Download Political Theory

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts

Daqin wikipedia , lookup

Ancient Roman architecture wikipedia , lookup

Promagistrate wikipedia , lookup

Executive magistrates of the Roman Republic wikipedia , lookup

Roman law wikipedia , lookup

Food and dining in the Roman Empire wikipedia , lookup

Travel in Classical antiquity wikipedia , lookup

Roman army of the late Republic wikipedia , lookup

History of science in classical antiquity wikipedia , lookup

Roman economy wikipedia , lookup

Roman funerary practices wikipedia , lookup

Roman Republican governors of Gaul wikipedia , lookup

Elections in the Roman Republic wikipedia , lookup

Roman agriculture wikipedia , lookup

Culture of ancient Rome wikipedia , lookup

Roman dictator wikipedia , lookup

Education in ancient Rome wikipedia , lookup

Senatus consultum ultimum wikipedia , lookup

Roman historiography wikipedia , lookup

Early Roman army wikipedia , lookup

Constitutional reforms of Augustus wikipedia , lookup

Cursus honorum wikipedia , lookup

History of the Roman Constitution wikipedia , lookup

Constitutional reforms of Sulla wikipedia , lookup

Tyrant wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
Political
Theory
http://ptx.sagepub.com/
The Tyranny of Dictatorship : When the Greek Tyrant Met the Roman
Dictator
Andreas Kalyvas
Political Theory 2007 35: 412
DOI: 10.1177/0090591707302208
The online version of this article can be found at:
http://ptx.sagepub.com/content/35/4/412
Published by:
http://www.sagepublications.com
Additional services and information for Political Theory can be found at:
Email Alerts: http://ptx.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts
Subscriptions: http://ptx.sagepub.com/subscriptions
Reprints: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.nav
Permissions: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav
Citations: http://ptx.sagepub.com/content/35/4/412.refs.html
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
The Tyranny of Dictatorship
When the Greek Tyrant Met the
Roman Dictator
Political Theory
Volume 35 Number 4
August 2007 412-442
© 2007 Sage Publications
10.1177/0090591707302208
http://ptx.sagepub.com
hosted at
http://online.sagepub.com
Andreas Kalyvas
New School for Social Research
The article examines the inaugural encounter of the Greek theory of tyranny
and the Roman institution of dictatorship. Although the twentieth century is
credited for fusing the tyrant and the dictator into one figure/concept, I trace the
origins of this conceptual synthesis in a much earlier historical period, that of
the later Roman Republic and the early Principate, and in the writings
of two Greek historians of Rome, Dionysius of Halicarnassus and Appian of
Alexandria. In their histories, the traditional interest in the relationship
between the king and the tyrant is displaced by a new curiosity about the
tyrant and the dictator. The two historians placed the two figures alongside
one another and found them to be almost identical, blurring any previous
empirical, analytical, or normative distinctions. In their Greco-Roman
synthesis dictatorship is re-described as ‘temporary tyranny by consent’ and
the tyrant as a ‘permanent dictator.’ Dictatorship, a venerated republican
magistracy, the ultimate guardian of the Roman constitution, is for the first
time radically reinterpreted and explicitly questioned. It meets its first critics.
Keywords: Dionysius; Appian; tyranny; dictatorship; Athens; Rome;
democracy; republicanism
F
or most of the twentieth century the concepts of dictatorship and tyranny
were treated as synonyms, two names for one form of autocratic political rule. “Dictatorship,” Fossey John Cobb Hearnshaw wrote in 1934, “is the
form of government the Greeks have very correctly connoted with the term
‘tyranny.’”1 The dictator and the tyrant were fused together in a single figure,
that of illegality, violence, and arbitrariness, and perceived as a common
threat to political freedom, constitutionalism, and the rule of law,2 a threat the
Author’s Note: I am grateful to Andrew Arato, Melvin Richter, Dmitri Nikoulin, Vassilis
Lambropoulos, and Mary Dietz for their advice and insightful comments on earlier drafts of
this article. I would also like to thank Nadia Urbinati, Jason Frank, Gerasimos Karavitis, Ann
Kornhauser, Claudio Lopez-Guerra, Jim Miller, and the two anonymous reviewers for their
helpful and constructive suggestions and criticisms.
412
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
Kalyvas / The Tyranny of Dictatorship
413
ancients had formulated as political enslavement. Accordingly, throughout
the century, this conceptual identification provided normative resources to
those who opposed the modern revival of dictatorship. Denunciations of the
many forms of dictatorship, both of the Right and the Left, which emerged
over the course of the last century as modern manifestations of tyranny
mobilized repeatedly these resources.3
The equation of dictatorship and tyranny is not, however, unique to the
twentieth century. It appeared as well in a preceding historical period in the
shifting political context of the revolutionary upheavals of Europe and its
overseas colonies and the decline of the monarchical order.4 Claude Nicolet
rightly observes that “since the eighteenth century,” the term dictatorship “has
served to refer to despotisms or tyrannies—in other words, essentially powers which are far from having been regularly conferred, and instead had been
usurped through force or deceit.”5 The conceptual marriage of the dictator
and the tyrant coincided with the radical transformation of Western society
and politics in the age of the modern democratic revolutions, legal rationalization, the gradual inclusion of new groups into the terrain of formal politics,
and the successive attempts to institutionally resuscitate Roman dictatorship
by such figures as Cromwell, the Jacobins, and Napoleon.6
Nicolet’s narrative accurately captures the modern blending of the two
terms and correctly relocates it within the broader historical movement and
diffusion of republicanism.7 But his story is incomplete. It disregards a still
earlier moment in Western political history when the dictator began to look
dangerously like a tyrant. In the turbulent transitional period between the
Roman republic and the Principate, Sulla and Caesar, and their struggle for
supreme power gravely tested the institution of dictatorship.8 The ‘abuse’ of
this emergency institution, its exercise outside the limits delineated by the
established legal framework, its appropriation for the advancement of personal ambitions, and even its use against the republic itself, prompted a profound reconsideration of its nature, function, and value.
Two Greek historians of the early and high Imperial periods, Dionysius
of Halicarnassus (60 BC-after 7 BC) and Appian of Alexandria (95-165
AC) undertook such a radical reassessment.9 While most of the annalists
and ‘republican historians’ cherished the memory of the republic and its
institutions, among which dictatorship was held in the highest esteem, the
writings of the two Greek narrators followed a different path.10 Their histories suggest a fresh reconsideration of this emergency magistracy, which
they carried out by utilizing concepts and methods borrowed from the
classical Greek tradition.11 In their Greco-Roman synthesis dictatorship is
re-described as ‘temporary tyranny by consent’ and the tyrant as a ‘permanent
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
414
Political Theory
dictator.’ This historical and conceptual revisionism inaugurated a comparative study of the Roman institution of dictatorship and Greek theories of
tyranny with some crucial implications.
Dionysius and Appian’s Greek histories of Rome include a critical
re-examination of dictatorship insofar as they interrogate its very capacity
to preserve the constitutional order.12 Was the abuse of Roman dictatorship
accidental, the effect of moral decline, or the result of its own unruly nature?
As their works raise this question, it seems the two historians were not only
engaged in the rewriting of Roman history or in a conceptual revision of
classical concepts; they were also involved in a critical debate about the
institution of dictatorship as such. It is likely that Marcus Antonius’ law that
officially abolished dictatorship in 44 BC (the Lex Antonia de dictatura in
perpetuum tollenda) sparked this debate.13 It was rekindled when two
decades later, the senate and the people sought to revive the institution by
twice offering Augustus the Dictatorate, which he declined.14 More importantly, their histories challenged the republican regime as a whole, directly
implicating it in its own collapse.15 Unlike Livy and Sallust who ascribed
the fall of the republic to various external causes and their corrupt effects,16
Dionysius and Appian’s diagnoses suggested the preponderance of internal
reasons for the inherent instability, decline, and ultimately fall of the
Roman republic. Their histories, for the first time, radically reinterpreted
and explicitly questioned dictatorship. This venerated republican magistracy, the ultimate guardian of the Roman constitution, met its first critics.
Certainly, I am not suggesting to oppose Dionysius and Appian against
more renowned and influential historians of their times in the name of some
objective, ‘true’ factual attributes of the Roman institution of dictatorship.
Rather, I seek to revisit the incipient discursive encounter between tyranny
and dictatorship. In particular, I examine how the two concepts gradually
came to be associated with new meanings as they were increasingly fused.
I consider Dionysius and Appian’s unprecedented equation by focusing on
the historical narratives, conceptual translations, and theoretical arguments
that permitted the identification of the two terms. It is, however, the normative implications of this encounter that I find intriguing and which have
not hitherto been adequately appreciated politically or illuminated interpretatively. By identifying the Roman dictator with the Greek tyrant,
