evolution. The development of individual qualities usually only meet needs within a limited ecological framework. The deer who become faster have a better opportunity of escaping (one type of ) predator. But this is all the development of this quality offers the deer population. Kropotkin’s perspective is that dependence on this type of natural selection in brutal, wildly varying ecologies makes little evolutionary sense. Within a relatively short time circumstances were going to arise where speed was not a particularly helpful quality, and might even © The Executive Management Committee/Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000 404 Michael Glassman be a hindrance (e.g., certain types of storms). What would happen to the species at this point? Individual selection only leads to short term solutions, not long term survival in a variable ecology. There is a second point to be made from a Kropotkin perspective along these same lines. Individual selection suggests an extraordinary level of coincidence between changes in the ecology and genetic mutation. Once again, Kropotkin tries to make the argument that changes in ecological milieu are very often random and sudden. Many times species cannot depend on development of individual qualities to meet needs when there is a change in the food supply. What if there weren’t any genetic structures leading to a sleeker, faster wolf ? Do the wolves automatically become extinct? Group based activities such as migration seem to be of far more worth to the survival efforts of a species than any types of individual variations. It is in fact far more likely that individual variations would occur in response to changing habits as a result of migration. This is not to say that individual selection does not occur, or that it does not offer short term solutions (in terms of evolutionary time) for certain species. But individual selection has little to offer long term survival of the species as opposed to group selection. The altruism trap Group selection’s greatest difficulty in acceptance involves what I will term the altruism trap. The great majority of group selection theories are based in the development of altruism within the group (Sober & Wilson 1998). Altruism is actually a very broad term as used by evolutionary theorists (that can conceivably include Kropotkin’s notion of sociability), but it is generally defined as the willingness to sacrifice benefits towards the self in order to benefit the group. The general argument against altruism is that organisms willing to sacrifice their own benefits have a far lesser chance of survival than organisms that are continuously looking after their own benefits. The self-sacrifice model of altruism has historically been a difficult one to make (Sober & Wilson 1998). The self-sacrifice model generally suggests that more altruistic members of the community will be lost through the course of natural survival activities. The non-altruistic “free-rider” organisms both benefit from the sacrifices of the altruistic organisms while at the same time avoiding risk. The argument whether such a model is mathematically viable has been going on for a number of years (logically the “free riders” genes should eventually overwhelm the altruistic organism gene pool). Sober and Wilson (1998) make a valiant attempt at showing it is mathematically possible for these types of altruistic/self-sacrifice communities to evolve if the sacrifice benefits the community to the extent that a credible population of altruistic organisms is maintained within the larger population. © The Executive Management Committee/Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000 Mutual Aid Theory and Human Development 405 It is important to realize that while Sober and Wilson have made a cogent argument for group selection through self-sacrifice/altruism, this is not Kropotkin’s theory of group selection. Kropotkin would, I believe, offer a very different explanation, one that points to important distinctions between sociability and altruism as it is usually conceived. In the type of altruism described above the self-sacrificing organisms can be viewed as individuals attempting to save a conglomeration of individuals that might or might not be a community. For Kropotkin it is the community that is primary and all things emanate from the community. This is a subtle but very important difference. If sociability is the key factor organisms would not automatically sacrifice themselves for the free rider dominated species group. This is because it splits the community and works against sociability rather than towards it. A division of self-sacrificing and free rider organisms is a community division that cannot easily be rectified. In a mutual aid theory of evolution the more sociable organisms will attempt to engage the less sociable free riders in a more collectively oriented solution to their dilemma (e.g., a change of venue). If the sociable organisms are unable to convince the “free riders” they will eventually break off through the process of migration, and form their own community. The new community may eventually become an “incipient species”. Sociability is far more neutral than altruism in individual selection. I believe that Kropotkin’s thesis may be a stronger argument for group selection than the self-sacrifice/altruism position. The neutrality of sociability in individual survival offers a compelling reason as to why the mutual aid instinct is the primary factor in the survival and the development of species. KROPOTKIN AND THE ISSUE OF CULTURE Kropotkin offers some important