Dionysius and Appian introduced a new understanding of emergency powers, directly challenging inherited political views and philosophical beliefs.
As I see it, the two Greek historians inaugurated a radical conceptual transformation in the language of classical politics. With a different political
history invested with new meanings and values and brought inside the
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
Kalyvas / The Tyranny of Dictatorship
415
broader category of tyranny, dictatorship acquired a polyvalence and ambiguity that it originally lacked and which came to characterize the tyrannical depiction of the modern dictator.
Part one of this essay recreates the intellectual background that preceded
Dionysius and Appian’s synthesis in order to underscore the novelty of their
respective approaches. To associate the dictator and the tyrant was not the
most obvious thing to do at the time. Rather, the norm was to consider
tyranny a corrupted form of monarchy, a pathological outgrowth of royal
power perverted by unjust kings.17 Thus, the tyrant was primarily a bad king
(µοχθηρο′ςβασ l λεν′ ς / regis injusti).18 In this context, Dionysius and
Appian’s historical writings represent a decisive shift in the history of political concepts. Parts two and three discuss how Dionysius and Appian displaced the traditional interest in the relationship between the king and the
tyrant with a new curiosity about the tyrant and the dictator. The two Greek
historians found the tyrant and the dictator to be almost identical, thereby
blurring previous empirical, analytical, and normative distinctions between
them.19 This blurring entailed as well a serious reworking of the classical
theories of tyranny and a departure from more canonical definitions. Part
four explores some of the implications resulting from the equation of the
tyrant and the dictator, including the possibility that the downfall of the
Republic may have been the fatal result of particular constitutional choices
and institutional flaws. Crucially, Dionysius and Appian demythologized
the institution of dictatorship, dispelling its republican aura. From a more
general point of view, their approaches recast the relationship of Athenian
democracy and the Roman republic, indicating a key difference between
the two regimes that could potentially contribute to current debates on
executive emergency powers and constitutional dictatorship in liberal
democratic states.
The King, the Dictator, and the Tyrant
Livy offers a historically influential account of the origins of dictatorship.20 In 501 BC, a few years after the deposition and exile of the king
Tarquinius Superbus and in the face of external dangers caused by the
aggression of neighboring tribes, a dictator was appointed for the first time
by means of a lex dictatore creando.21 Although his appointment appears
to have been constitutional in accordance with certain established rules and
procedures, his public display generated a “great fear” among the plebeians.
Their sudden dread at the sheer sight of dictatorial power, a power beyond
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
416
Political Theory
appeal at the time and not subject to countervailing checks, rendered
them obedient while at the same time subduing their enemies and protecting the nascent republic.22
Aside from the element of fear and the powerful effects of docility that
both dictatorship and tyranny seemed to produce, Livy’s narrative does not
suggest other similarities. This absence is not surprising. From the first
moment of encounter of the two concepts in late antiquity as Rome
expanded eastwards around the time of the Punic wars and the tyrant was
brought into the republican language of politics and literature, we find a
clear conceptual division of labor.23 The tyrant occupied a fixed, welldefined position in the Roman imaginary, plainly and unambiguously distinguished from the dictator. They marked dissimilar forms of political rule,
carrying contrasting, even antithetical meanings. The dictator denoted a
legal and regular though extraordinary magistracy intended to protect the
public good in moments of crisis and danger; tyranny designated an unjust
and violent power, the destruction of the common interest, and the downfall of legality and freedom.
The many differences that set them apart were, in fact, too obvious and
dramatic to have been ignored. Dictatorship was a constitutional office
appointed legally through the cooperation of the higher republican authorities and according to “what the law commanded.”24 The tyrant acquired his
power extra-constitutionally, through force, deceit, and the violent overthrow of the established regime.25 Moreover, the dictator had a concrete
task, the elimination of threats during a crisis and a return to the status quo
ante bellum. Although the salvation and re-establishment of the constitution
was the strict commission of the dictator, no such authorization existed for
the tyrant whose acts were arbitrary and indeterminate, directed toward the
satisfaction of his selfish desires and private interests.26 The dictator’s
actions were generally considered to be inspired by a strong civic commitment to the public good, a real manifestation of the patriotic attachment of
the republican citizen. He was the guardian of the republican order; the
tyrant its usurper. In short, the dictator was a servant who defended what
the tyrant aspired to acquire and destroy.
The contrasts proliferate. Most significantly perhaps, the institution of
dictatorship was temporally bound.27 The dictator’s rule could never exceed
a six-month period and upon the successful completion of his assignment
he had to abdicate.28 Tyranny, however, entailed an attempt to seize control
of a government in order to hold it indefinitely. Whereas the dictator suspended the constitution or parts of it for a limited period, the tyrant did so
for an unspecified period, normalizing his rule and endeavoring to habituate
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
Kalyvas / The Tyranny of Dictatorship
417
the people to it.29 Dictatorship was exceptional and provisional; tyranny
“unnatural” but permanent.30 Because the dictator lacked the legislative
powers that the tyrant simply usurped he could not modify, alter, or abolish
the established constitutional structure but only suspend it. Thus, while the
dictator appealed to the exception to uphold the norm, the tyrant attempted
to normalize the exception. Finally, Roman dictatorship was not itself a form
of government, but rather an institutional component of a broader republican
regime. Tyranny by contrast was generally treated as a regime-type of its
own, albeit a perversion and a deviation of the just forms of political rule.
The ancient Romans knew these distinctions, which might have had
some bearing on their historical inquiries and on how they understood their
institutions. However, there were some telling similarities between dictatorship and tyranny that could not have escaped notice. For example, dictatorship and tyranny were both closely associated with regal rule and in
particular with its stronger personalistic and autocratic versions. In the writings of the Polybius and Cicero this affinity is reflected in the intimate and
privileged relationship both concepts enjoyed with kingship.31
There is here, however, a slight but indicative divergence between the
Roman philosopher and the Greek historian. Although Cicero, like Polybius,
considered tyranny as a perverted form of monarchy, he also thought that
dictatorship, a decisive higher authority with a plenitude of power to overcome the forces of dissolution, rescued the best monarchy had to offer, “for
safety prevails over caprice.”32 Cicero commended the survival of monarchical powers (especially those necessary for war or civil discord) in the
institution and practice of dictatorship.33 For him, dictatorship appeared as
a remnant of monarchy, a necessary but temporary retreat to royal powers,
and an advantageous return to the deposed form of personalistic rule.34 In
cases of emergency, the King’s regal authority was revived, so as to set
aside the limitations imposed by the collegiate arrangement, the mixed
character of the republic, and by the special curtailments of jurisdiction. For
Polybius, however, the monarchical derivation of tyranny primarily explained
the vicious excesses of the former. In his famous cyclical theory of regime
change, Polybius described how the absolute power of kingship necessarily
degenerates into tyranny, that is, into the ruler’s instrument for the limitless
pursuit of his lawless pleasures and passions.35 Although Cicero agreed
with Polybius’ views on the immanent threat of corruption, he also
acknowledged the best of monarchy. The ideal of kingship is realized, but,
paradoxically, only briefly and provisionally, that is, dictatorially. For
Polybius, however, tyranny represented the worst of monarchy, a natural
deviation from the right form and a necessary slip into lawlessness.
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
418
Political Theory
It would be wrong to underestimate the difference between dictatorship
and tyranny as it emerges out of the contrasting figures of the dictator as the
good, temporary king and the tyrant as an unjust, corrupted monarch.
However, even though Cicero’s understanding of dictatorship contains
positive elements of monarchy while Polybius’ concept of tyranny embodies
its negative aspects, both conceptualizations reveal a close affinity with regal
power, or what Dio Cassius described as “a love for monarchy” (ε′ρωτα
.
µοναρχιας).36 This affinity between dictatorship and kingship recalls earlier classical Greek explorations into the nature of tyranny, suggesting certain similarities between dictatorship and tyranny. One similarity is a
common claim to supreme power (κυ′ριος πα′ντων /majus imperium) once
held by a legitimate monarch.37 In this view, the supreme power over the life
and death of their subjects, a power without collegiality, characterize both
dictatorship and tyranny. This autocratic form of power also suggests
another similarity between the two concepts regarding their indeterminate
and tense relation with the established legal order and their alarming proximity to anomie.38 After all, the Romans drew a thin line separating the king
from the tyrant in relation to whether a king ruled by law or according to
his desires, and it was recognized in the force of corruption to transform
kings into tyrants.
It is not surprising, therefore, that the dreadful incidents of Sulla (82-79
BC) and Caesar (49 BC, 48-47 BC, 46-45 BC, 45-44 BC) would finally
draw attention to these similarities, inviting a serious reexamination of dictatorship. Dionysius seems to have been the first to undertake such a revision, and Appian the second.39 Dionysius, a contemporary of Livy, wrote
his history of Rome at the conclusion of a tumultuous, transitional period
between the late Republic, its fall, and the consolidation of imperial monarchy. His Roman Antiquities, consisting of 20 books, began to appear in 7
BC, approximately two decades after his permanent move to Rome, at a
moment when the problem of dictatorship was again a topical issue, acquiring a new historical and political salience perhaps through the ambiguous
legacy of Cicero’s late writings on Caesar and Antonius.40 Unlike most of
his fellow historians, Dionysius developed a distinct understanding of dictatorship, proposed a new history of its origin and evolution, and profoundly reassessed its involvement in the fall of the republic.
Appian closely followed and further developed Dionysius’ approach on
dictatorship although he completed his Roman History one century and a
half later, around 162 AD in a mature and relatively stable imperial order.
From the vantage point of a consolidated imperial monarchy, Appian
looked back at the instability of the republic and linked dictatorship to a
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
Kalyvas / The Tyranny of Dictatorship
419
series of disruptive and violent civic conflicts that brought about the collapse of the res publica. As an emergency magistracy, dictatorship played a
decisive role in the republic’s slow and painful descent into discord and disorder.41 Its direct interventions in the politics of social conflict enjoy a
prominent place in Appian’s depiction of the gradual dissolution and ultimate death of republican institutions. With Appian, dictatorship remained
where Dionysius had relegated it, fallen from its previously lofty constitutional position and irremediably tainted by its association with tyranny.
Dionysius and the Elective Tyranny of Dictatorship
Dionysius’ account of the historical origins of the first dictatorship differed sharply from and even at times contradicted Livy’s.42 Several examples illustrate this divergence. First, Dionysius located its birth three years
later than Livy, in 498 BC. More importantly, he underplayed the influence
of external factors in the creation of this emergency institution that were
central in Livy’s account. Dionysius’ narrative stressed almost exclusively
the central role of domestic politics.43 It depicted a fragile nascent republican order struggling for balance and stability. A highly polarized society,
fractured by the problem of the debts, shaken by popular unrest, and threatened by civic discord between the patricians and the plebeians, challenged
this quest for survival. In this immediate volatile post-monarchical context,
Dionysius firmly located the republican genesis of dictatorship at a critical,
foundational junction amidst fierce debates over the political identity of the
republic, the distribution of freedoms and protections of the different
orders, and the shape of its constitutive norms and rules.
Dionysius identifies as the main reason behind the establishment of dictatorship a law proposed by the consul Publius Valerius (Publicola) and ratified by the people. This law sparked a quarrel that further inflamed the
conflict between the two orders on the question of debts, endangering the
incipient republic.44 Publicola’s law strengthened considerably the position
of the plebeians by granting the right to appeal (ius provocationis) to Roman
citizens, proposing that no Roman should be punished without a trial. This
law made it illegal for a magistrate to put a citizen to death without a trial
before a popular court, that is, before one’s peers (provocation ad populum).45 The right to appeal was thus established as a protection of the plebeians against the political and social predominance of the patricians in the
republic.46 Defendants could now appeal the judgment of the consuls to the
people and its assemblies,47 an innovation both Livy and Cicero recognized
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
420
Political Theory
as “the unique defense of liberty.”48 Nevertheless, as Dionysius bluntly
reports, in order to “prevent the plebeians from creating any fresh disturbances,” the senate proposed the creation of a new superior magistracy
endowed “with authority over war and peace and every other matter, possessed of absolute power and subject to no accounting for either its counsels or its actions.”49
Dictatorship was therefore deliberately designed to stop the political
ambitions of the multitude and “to the end that the poor might offer no
opposition,” the senate “introduce[d] into the government a magistracy of
equal power with tyranny (ισοτν′ ραννον αρχη′ ν ), which should be superior to all the laws.”50 The dictator (δικτα′ τορας) was instituted against
Publicola’s legal right to appeal. The implication of the senate’s judgment
was, as Dionysius reports, “that while this law remained in force the poor
could not be compelled to obey the magistrates . . . whereas, when this law
had been repealed, all would be under the greatest necessity of obeying
orders.”51 With the dictator, as Livy himself recognized, “there was neither
appeal nor help anywhere.”52 The plebs subsequently ratified the senate’s
plan for this temporary magistracy. But as Dionysius argued, the nobility
deceived and misguided them to vote against their own interests, thereby
approving the abolition of the law that guarded their freedom.53 The new
decree was immediately put into effect. The senate deliberated and the first
dictator was appointed to restore order. After he “terrified the turbulent and
the seditious,” he took a census, made a yearly truce with Rome’s neighboring enemies, and resigned.54
Dionysius’ approach is not only more detailed than Livy’s but also more
sociologically sensitive and politically alert. He associated closely the creation of dictatorship with social struggles, the balance of power between the
contending classes, their strategic reasoning and sense of self-interest, and
in particular, with the political, legal, and social advancements of the poor
after the expulsion of the kings.55 Thus, in Dionysius’ narrative dictatorship
appears from its very beginning as an aristocratic political instrument aiming at quelling domestic turmoil and preserving the interests and authority
of the patricians.56
Dionysius redefined this new powerful magistracy of dictatorship “elec.
tive tyranny” (αι′ρετη′ τνραννις ), thus radically transforming its meaning
within the context of Roman political thought.57 The critical thrust of
Dionysius’ drastic historical revisionism becomes more palpable in light
of his undeniably pejorative views on tyranny. In his critical discussion of
Thucydides, for instance, he portrayed tyranny as a bad form of political
power that excludes the many from common life by depriving them of those
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
Kalyvas / The Tyranny of Dictatorship
421
things that are universally advantageous and useful.58 This synoptic disapproval resonates throughout Dionysius’ Roman history. Based on the
description of its genesis, dictatorship was more of a political weapon in
Rome’s ongoing civic struggles than a military magistracy aimed at external foes.59 The senate deliberately designed dictatorship as an instrument
for domestic emergencies. Its purpose was to spread fear and insecurity
among the disobedient masses, abolish legal protections and rights if
needed, suppress popular dissent, and protect the interest and privileges of
the patricians. This may explain why, as Theodor Mommsen observed,
“since the fall of monarchy, the suppression of dictatorship became in
Rome the objective of the party of liberty.”60
As a supreme device of repression, the result of “an aristocratic plot,”
institutionally engineered for situations of class warfare, dictatorship necessarily militarized political contestation.61 The fact that the first archaic name
for the dictator was magister populi underscores the primary function of a
military commander.62 Dictatorship not only criminalized political conflict
and militarized the city but also transformed the political adversary into a
hostis, a public enemy, against whom the dictator could legally apply in full
force the law of war.63 As Clinton Rossiter observes, “the resort to the dictatorship converted the Roman Republic and its complex constitution into the
simplest and most absolute of all governments—an armed camp governed
by an independent and irresponsible general.”64 All this would have sounded
familiar to Greek ears. Tyrants “know well that all who are subject to their
.
tyranny are their enemies (ε′χθροι ),” Xenophon’s “Hieron” laments, as they
live “in a perpetual state of war.”65 Tyranny was a friendless power, and the
militarization of the political was considered a defining attribute of tyrannical rule.66 Aristotle, in his historical and comparative investigations on the
nature of this form of boundless power, concurred: the tyrant is a war-maker,
a “πολεµοποιο′ς.”67 The tyrannical city was always under siege; and so it
was with Rome under the rule of a dictator.68
These similarities may have informed Dionysius’ sweeping redefinition
of dictatorship as “elective tyranny.” On the one hand, dictatorship was
tyrannical because it was absolute and unaccountable, entailed the discretionary use of the means of violence, the ability to breach the laws at will,