additions to perspectives on culture and the role that culture plays in human development. Through his writings he allows a vision of human culture as the far end of a continuum, directly related to, but qualitatively different from the social organization of other animals. This model suggests that the core constituent of culture is mutual aid, and that the way animal societies in general, and human culture in particular, are best understood as the way mutual aid manifests itself within the biological and ecological parameters of the species. I would argue that this represents a different perspective on culture than is usually found in discussion of human development. In general culture is seen as something that is separate from the relationship humans have with the rest of nature; as something created by humans, in an attempt to advance or create a more hospitable environment for humans. It accomplishes this by either by harnessing the power of the human genetic structure (Scarr 1993), or creating collective utilitarian organizations that more efficiently meet the needs of their members (Vygotsky 1987). There is a third view of culture, as © The Executive Management Committee/Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000 406 Michael Glassman a disembodied non-rational rule system that drives human activity (Shweder 1984). It is this third view that probably has the most to gain from Kropotkin’s perspective. Those who seem to argue for culture as a harnessing force take the position that individual DNA is primary in development, but that trajectory of the individual is at least partially determined by the environment (e.g. Scarr & McCartney 1983, Geary 1995, 1996). Environment can take any number of forms, but one of the major forms is certainly the type(s) collective organization that can be considered culture. Geary for example makes the argument that certain individual cognitive abilities (mathematical) are primarily driven by biological predispostions. The sensory and perceptual systems that form the basis for the abilities are the result of evolutionary pressures (individual selection). Social and environmental information plays the role of “activating” force. In this view humans have specific individualized abilities developed over the course of evolution that can be used in exerting control over their environment. Culture acts as an activating force and in some cases a canalizing device for such abilities. It is not clear exactly how these collective organization come about, but because individual abilities are primary, genesis of culture most probably has some type of Huxleyan basis (i.e., a unique human conception, created by individual humans, for the benefit of humans). A second view of culture sees the social/cultural construct as primary in immediate development, but still as a unique creation of humanity (Vygotsky & Luria 1993). This view of “cultural psychology” sees culture as utilitarian, based on meeting the needs of a social organization’s members most efficiently. This view of culture is heavily invested in the power of praxis, human activity developed through social relationships that directly meets needs. “Life involves before everything else eating and drinking, a habitation, clothing and many other things. The first historical act is thus the production of means to satisfy these needs . . .” (Marx and Engels 1965, p. 39). Pivotal to this view of culture is tool use and education/teaching. This reflects the more general notion that the discriminating factor of human culture is the ability to teach tool use to neophytes so efficient methodologies can be passed down from generation to generation. The idea of culture as a mediating force for the teaching of socially efficient behavior is central to Vygotsky (1987) and many of the Activity Theorists who followed him (Leontiev 1981, Glassman 1996). Recently theorists such as Rogoff and Lave have the pursued the idea that cultures serve important educational functions that meet the needs of the social organization. Rogoff and Chauajay (1995) describes two types of learning in cultural contexts. Individuals learn through participation in shared activities that are derived from community traditions and constitute community traditions. The emphasis seems to be on individual development through a teaching learning process that promotes the general culture. Lave and Wenger (1991) introduce the notion of legitimate peripheral participation, which focuses on the role of apprenticeships involving activity with © The Executive Management Committee/Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000 Mutual Aid Theory and Human Development 407 some discernable community purpose. General culture fosters individual cognition to meet its purposes. The view of human culture as a utilitarian endeavor developed through particularly human capabilities in order to tame, and possibly dominate, their environment is a seductive one. Such a notion, 1) Places humans on a qualitatively different evolutionary plane than all other animals (if we must admit some great apes as junior partners we will do so . . . grudgingly). 