and threatened the life, liberties, and property of its subjects while seeking
to protect and advance partial class interests against the common good. On
the other hand, it was also elective. The people explicitly consented to
sacrifice temporarily their freedom when they ratified the senate’s proposal.
That they were fooled and manipulated, as Dionysius maintained, does not
alter the fact that in the end they sanctioned the new law, thus surrendering
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
422
Political Theory
.
.
to a “voluntary tyranny” (αν′θαιρετον τνραννιδα).69 With the Romans,
the tyrant became a constitutional choice in moments of crisis and tyranny
took the new form of arbitrary personal rule by consent.
Dionysius’ radical reappraisal not only challenged established views on
dictatorship, it also questioned classical definitions of tyranny. For instance,
from the well-known Greek designations of tyranny as a particular form of
rule over unwilling subjects, against the law, and in the service of the
private interests of the ruler, Dionysius retained the two last attributes,
illegality and partial interests, and reduced the significance of the first,
involuntary rule.70 As a consequence, the non-consensual foundations of
tyranny and its association with usurpation became less important in his use
of the term, given that he thought it possible to have a tyranny consented to
by the many as long as the ruler remained unaccountable and outside the
law, enjoying full powers over his subjects while seeking to advance
particular social interests. In this way, Dionysius distanced himself from
the classical meanings traceable at least to Herodotus’ story of the first
tyrant Gyges, according to which tyranny was an act of usurpation in violation of established norms and rules regulating the acquisition of power.71
Dionysius drew attention instead to the nature and quality of rule itself and
not to the method of its possession, thus departing from the view of tyranny
as a violation of the procedural law of succession. This reformulation of
tyranny anticipates the medieval distinction between tyranny ex defectu
tituli (with respect to the illegitimate and non-consensual acquisition of
power) and tyranny quoad exercitium (with respect to the way of exercising power).72
This subtraction of the principle of consent from the attributes of tyranny
was not fully innovative considering the Aristotelian category of “elective
tyranny” that was included in his typology of royalty.73 Aristotle distinguished among several types of kingship, dissimilar but still partaking in
the same regime form, allowing for a more complex, comparative approach.
Dionysius’ approach directly relies on one of Aristotle’s royal sub-types,
the obscure and almost unknown to us archaic, pre-democratic Greek institution of aesymne–tae, under which a military commander was elected and
granted additional powers to save the city from external dangers.74 After the
completion of the mission, the aesymne–tes abdicated. Aristotle considered
this ancient practice tyrannical because it was absolute in the manner of its
rule, notwithstanding its likely origin in popular support or through the
established legal forms and procedures. Such regimes “are of the nature of
tyrannies,” Aristotle writes, “because they are despotic, but of the nature of
kingships because they are elective and rule over willing subjects.”75 The
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
Kalyvas / The Tyranny of Dictatorship
423
aesymne–tes is thus a hybrid of tyranny and kingship, blending absolute,
personalistic power with consent in moments of exceptional danger.76
Pittacus, the ruler of Mitylene, for example, was officially an aesymne–tes
before he became the legendary tyrant and one of the seven sages.77
Dionysius’ appropriation of the Aristotelian category of “elective
tyranny” is crucial for his concluding narrative on Sulla, whose dictatorship he assessed as having one positive, if inadvertent effect: it finally
compelled the Romans to realize the true nature of this magistracy insofar
as it exposed the real face of dictatorship in terms of the tyrant within.78 So
cruel and harsh was Sulla’s dictatorship, Dionysius wrote, “that the
Romans perceived for the first time what they had all along been ignorant
of, that dictatorship is a tyranny.”79 Dionysius’ comment does not indict
Sulla for abusing the Roman magistracy and its extraordinary powers or
for violating its constitutional limitations, as Mommsen would later do in
his famous distinction between two types of dictatorship.80 Nor does
Dionysius inflect his notion of tyranny with such subjective moral characterizations as Sulla’s personal lust to power. Rather, Dionysius’ indictment
of Sulla is predicated on the emergency institution of dictatorship itself,
devised to tyrannize the republic, even if only temporarily and by consent.
In short, for Dionysius, Sulla was the tyrannical symptom of dictatorship,
not its cause.
Appian and the Temporary Tyranny of Dictatorship
This incipient but compelling critical redefinition of the republican
emergency magistracy was further explored and developed almost a
century and a half later in the writings of another Greek historian, Appian
of Alexandria.81 Although Appian’s approach is quite dissimilar to that of
Dionysius, it nonetheless shares with the latter a common understanding of
Roman dictatorship. Thus, their writings on dictatorship complement one
another and their shared vision of the tyranny of dictatorship sets their work
apart from the other historians of their time. In fact, Appian’s narrative confirms Dionysius’ interpretation of the tyrannical nature of dictatorship.
Dionysius’ thorough examination of the first Roman dictator is matched
only by Appian’s equally meticulous discussion of Sulla, one of the last to
ascend to absolute power.82
In his history of the Roman republic, Appian shows how during the
civil wars Sulla resorted to the institution of dictatorship by walking a thin
line between legality and anomie. After invading Rome in 82 BC and taking
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
424
Political Theory
advantage of the death of the two consuls during the civil war, Sulla ‘convinced’ the senate to appoint an interrex. He subsequently ‘persuaded’ the
interrex not to organize and supervise the elections for the new consuls
but instead to appoint him dictator for an indefinite period and with legislative powers.83 The interrex followed Sulla’s ‘suggestion’ and proposed a
new law which was approved by a weakened and demoralized centuriate
assembly thus formally appointing Sulla dictator (βασιλεν′ ων δικτα′τωρ),
and establishing, in effect, a dictatorship by popular election.84 As if history
were repeating itself within just a few centuries, “the Romans welcomed this
treachery of an election as an appearance and pretence of freedom and
appointed Sulla as tyrant with absolute power (τν′ραννον αντοκρα′τορα) for
as long as he wished.”85 Like the closing of a circle, the republic’s beginnings
met the republic’s end: in “voluntary servitude.”86
Like Dionysius, Appian redefined Sulla’s dictatorship as a tyrannical
form of rule.87 What exemplified Sulla’s tyranny was not external, solely
because of his skillful manipulation of his appointment procedure. Nor was
the tyrannical character of his rule due simply to the crimes he committed
and the visceral terror he unleashed. Likewise, Sulla’s dictatorship could
not be explained by his legislative constituent powers (dictator legibus
scribendis et rei publicae constituendae) which gave him unlimited powers
to make laws and amend the constitution.88 Rather, the tyrannical nature of
Sulla’s rule was inscribed in the very logic of his dictatorial position as
such. As Appian claimed, following on Dionysius’ steps, dictatorship is in
itself a form of tyranny and thus “even in the past the dictator’s power had
been tyrannical.”89 Dictatorship had always been a tyrannical power, irrespective of Sulla’s procedural irregularities and innovations.
If Appian was right, however, there would be no difference between
Sulla and all the previous dictators, all of whom would look like tyrants.
Obviously this cannot be the case since Appian is well aware of the historically distinct character of Sulla’s dictatorship. It was the violation of the
temporary limits of dictatorship that accounts for Sulla’s historical uniqueness. By removing the time limits, Sulla unleashed the tyrant residing
within the emergency magistracy, and its dreadful powers. While in the past
.
the tyranny of dictatorship “was limited to short periods” (ο′λι γω χρο′νω
δ’ο′ριζοµε′νη), with Sulla it became “indeterminate” (α′ ο′ριστος).90 Here,
Appian’s approach recalls Plutarch’s, insofar as it was the latter who a
century earlier had defined Caesar’s dictatorship as tyrannical precisely
because it was perpetual and who also identified Sulla as “nothing else than
always a tyrant.”91 But Plutarch did not qualify his definition. It was in
Appian’s histories, as Mario Turchetti correctly notes, that “dictatorship
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
Kalyvas / The Tyranny of Dictatorship
425
was originally a tyrannical power, even if it was short-term limited. But for
the first time, granted without limits, it became a perfect tyranny.”92
Appian’s distinction between dictatorship and tyranny derives from the
fact that the first is a limited form of the latter. The dictator is a temporary
tyrant, whose tyranny is short-lived, regulated, and bounded. Thus, the difference between Sulla and previous dictators was that the latter were limited.
In Appian’s narrative, the dictator resembles an interim tyrant, restrained and
.
contained, designed to exercise “tyrannical power” (τνραννικη′ µα′ρχη′ν)
only in brief moments of grave emergencies not exceeding the six months of
unlimited power, not subject to appeal and to countervailing checks, when
the law undoes the temporal chains that bind him.93 As a slumbering tyrant,
he lies dormant in normal times, waking up only temporarily during a crisis
to wear his dictatorial mantle. By being appointed for an indefinite period,
Sulla seems to have fulfilled the tyrannical logic of dictatorship. From a limited tyranny, periodic and segmented,94 Sulla moved to a form of tyranny that
.
was, for Appian, pure and absolute (εντελη′ ς τνραννι ς).95
Appian’s argument is subtle but decisive. The constitutional principle of
time-limits does not indicate an essential difference between these two
forms of power but rather an internal differentiation of degree between a
limited and an unlimited tyranny. The temporary suspension of the law
amounts to a provisional abolition that subordinates it to the arbitrary rule
of human will. Dictatorship and tyranny partake in the same species of
power: supreme, discretionary, arbitrary, personal, and violent. Two variations on a common theme, the dictator is a temporary tyrant and the tyrant
a permanent dictator. Sulla’s magistracy is thus at once both typical and
unique in that it realized the genuinely tyrannical nature of dictatorship by
ridding it of temporal limits. By redefining dictatorship as a temporary
tyranny and tyranny as a permanent dictatorship, Appian registered the
deep affinities between the two concepts, thereby reaffirming Dionysius’
view of dictatorship as tyrannical by nature.96
To be sure, Appian’s account is not identical to Dionysius’. Their intentions and preoccupations were not similar as the historical, biographical,
cultural, and political contexts of their respective histories diverged sharply.
Many differences separate the two Greek historians. Even on the issue of
dictatorship, there are some discrepancies in tone and orientation. Appian
appears ambivalent toward the tyrannical effects of dictatorship as in one
occasion he displayed a kind of appreciation for how in the past dictatorship had served Rome. He thus acknowledged that this exceptional magistracy “had been useful in former times.”97 However, it is unclear why he
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
426
Political Theory
thought so and how this relates to his more systematic, informed observations on dictatorship and its role in the demise of the republic, where there
is no mention of any positive advantage. Might it be that he held a pragmatic view according to which the dictator as a short-term tyrant could still
be useful in certain occasions? Here, the interpretative difficulty relates to
whether Appian, while stressing the usefulness of dictatorship, recognized
the necessity of tyranny for moments of crisis. This puzzle pertains to the
consistency and clarity of Appian’s account and how this brief commentary
could fit into his broader narrative. But the fact remains that even in this
case Appian upheld his description of dictatorship as an absolute power,
thus concurring not only with his explicit analysis of this institution as
tyrannical and unlimited but also with Dionysius’ version of unaccountability. When it comes to their descriptive understanding of the nature of
dictatorship the similarities between the two Greek historians are more
pronounced than any of the differences that may set them apart.
Dictatorship and the Legalization of Tyranny
Dionysius and Appian’s strikingly original contribution is to have
noticed a tyrannical presence in the republican institution of dictatorship.
By doing so, the two Greek historians inaugurated a powerful revision of
one of ancient republicanism’s more esteemed institutions and a conceptual
transformation with some critical ramifications. The first and most significant is the heterodox redefinition of dictatorship, now understood as a ‘temporary tyranny by consent.’ This redefinition points at a novel theory of the
Roman magistracy as ‘legalized tyranny.’ Dictatorship represents the legalization of tyranny wherein the tyrant is legally summoned by a higher
instance of the republican constitution in moments of danger to protect the
existing order. As Cicero himself finally came to recognize (but only in the
particular case of Sulla thus missing the general significance of his own
observation), while “in other cities, when tyrants are established all laws
are extinguished and destroyed, in the republic it is by law that a tyrant
was established.”98 As legalized and proceduralized tyranny, dictatorship
embodies the desire to tame and control the tyrant. There is a yearning to
use his supreme powers for one’s own advantage, for love of country. To
command the tyrant and unleash him with full discretion against enemies
and for one’s own collective survival is what makes dictatorship an attractive option. ‘Legal tyranny’ promises that absolute power outside the law
can be domesticated without losing any of its repressive effects.
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
Kalyvas / The Tyranny of Dictatorship
427
A second implication is that this atypical view of dictatorship as legal
tyranny challenges the historiography of Dionysius and Appian’s times,
unsettles received opinions about this exceptional emergency office, and
implicates it in the fall of the Roman republic. For instance, the two Greek
historians depart significantly from Livy’s more canonical narrative of dictatorship and accountability according to which a dictator could be charged
with crimes committed after laying down his office. For the Roman historian, although the right to appeal was suspended during the dictator’s actual
tenure of office, it could be reactivated following his resignation, thus
allowing for his impeachment as a private person. Livy mentioned only one
such case where a dictator, Gaius Manius, and his master of horse were
brought to trial after holding office in 314 BC.99 Unfortunately, it is impossible to know how Dionysius and Appian described or interpreted this event
because the relevant books of their histories that might have mentioned it
have not survived.100 Because the historical sources are very scanty and
those that survive vary on this issue there is no conclusive evidence to
resolve their differing versions between Dionysius and Appian on the one
hand and Livy on the other, the problem of the accountability of dictatorship remains undecided and controversial.101 Andrew Lintott, who is more
inclined to side with Livy on this matter, recognizes that “how absolute the
power of the dictator was, seems to have been an issue which was determined not by statute or by any clear rule, but by casuistry, and it remained
debatable at the time when the annalist tradition was being developed in the
last two centuries of the Republic. As with many uncertain constitutional
issues, the different positions that could be taken reflected either an aristocratic, authoritarian ideology or one that was popular and libertarian.”102
Here, however, the question is not to choose between Livy on the one
hand and Dionysius and Appian on the other, in a futile search for historical objectivity, but rather to underscore the originality of two less known,
underestimated reinterpretations of dictatorship that stand out as the only
surviving accounts that share a similar tyrannical depiction of this Roman
extraordinary institution, and which have customarily been disregarded in
favor of Livy’s single reference. Once these two dissenting interpretations
are taken seriously, not only do we witness in detail the ancient formation
of what Melvin Richter has called “family concepts,” but we also gain a
privileged access to an unusually audacious revision of the classical
republican regime-type.103
Dionysius and Appian’s Greco-Roman synthesis altered the normative
connotations associated with classical ideal of dictatorship. It demystifies
the republican portrayal of dictatorship and exposes the monster lurking
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
428
Political Theory
behind the hero, the wolf inside the soldier, the anomie inhibiting the law.
The towering reputation dictatorship enjoyed with its martial aura of nobility, an ethical embodiment of civic virtue and patriotism, are now all cast
aside as institutional and oratory ornaments to reveal that dictatorship is
another name for tyranny. As a consequence their histories disclosed a
tyrannical kernel hidden inside the institutional fabric of republican
government.
Furthermore, an additional ramification is that both Dionysius and
Appian’s views question much later attempts, such as those of Mommsen
and Carl Schmitt, to distinguish between two different dictatorships: an
older, ancient dictatorship and its irregular, radical reinvention by Sulla and
Caesar.104 Against this influential interpretation of two types of dictatorship,
the one commissarial and the other constituent, the two Greek historians
point to the historical continuity and institutional consistency of Roman
dictatorship. For instance, in their historical revisions of Roman history,
Sulla’s dictatorial tyranny loses all of its exceptional or innovative character. It is neither an unfortunate anomaly nor an erratic occurrence. His dictatorship does not signify a break in the history of the institution. Instead,
it is regarded as the repressed but permanent, endemic tyrannical possibility of dictatorial powers. Tyranny, therefore, is seen as an integral part of
dictatorship. They may differ from a formal point of view but they are similar in substance. In fact, if the two Greek historians did not consider Sulla’s
rule accidental or ground-breaking, it is only because they situated its
tyrannical deeds within the very structure and logic of this supreme emergency magistracy that offers itself to abuse.105
Here, one cannot help but notice the tragic irony, even poetic justice, of
Dionysius and Appian’s histories. Although the Romans took pride in overthrowing the monarchy, elevating the removal of Tarquinius to a republican
foundational myth, to an anti-tyrannical instituting act, they were ultimately
unable to rid themselves of the (bad) king.106 And along with praising themselves for their devotion to the law and their patriotic respect for tradition
and custom, the Romans opened up a permanent gap, an internal fissure in