2) Offers a simple and easy explanation as to why culture exists, while at the same time making the argument that all benefits of human culture are well deserved . . . because humans created it. Culture as non-rational The idea that culture is utilitarian is based in the notion that rationalism is the primary force in cultural (and ontogenetic) human development. At its core this is a specific teleological argument in which rationalism is the ultimate adaptive function, and therefore the natural goal of all humans and human societies. A culture starts out with limited rational capabilities. A series of interactions in the world forces the development of greater rationality (or eventual extinction of the species group). This is a deficit model of development with roots in Huxley’s thesis. The greatest difficulty with rationality as the ultimate adaptive function is that it is belied by evidence concerning actual cultures in the world. Theorists as diverse as Kropotkin (1902), Levy-Bruhl (1926), Sahlins (1976) and Shweder (1984) have pointed out numerous successful cultures in which social institutions and rule systems are not rational. A great many cultures are non-rational (very different from irrational or arational) in that social institutions and rule systems have little (if any) direct relationship to utility. Rather than seeing functionality as driving culture, it is culture that drives the functionality and/or maintenance of the activity (i.e., members of a cultural group engage in activity because it promotes the culture) (Miller 1999). This realization however still leaves a question. If culture does not come into existence for transparently utilitarian purposes, why then does it come into existence, and why does it continue? In other words, if rationality is not the adaptive function that accounts for culture, then what is? It is a rational question in search of a non-rational answer. Sahlins (1976) for instance provides strong evidence for successful cultures as non-rational, what he terms “cultures of meanings”. The raison de etre for a culture of meanings is mostly implicit in Sahlin’s writings: the human desire to live in a community. There is a willingness to participate in and maintain social superstructures for the sake of community, rather than for any utilitarian or rational purpose. © The Executive Management Committee/Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000 408 Michael Glassman Social constructionists such as Shotter (1992) take a similar position from a distinctly more philosophical perspective. Shotter for instance emphasizes that you must understand the development and maintenance of intricate social systems through social activity itself, rather than assuming some rational meaning/ progression driving the development. He makes the case (1984) that the unit of analysis in understanding (deconstructing) social systems is joint activity. At the core of this thinking is the same point made by Sahlin’s (and from an evolutionary perspective Kropotkin) that it is the desire for social relationships, or more specifically sociability, that is at the core of human activity. The ways in which these social relationships develop is relatively tangential to what is driving human society. Kropotkin’s theory offers a well argued, developmental explanation for why this human desire for community is so strong it overpowers all other considerations. For Korpotkin, culture is not unique to the human condition (this is actually an area where he may be at odds with Sahlins), but it is an expansion of the mutual aid instinct that exists to one degree or another in all species. The addition of human language and abstract thinking gives mutual aid a different quality in human activity, but only by means of extending it in a new direction. Humans live in cultures not because they meet their needs or act as collective maintenance systems, but because humans are naturally drawn together and find greater “joy of life” in community rather than out. The fact that human communities do act as maintenance systems is of course not just a happy coincidence. It is the result of long term evolutionary pressures. Sociability in and of itself serves the adaptive function; mediating forces such as rational and nonrational cultural institutions are only that, mediating forces. The desire to live within a culture is primary. The culture itself is a very general vehicle for adaptation to circumstances similar to the way other animal societies are general vehicles for adaptation to circumstances. Teaching and passing down of culture emerges in humans much the same way that migration emerges in squirrels; level of sociability combines with other species wide qualities to create a natural momentum for this type of activity. Mutual aid and theories of social behavior One area where Kropotkin’s ideas could have an important influence is very obviously the social realm. A good deal of the research in the areas of social behavior and social development has approached relevant questions from the perspective of individual responsibility, individual choices, and or individual activity. In many ways it is the same argument that individuals create social community through their actions that is at the base of the ideas proposed by Trivers (1971). Mutual aid was originally envisioned as much an ethical theory as an evolutionary theory. Mutual aid theory sees social/ethical behavior as © The Executive Management Committee/Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000 Mutual Aid Theory and Human Development 409 occurring and developing naturally through transparent social interactions. Society does not develop ethical behavior to enhance the human condition, but it can subvert ethical behavior to enhance itself. The concept of morality takes on a very different tenor in this light. Moral rules are created by society to protect the integrity of the society, but may actually work against the natural social/ethical behavior of human community. Mutual aid theory could offer a fresh perspective