the legal edifice of their republic. To save the city, the constitution created
this void, this empty space of the law, the space of a-nomia, where the dictator comes to encounter the tyrant in their common ambition to fill it up
with the power once owed by the kings. It is ironic that despite the Romans’
renowned hatred of kings (odium regni), the expulsion of Tarquinius, and
the collegiality of the consuls, the tyrant was never really barred from the
city but rather remained harbored within the republican institution of dictatorship.107 By retaining the kingly powers, the Romans ‘inadvertently’
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
Kalyvas / The Tyranny of Dictatorship
429
preserved as well their tyrannical potential and failed to fully break away
from their monarchical past.108
In fact, kingship, whose abolition was predicated on the dangers it posed
to liberty, was preserved by the republic in the ‘minimal’ form of dictatorship with the utmost task of defending the city in its most vulnerable
moments.109 In the Roman republic, the enemy of freedom was elevated as
its defender. And what was meant to be used against internal and external
enemies was turned ultimately against the Roman constitution itself, which
thus fell victim to its own dangerous creation. Plotting to strengthen executive power beyond law, the constitution ended up caught in its own trap,
undermining the freedoms that had sustained its very existence and identity.
By importing the tyrant into their republic after the expulsion of the kings
under the guise of extraordinary emergency powers, the ancient Romans
made an ill-fated choice that eventually contributed to the loss of their liberty. To lose their libertas, what the citizens feared and hated the most,
finally became a reality. With Sulla and Caesar the dictator is finally
exposed: he is the tyrant within a free city, a Trojan horse situated at the
heart of the Roman constitution. Thus, Tarquinius might have been banished but his abusive, tyrannical powers survived in the new emergency
magistracy and returned with a vengeance to play an active part in the conflicts that brought the republic to an end.
Many centuries later, this reinterpretation of dictatorship would reverberate in modern political thought in a radically altered historical context. With
the return of dictatorship and its dissemination through republican doctrines
of politics, the moderns gradually rediscovered its tyrannical nature. From
this rich and fascinating period, one telling example stands out. It is in
Thomas Jefferson’s writings that Dionysius and Appian’s analysis is fully
resuscitated and brought to its ultimate conclusion. In a section of his Notes
on Virginia regarding the defects of the Virginia State constitution he
denounced two proposals made in 1776 and 1781 “to create a dictator,
invested with every power legislative, executive, and judiciary, civil and military, of life and of death, over our persons and over our properties.”110
Jefferson used his disagreement with these two proposals as an occasion
not only to deplore dictatorship but, more tellingly, to attack tyranny.
Commenting on the Romans, he keenly reproached their republican constitution because it “allowed a temporary tyrant to be erected, under the name
of a Dictator; and that temporary tyrant, after a few examples, became
perpetual.”111 Temporality is the crucial feature, the one that blends the
tyrant and the dictator together. More forthright than Dionysus and Appian,
Jefferson explicitly recognized the extent of the destructive potential of
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
430
Political Theory
tyrannical rule which he did not think could be tamed and regulated in the
form of dictatorship. The temporal constraints would not last forever to perpetually bind this extraordinary device of domination and to compel it to
act for the preservation of the republic. Once included in the constitutional
arrangement of dictatorship, tyranny becomes a permanent, endemic threat
to that same arrangement. This threat arises because the tyrant cannot be
moderated by or accommodated within an institutional mechanism and an
overarching constitutional system of mixed powers. Instead, he will throw
the mixed constitution out of balance. The tyrant, who inhibits the dictator,
will seek to permanently unbind himself from the legal restrictions and use
his exceptional power to subvert constitutional constraints.
The ancient Greeks noticed early on this unruly drive of tyranny and registered it in classical political philosophy. Tyranny is excessive, “unlimited”
.
(α′ο′ριστος τνραννι ς), striving voraciously for absolute sovereignty (απα′ντων
112
κν′ριο′ς). It amounts, for Herodotus, to hubris, as the tyrant’s desires
overreach, never to be satisfied.113 Plato’s description of the excess of
tyranny remains telling as well. The tyrannical life, Gorgias commends, is
“a life of insatiable licentiousness,” that same life which Socrates deplored
as “always greedy, suffering from unfulfilled desires.”114 Tyranny is pure
immoderation caught in the vicious circle of power for the sake of power.
These classical depictions of tyrannical power question directly the capacity of legal stipulations regulating dictatorship ever to succeed in permanently containing and neutralizing the tyrant within the dictator.
In addition, Jefferson did not shy away from drawing a second conclusion from the tyrannical character of dictatorship. The Roman constitution
was self-defeating for the simple reason that although the dictatorship was
“proved fatal” to the republic, it was also indispensable to it.115 Rome’s
republican constitution was trapped in a deadly paradox: its factional politics, an “unfeeling aristocracy,” and a “ferocious” and impoverished people
made its survival in moments of internal dissension dependent on a tyrant
who would save the republic only to destroy it himself at a later time.116
Herein lays the Jeffersonian paradox: by its very nature the Roman
republic could not survive emergencies without the assistance of tyranny,
the very form of political rule that most endangered its very existence.
Consequently, the instrument that was vital for the survival of the republic
was simultaneously the tool of its downfall. As a “remedy,” dictatorship is
worse than the malady, yet it is essential.117 Hence the paradoxical situation
of an institution that is both essential to the ancient republic’s survival as
well as the cause of its ultimate demise. The Jeffersonian paradox directly
questions the ideal of the republican constitution and in particular its claim
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
Kalyvas / The Tyranny of Dictatorship
431
of stability and permanence generated and sustained by an institutional
equilibrium.118 It is not a coincidence that Jefferson was particularly severe
in his judgment of Roman republicanism: its structural defects outdo any
possible benefits and therefore it is not a model to emulate.119
Aside the issue of historical reception, there is a much broader implication. If Dionysius and Appian are right and dictatorship is indeed another
name for tyrannical rule, a significant historical and political difference
between the Athenian democracy and the Roman republic comes to the
fore. The fusion of the dictator and the tyrant in these interpretations provides a unique point of entry to reconsider the broader question of the relationship between the two ancient regimes and points to the likely relevance
of this account of the Roman experience with dictatorship to current
debates on emergency powers and constitutional regimes of exception in
liberal democracies.120 Here I will comment briefly only on one aspect of
this relationship in need of further elaboration elsewhere.
Although democratic Athens and republican Rome are often identified as
the two archetypical free regimes of antiquity, they diverged on the crucial
issues of the role of absolute, autocratic power within their respective political and legal frameworks. Whereas democratic Athens banned the tyrannical form of power in the name of freedom, the Roman republic legalized it
in the name of liberty. What was excluded from the constitutional arrangement of Athens was fully included in the mixed regime of Rome. From the
writings of Dionysius and Appian it seems as though the Roman constitution
welcomed unwittingly the tyrant to cross over the line separating the state of
nature (and war) and the city. Dictatorship is the result of this republican
invitation. By contrast, ancient democracy was the only regime we know of
that legislated explicitly against the tyrant, designating him a “public
enemy” (πολε′µιος) and calling for his assassination.121 Not only was the
tyrant outlawed, but as has been correctly noted, “In Athens there was no
provision in the constitution for dealing with emergencies such as the
Roman tumultus or the modern martial law.”122 Considering this difference
from the perspective of Dionysius and Appian’s histories, it seems that
while in democratic Athens the tyrant was an enemy to be resisted, in
republican Rome he was a friend to rely on. These are two very different
attitudes toward tyrannical power.
This distinction is important because it suggests that while historically
republics could accommodate themselves to the tyranny of dictatorship,
democracies could not. This also denotes two different attitudes toward
power, its scope and directionality, and its relationship to the law. From
the perspective of democratic, anti-tyrannical legislation the figure of the
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
432
Political Theory
temporary tyrant must have looked not only paradoxical, but deeply unreasonable and dangerous. How is it possible that in moments of crisis a free city
appeals to a tyrant for its survival as the only means to restore order? Can the
tyrant whom Cicero described, following Plato, as “the most monstrous of the
wild beasts in the cruelty of his nature . . . who desires no bond of shared law,
no partnership in human life with his fellow citizens” be constitutionally
bound as to safeguard the republic?123 Can a tyrant ever be trusted? Can he
defend liberty? From a democratic standpoint, the republican theory of dictatorship now viewed through the lens of Dionysius and Appian asks of citizens that they entrust provisionally their freedoms, life, and property to a
power they most fear and find insufferable, “since no free man willingly
endures such a rule.”124 It demands to surrender the defense of the city to its
enemy and it undoes the civic vow of democratic citizenship.
Finally, and more crucially, Dionysius and Appian help us grapple with
the politically pressing issue of whether it is wise for citizens of constitutional democracies to grant extraordinary emergency powers for security
reasons (even if temporally limited and constitutionally defined) to an office
which stands in an ambiguous relation to the rule of law.125 Especially in a
time when democratic republics are willingly or tacitly opting to suspend
some of their constitutional liberties for purportedly greater security,
Dionysius and Appian’s radical reinterpretation of Roman dictatorship
appears astonishingly salient. Of course, one should not expect to find in
their ancient histories precise answers and definitive solutions to today’s
problems and dilemmas regarding constitutional dictatorship and the threat
of terrorism. But precisely because they recognized that Roman dictatorship
can enjoy a semblance of democratic legitimacy and accommodate itself
with electoral consent, their investigation into the origins and effects of this
ancient exceptional institution could advance a more informed, critical, and
politically incisive understanding of emergency regimes in liberal democratic states. The enduring legacy of the two Greek historians is to have reformulated the question of whether the citizens or their elected representatives
in exceptional moments of crisis should have recourse to a dictator in terms
of the more fundamental issue about the relative advantages of tyranny and
its unpredictable, counter-productive consequences.
Notes
1. Fossey John Cobb Hearnshaw, “Democracy or Dictatorships?” The Contemporary
Review, 286 (1934), p. 432. Also see, Gaetano Mosca, The Ruling Class, Hannah D. Kahn
(trans.), New York: McGrawn-Hill Book Company, 1939, pp. 355, 486; Giovanni Sartori, The
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
Kalyvas / The Tyranny of Dictatorship
433
Theory of Democracy Revised, Vol. I, Chatham, New Jersey: Chatham House Publishers,
1987, p. 204.
2. Norberto Bobbio, Democracy and Dictatorship, Peter Kennedy (trans.), Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press, 1989, p. 166.
3. For example, see E. E. Kettlet, The Story of Dictatorship. From the Earliest Times till
Today, London: Ivor Nicholson and Watson, 1937; Alfred Cobban, Dictatorship: Its History
and Theory, New York: Haskell House Publishers, 1939; Oscar Jászi and John D. Lewis,
Against the Tyrant: The Tradition and Theory of Tyrannicide, Illinois: The Free Press, 1957;
Maurice Latey, Patterns of Tyranny, New York: Atheneum, 1969; Maurice Latey, Tyranny: A
Study in the Abuse of Power, London: Macmillan, 1969; Raymond Aron, De la dictature,
Paris: René Julliard, 1961; Raymond Aron, Machiavel et les tyrannies modernes, Paris: Éditions de Fallois, 1993; Brian Loveman, The Constitution of Tyranny: Regimes of Exception in
Latin America, University of Pittsburgh, 1993; Alan Axelrod and Charles Phillips, Dictators
and Tyrants: Absolute Rulers and Would-Be Rulers in World History; Facts on File, 1995; Daniel
Chirot, Modern Tyrants: The Power and Prevalence of Evil in Our Age, New Jersey: Princeton
University Press, 1996; Simon Tormey, Making Sense to Tyranny: Interpretations of
Totalitarianism, Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1995; Roger Boesche, Theories of
Tyranny From Plato to Arendt, University Park, Pennsylvania: The Pennsylvania State
University Press, 1996; For three noticeable exceptions, see Élie Halévy, The Era of
Tyrannies: Essays on Socialism and War, New York: New York University Press, 1966, p. 308;
Hannah Arendt, The Origins of Totalitarianism, New York: A Harvest Book, 1975, p. 6;
Andrew Arato, “Good-bye to Dictatorship?” Social Research, 67:4 (2000), pp. 926, 937. Franz
Neumann adopts a different view in his “Notes on the Theory of Dictatorship.” See Franz
Neumann, The Democratic and the Authoritarian State: Essays in Political and Legal Theory,
Herbert Marcuse (ed.), New York: The Free Press, 1957, pp. 233-256. For an illuminating discussion of dictatorship and tyranny in the twentieth century, see Melvin Richter, “A Family of
Political Concepts: Tyranny, Despotism, Bonapartism, Caesarism, Dictatorship, 1750-1917,”
European Journal of Political Theory, 4:3 (2005), pp. 242-243.
4. Chantal Millon-Delson, “Dictature et despotisme, chez les Anciens et chez les
Modernes,” Revue Française D’Histoire des Idées Politiques, 6 (1997), pp. 245-251.
5. Claude Nicolet, “Dictatorship in Rome,” Peter Baehr and Melvin Richter (eds.),
Dictatorship in History and Theory. Bonapartism, Caesarism, and Totalitarianism, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2004, p. 263.
6. It may well be that Cromwell was the first modern to be considered by many of his
contemporaries to be both a tyrant and a dictator. Pierre Jeannin, “Cromwell: une dictature
introuvable?” Maurice Duverger, Dictatures et Légitimité, Paris: PUF, 1982, pp. 143-158;
R. Zaller, “The Figure of the Tyrant in English Revolutionary Thought,” Journal of the History
of Political Ideas, 54 (1993), pp. 585–610.
7. Claude Nicolet, L’idée républicaine en france (1789-1924), Paris: Gallimard, 1994,
p. 101-105.
8. François Hinard, “De la dictature à la tyrannie. Réflexions sur la dictature de Sylla,”
François Hinard (ed.), Dictatures, Actes de la Table ronde de Paris, 27-28 février 1984, Paris:
De Boccard, 1988, pp. 87-96.
9. For the Greek historians of the Roman empire, see G. W. Bowersock, Augustus and
the Greek World, Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1965; G. W. Bowersock, “Historical Problems
in Late Republican and Augustan Classicism,” T. Gelzer, F. W. Bowersock (eds.), Le classicisme à Rome aux I siècle avant et apres J.-C., Geneva: Fondation Hardt, 1978, pp. 65-72; Bettie
Forte, Rome and the Romans as the Greeks Saw Them, Rome: American Academy in Rome,
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
434
Political Theory
1972; E. L. Bowie, “The Greeks and their Past in the Second Sophistic,” Studies in Ancient
Society, M. I. Finley (ed.), London: Routledge and K. Paul, 1974, pp. 166-209; Hugh J.
Mason, Greek Terms for Roman Institutions, Toronto: American Studies in Papyrology, 1974;
André Hurst, “Un critique grec dans la Rome d’Auguste: Denys d’Halicarnasse,” ANRW II.
30.1, 1982, pp. 839-865; Claude Nicolet (ed.), Demokratia et Arisokratia. A propos de Caius
Gracchus: mots grecs et réalites romaines, Paris: Publications de la Sorbonne, 1983; Emilio
Gabba, “The Historians and Augustus,” Fergus Millar and Erich Segal (eds.), Caesar
Augustus: Seven Aspects, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984, pp. 61-88; Erich S. Gruen, The
Hellenistic World and the Coming of Rome, Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984,
pp. 316-356; Robert Syme, “Greeks Invading the Roman Government,” Roman Papers, 4,
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988, pp. 1-20; Claude Nicolet, “Dictateurs Romains,
stratégoi autokratores et généraux carthaginois,” Dictatures, pp. 27-47; I. S. Moxon, J. D.
Smart, and A. J. Woodman (eds.), Past Perspectives. Studies in Greek and Roman Historical
Writings, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986; George A. Kennedy (ed.), The
Cambridge History of Literary Criticism. Vol. I: Classical Criticism, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1989; Kurt A. Raaflaub and Mark Toher (eds.), Between Republic and
Empire: Interpretations of Augustus and His Principate, Berkeley: University of California
Press, 1990; Michael Grant, Greek and Roman Historians: Information and Misinformation,
London: Routledge, 1995; Paul Cartledge, Peter Garnsey, Erich Gruen (eds.), Hellenistic
Constructs: Essays in Culture, History, and Historiography, Berkeley: University of
California Press, 1996; Simon Swain, Hellenism and Empire: Language, Classicism, and
Power in the Greek World, AD 50-250, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996; David S. Potter,
Literary Texts and the Roman Historian, London: Routledge 1999; Fergus Millar, The Roman
Republic in Political Thought, Hanover and London: The University Press of New England,
2002, pp. 37-49; Timothy E. Duff, The Greek and Roman Historians, London: Bristol
Classical Press, 2003.
10. T. J. Cornell, “The formation of the historical tradition of early Rome,” Past Perspectives.
Studies in Greek and Roman Historical Writings, pp. 74, 80-81; Emilio Gabba, Dionysius and
the History of Archaic Rome, Berkeley: University of California Press, 1991, pp. 10-11, 21-22,
87-96, 152; Harvey C. Mansfield, Taming the Prince. The Ambivalence of Modern Executive
Power, Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1989, pp. 84-85; Gregory S. Bucher,
“The Origins, Program, and Composition of Appian’s Roman History,” Transactions of the
American Philological Association, 130 (2000), pp. 411-458; Duff, The Greek and Roman
Historians, p. 118.
11. Nicolet, “Dictateurs Romains, stratégoi autokratores et généraux carthaginois,” pp. 35-36,
38; Schultze, “Dionysius of Halicarnassus and his audience,” p. 128; Gabba, Dionysius and
the History of Archaic Rome, pp. 23-59; Matthew Fox, “History and Rhetoric in Dionysius of
Halicarnassus,” The Journal of Roman Studies, 83 (1993), p. 42; Alain M. Gowing, The
Triumviral Narratives of Appian and Cassius Dio, Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan
Press, 1992, pp. 283-287; Swain, Hellenism and Empire, pp. 253, 414-421; Millar, The Roman
Republic in Political Thought, pp. 38-39; Mario Turchetti, Tyrannie et Tyrannicide de
l’Antiquité à nos jours, Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 2001, pp. 162-164.