on some of the landmark research done by social theorists such as Milgram (1974), Sherif (Sherif, Harvey, Hoyt, Hood & Sherif 1961) and Asch (1956). For instance, it is possible to reconceptualize the obedience to authority in the Milgram experiments in terms of Milgram’s ability to define the social community, and present his proposed activity in the context of rule systems integral to the survival of the that community. The more opaque and abstract the rule system (divorced from actual community) the easier it became for the subjects of the study to follow moral imperatives at the expense of human community. Mutual aid may have even more important implications for research and theory involving social development (particularly moral development). Much of socio-moral theory is dominated by the idea that humans create moral systems out of egoistic concerns (e.g., Turiel 1983, Kohlberg 1981, Eisenberg 1996). Turiel suggests that individuals recognize the absolute difference in the moral quality of various activities. For instance, an individual understands the difference between an activity that is conventional and one that is moral. The assumption then is that humans build their social organizational systems based on this differentiation. Mutual aid theory suggests that any such differentiation, and indeed the way any member of any community understands the ethical dimensions of an activity, is the residue of that activity as it affects that community. The ethical nature of an activity is primarily dependent on the transparent impact that activity has on the community. Thus when children, or adults, are confronted with activities with obvious community repercussions they will take these activities as far more serious than activities with opaque, or no apparent, repercussions. Of primary importance is not the individual’s thinking about such activity, but the ways in which the community is defined, or understood by the target member of the community. The research on pro-social development, and its reliance on concepts of individual altruism might also find some relevance in Kropotkin’s ideas. Eisenberg (1996) suggests that individuals engage in altruistic, helping behaviors because they view themselves as altruistic. The reasoning and behavior of the individual reflects “the individuals hierarchy of goals in a given context” (p. 61). Other prosocial researchers such as Staub (1984) seem to reflect the same individualist, personal orientation to perceived pro-social behavior. Kropotkin might dismiss this notion of altruism (which Eisenberg says is only a sub-category of pro-social) and claim that activity should be understood as pro-social, but from a social rather than an individual perspective. Any activity that works towards the benefit © The Executive Management Committee/Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000 410 Michael Glassman of the community is pro-social. But it is also true that for the type of abstract ethical systems that humans create the definitions of pro-social activity come from the social community itself. Individuals then engage in pro-social activity if they feel a member of that community, and through membership an obligation to maintain that community. This leads to a very interesting idea; that pro-social activity is completely dependent on the individual’s sense of community. Overlapping communities, where individuals move back and forth between social organizations that engage them as cooperative members, and social organizations that do not engage certain individuals to the point that they have feelings of sociability, make the examination of pro-social and/or anti-social activity extraordinarily complex. CONCLUSION This paper has attempted to define mutual aid theory as an alternative theoretical base for the study of human development and activity. The idea that humans are social creatures first, and that individuality emerges from sociability, may open new, important avenues of research, and certainly allows for interesting re-interpretation of existing theory and research. In addition to the examples mentioned in this paper, mutual aid theory could have an impact on the way the field approaches emotional development, language development, and cognitive development. Mutual aid and pragmatic cooperation are still relative mysteries precisely because they have been ignored for so long. There is, however, little doubt that such orientations offer a fresh perspective for much of the research that has been, and continues to be done. Michael Glassman Department of Human Development & Family Sciences The Ohio State University 135 Campbell Hall 1787 Neil Avenue Columbus, OH 43210-1295 Phone: 614-292-5622 e-mail: [email protected] NOTES 1 Kropotkin’s theory has scientific merit within the particular world hypothesis it occupies (i.e., organicist). Kropotkin’s theory is based on a large body of research (based not only on his own empirical research, but the research of a large body of Russian biologists—see Todes 1989 for an expanded discussion). It is not based on a religious or even overtly philosophical system. It has, I believe, force, weight and cogency. Mutual aid © The Executive Management Committee/Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000 Mutual Aid Theory and Human Development 411 theory is a logical argument extremely well constructed where, if the premises are correct, Kropotkin’s major thesis cannot be denied. 2 A third member of a triumvirate offering a cohesive argument for cooperation as the driving force in human relations on a species, cultural, and social level is Emile Durkheim. Durkheim’s concept of a “conscience collective” (1960) captures the idea that humans are in essence social animals who desire and pursue collective activity for the sake of participating in collective activity. The most primary human societies are those in which the attitudes of the individual are a microcosm of the attitudes of the community. Perhaps even more interesting in Durkeim’s work is his view of later societies as advanced organisms which are made of different parts functioning interdependently, maintaining a certain level of cohesiveness in the face of a more dispersed social community, and the way this mirrors Kropotkin’s view of later complex societies. Durkheim is certainly not the anarchist that Kropotkin is, and does not take as dim a view of these later, complex societies. But they both have similar visions of what drives the development of social collectives. REFERENCES A, S. (1956). Studies of independence and conformity: a minority of one against the unanimous majority. Psychological Monographs, 70:no.9. B, P. (1988). The Non-Darwinian Revolution: Reinterpreting a historical myth. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. D, C. (1859/1968). The Origin of the Species. Middlesex, England: Penguin Books. D, C. (1871/1971). The descent of man and selection in relation to sex. Adelaide, Australia: Griffin Press. D, E. (1960). The division of labor in society. (G. Simpson trans.). Glencoe, Ill: Free Press. E, N. (1996). Caught in a narrow Kantian perception of prosocial development: Reactions to Campbell and Christopher’s critique of moral development theory. Developmental Review, 16, 48–68. G, D.C. (1996). The evolution of cognition and the social construction of knowledge. American Psychologist, 51, 265–266. G, D.C. (1995). Reflection of evolution and culture in children’s cognition: Implications for mathematical development and instruction. American Psychologist, 50, 24–37. G, M. (1996). Understanding Vygotsky’s motive and goal: An exploration of the work of A.N. Leontiev. Human Development, 39, 309–327. H, T.H. (1908). The struggle for existence in human society. The Nineteenth Century, 23, 161–180. K, I. (1996). The Critique of Pure Reason. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co. (Original work published 1781, 1787). K, L. (1981). Essays on Moral Development Vol. I: The philosophy of moral development. San Francisco: Harper & Row. K, P. (1902/1955). Mutual aid: A factor in evolution. Boston: Extending Horizons Books. K, P. (1924). Ethics: Origin and Development. New York: The Dial Press. L, J. & W, E. (1991). Situated learning: Legitimate peripheral participation. Cambridge England: Cambridge University Press. L, A.N. (1981). Problems of the development of the mind. Moscow: Progress Press. M, T.R. (1817/1958). An essay on population. New York: Dutton Press. © The Executive Management Committee/Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000 412 Michael Glassman M, L. (1970). Origin of Eukarytic Cells. New Haven: Yale University Press. M, S. (1974). Obedience to Authority. New York: Harper & Row. M, J.G. (1999). Cultural psychology; Implications for basic psychological theory. Psychological Inquiry, 10, 85–91. M, A. (1955). Introduction, Mutual aid: A factor in evolution. Boston: Extending Horizons Books. P, J. (1924). Judgment and reasoning in the child. New York: Harcourt Press. R, B. and C, P. (1995). What’s become of research on the cultural basis of cognitive development. American Psychologist, 50, 859–877. S, M. (1976). The use and abuse of biology: an anthropological critique of sociobiology. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. S, S. (1993). Biological and cultural diversity: The legacy of Darwin for development. Child Development, 64, 1333–1353. S, S. & MC, K. (1983). How people make their own environments: A theory of genotype → environment effects. Child Development, 54, 424–435. S, M., H, O.J., H, B.J., H, W.R., and S, C.W. (1961). Intergroup conflict and cooperation: The robber’s cave experiment. Norman: University of Oklahoma Book Exchange. S, J. (1992). Social constructionism: relativism, moral sources, and judgments of adequacy. In D.N. Robinson (Ed.) Social discourse and moral judgment. San Diego: Academic Press. S, J. (1984). Social Accountability and Selfhood. Oxford: Blackwell. S, R. (1984). Anthropology’s romantic rebellion against the enlightenment or there’s more to reason than thinking and evidence. In R.A. Shweder & R.A. Levine (Eds.) Cultural theory: Essays on mind, self, and emtoin. (pp. 27–66). New York: Cambridge University Press. S, E. and W, D.S. (1998). Unto Others. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press. S, L. (in press). Epistemological principles for developmental psycholoy: Frege & Piaget. New Ideas in Psychology. S, E. (1984). Notes toward an interactionist-motivational theory of the determinants and development of (pro)social behavior. In E. Staub, D. Bar-Tal, J. Karylowski, & J. Reykowski (Eds.), Development and maintenance of prosocial behavior: International perspectives on positive morality (pp. 29–49). New York: Plenum Press. T, D. (1989). Darwin without Malthus: The struggle for existence in Russian evolutionary thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press. T, R.L. (1971). The evolution of reciprocal altruism. Quarterly Review of Biology, 46, 35–57. T, E. (1983). The development of social knowledge: Morality and convention. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. © The Executive Management Committee/Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000