12. Dionysius of Halicarnassus, Roman Antiquities, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
Press, 1971, Book V: 70-77, pp. 211-237; Appian, Roman History: The Civil Wars, Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2002, Book I: 98-115, pp. 181-215.
13. Cicero, “Philippic I,” Philippics, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2001,
1, p. 23; Cicero, “Philippic II,” Philippics, 36, p. 155; Appian, The Civil Wars, Book III:25,
p. 565; Dio Cassius, Roman History, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2001.
Book 54:51, p. 401, Book 54:2, pp. 283-285.
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
Kalyvas / The Tyranny of Dictatorship
435
14. Res Gestae Divi Augusti, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2002, 5, p. 353;
Theodor Mommsen, Le droit public romain, Paris: Thorin et fils, Éditeurs, Vol. IV, 1894,
pp. 428-429, 436-438; Ronald Syme, The Roman Revolution, Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2002, pp. 53-54; Cobban, Dictatorship. Its History and Theory, p. 331; Arthur Kaplan,
Dictatorships and “Ultimate” Degrees in the Early Roman Republic 501-201 BC, New York:
Revisionist Press, 1977, pp. 6, 165.
15. Clemence Schultze, “Dionysius of Halicarnassus and his audience,” Past Perspectives.
Studies in Greek and Roman Historical Writings, pp. 131-134; Bucher, “The Origins,
Program, and Composition of Appian’s Roman History,” pp. 431, 433-437, 441.
16. For example, see Sallust, The Conspiracy of Catiline, New York and London: Penguin
Books, 1963, Book I: 10-12, p. 181-183; Livy, History of Rome, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press, 1998, Book I: Preface, pp. 3-9; Gabba, Dionysius and the History of Archaic
Rome, pp. 211-213.
17. Polybius, The Histories, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, Book VI: 7-8,
pp. 283-285; Cicero, De Re Publica, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, Book I: 33,
42, pp. 77, 97-99; Book II: 26-29, 32, pp. 150, 167-169. Also, see Roger Dunkle, “The
Rhetorical Tyrant in Roman Historiography: Sallust, Livy, Tacitus,” Classical World, 65
(1971), pp. 12-20; Alain Michel, La philosophie politique a Rome d’Auguste a Marc Aurèle,
Paris: Armand Colin, 1969, pp. 22-27.
18. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1999,
Book VIII: 10, p. 491; Cicero, De Re Publica, II: 27, p. 159; Melvin Richter, “A Family of
Political Concepts: Tyranny, Despotism, Bonapartism, Caesarism, Dictatorship, 1750-1917,”
p. 224.
19. For the merging of the Roman king and the Greek tyrant, see Roger Dunkle, “The
Greek Tyrant and Roman Political Invective of the Late republic,” Transactions and
Proceedings of the American Philological Association, 98 (1967), pp. 151-171.
20. Livy, History of Rome, Book II: 18, pp. 275-277; Cicero, De Re Publica, Book II: 56,
p. 69-71. More generally, see D. Cohen, “The Origin of Roman Dictatorship,” Mnemosyne,
4:10 (1957), pp. 300-318.
21. Livy, History of Rome, Book II: 18, pp. 275-277. Also see, Clifton Walker Keyes, “The
Constitutional Position of the Roman Dictatorship,” Studies in Philology, 14 (1917), pp. 298305; Mommsen, Le droit public romain, Paris: Thorin et fils, Éditeurs, Vol. III, 1893, p. 163;
Andrew Lintott, The Constitution of the Roman Republic, Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1999, pp. 109-113.
22. Livy, History of Rome, Book II: 18, pp. 277. A reaction mentioned by Cicero as well.
Cicero, De Re Publica, Book I: 60, p. 95; Nicolet, “Dictateurs Romains, stratégoi autokratores
et généraux carthaginois,” p. 30.
23. Dunkle, “The Greek Tyrant and Roman Political Invective of the Late Republic,”
pp. 153-156; J. Béranger, “Tyrannus: Notes sur la notion de la tyrannie chez les Romains
particulièrement a l’époque de César et de Cicéron,” Revue de études Latines, 13 (1935),
pp. 89-90; Jászi and Lewis, Against the Tyrant, pp. 10-11; Mario Turchetti, Tyrannie et
Tyrannicide de l’Antiquité à nos jours, pp.160-164; Cicero, “Pro rege Deiotaro,” Orations,
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2000, p. 501-541; Jean-Louis Ferrary, “Cicéron
et la. dictature,” Dictatures, pp. 97-105; Neal Wood, Cicero’s Social and Political Thought,
Berkeley: University of California Press, 1988, pp. 155-158.
24. Livy, History of Rome, Book II: 18, pp. 275-276; Mommsen, Le droit public romain,
Vol. III, pp. 162-163.
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
436
Political Theory
25. Aristotle, Politics, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1990, Book V: 10,
pp. 457; Plato, The Republic, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1994, Book VIII:
19, p. 333; Book II: 3, pp. 117-119; Diogenes Laertius, “Plato,” Lives of Eminent Philosophers,
Vol. I, Cambridge: Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2000, III: 83, p. 349; Heredotus’ story of
Gyges, the first tyrant, exemplifies the violent, murderous beginnings of tyranny. Herodotus,
Histories, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1995, Book I: 8-15, pp. 11-19;
Cicero, De re publica, Book I: 64, pp. 101-103. For the relationship between tyranny and
violent usurpation, see Dolores Hegyi, “Notes on the Origins of Greek Tyrannis,” Academia
scientiarum Hungarica, Acta Antiqua, 13 (1965), pp. 303-318; H. W. Plecket, “The Archaic
tyrannis,” Talanta, 1 (1969), pp. 19-61; Jules Labarbe, “L’apparition de la notion de tyrannie
dans la Grèce archaique,” L’Antiquité Classique, 40 (1971), pp. 471-504.
26. Aristotle, Politics, Book IV:8, p. 327; Book VI:2, p. 507; Polybius, The Histories, Book
VI:7, pp. 283-284.
27. Cicero, Laws, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1994, Book III:3, p. 467.
28. This contrasts with the arbitrariness and indeterminacy of tyranny that made law its
enemy. For an insightful discussion of this aspect of tyranny, tyranny as freedom, see Arlene
W. Saxonhouse, “The Tyranny of Reason in the World of the Polis,” The American Political
Science Review, 82:4 (1988), pp. 1261-1275.
29. Aristotle, Politics, Book V:9, 10-11, p. 467.
30. Aristotle, Politics, Book III:11, pp. 269-271; Book V:9, p. 459-475; Plato, The Laws,
Book VIII, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 832c, pp. 137-139; Nicolet,
“Dictatorship in Rome,” p. 265; Lucien Jerphagnon, “Que le tyran est contre-nature. Sur
quelques clichés de l’historiography romaine,” Actes du Colloque: La Tyrannie, Centre de
Publication de l’Université de Caen: Cahiers de philosophie politique et juridique, 1984,
pp. 39-50.
31. Herodotus, Histories, Book III:80, p. 105; Aristotle, Politics, Book III:5, p. 207;
Cicero, De Re Publica; Book II:32, pp. 169; Dio Cassius, Roman History, Book IV:13
(Zonaras), p. 107; Mommsen, Le droit public romain, Vol. III, pp. 7, 164-165, 191-197; D.
Cohen, “The Origins of Dictatorship,” pp. 300-318; F. E. Adcock, Roman Political Ideas and
Practice, Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Press, 1967, p. 46; Mansfield, Taming the
Prince. The Ambivalence of Modern Executive Power, pp. 82-85. Polybius and Cicero recognized in the tyrant a deviant ruler, an unjust king. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, Book
VIII: 10, pp. 489-491; Cicero, De Re Publica, II:27, p. 159; Book I: 28-31, 60, 62, pp. 6971, 93-95, 97; Book II: 25-27, 32, pp. 155-161, 169; Polybius, The Histories, Book VI:7,
pp. 284-285. Tyranny was regarded as an almost inevitable, natural perversion of kingship in
that the limits separating them did not mark any real difference. See, Aristotle, Politics,
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1994, Book III:5, p. 209; Aristotle,
Nicomachean Ethics, Book VIII:10, pp. 489-491; Aristotle, Rhetoric, Book I:8, p. 89;
Polybius, The Histories, Book VI:7, p. 285; Cicero, De Re Publica, Book II:25, 157; Claude
Nicolet, “Polybe et les institutions romaines,” Entretiens sur l’Antiquité Classique de la
Fondation Hardt, XX, Genève: Vandoeuvres, 1974, p. 209-265; Neal Wood, Cicero’s Social and
Political Thought, Berkeley: University of California Press, 1988, pp. 156-157.
32. Cicero, De Re Publica, Book I: 30, p. 95; Dio Cassius, Roman History, Book IV:13
(Zonaras), pp. 107-109; Carl Schmitt, Die Dictatur, Berlin: Duncker und Humblot, 1994,
p. 2l; Clinton Rossiter, Constitutional Dictatorship: Crisis Government in the Modern
Democracies, New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers, 2004, pp. 17-18.
33. Cicero, De Re Publica, Book I:40-43, pp. 93-101; Book II:26-30, 32, pp. 157-163, 169;
Dio Cassius, Roman History, Book IV:13 (Zonaras), p. 107. Also, see Jean-Louis Ferrary,
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
Kalyvas / The Tyranny of Dictatorship
437
“Cicéron et la dictature,” pp. 97-105; Béranger, “Tyrannus: Notes sur la notion de la tyrannie
chez les Romains particulièrement a l’époque de César et de Cicéron,” pp. 89-90.
34. Clinton l. Rossiter, Constitutional Dictatorship, p. 17.
35. Polybius, The Histories, Book VI: 7, pp. 284-285; Kurt von Fritz, The Theory of the
Mixed Constitution in Antiquity. A Critical Analysis of Polybius’s Political Ideas, New York:
Columbia University Press, 1954; T. Cole, “The Sources and Composition of Polybius VI,”
Historia, 13 (1964), pp. 440-486; Claude Nicolet, “Polybe et les institutions romaines,” Emilio
Gabba (ed.), Polybe. Entretiens sur l’Antiquité classique, Geneva: Vandoeuvres, 1973,
pp. 209-259; S. Podes, “Polybius and his Theory of Anacyclosis—Problems of not just
Ancient Political Theory,” History of Political Thought, 12:4 (1991), pp. 577-587.
36. Dio Cassius, Roman History, Book IV:13 (Zonaras), p. 109.
37. Aristotle, Politics, Book III:4, p. 201, Book III:9, p. 249; Polybius, The Histories; Book
III:86, 87, pp. 213, 215; Cicero, De Re Publica, Book I:32, p. 77, Book I:60, p. 95, Book II:32,
p. 169. Also see, James F. McGlew, Tyranny and Political Culture in Ancient Greece, Ithaca:
Cornell University Press, 1993, pp. 9. Here, the term anomia refers to its original ancient
Greek meaning and not to its modern appropriation by Emile Durkheim.
38. For tyranny as anomy, see Plato, Republic, Book IX: 572b, 575a-b, pp. 339, 349; Plato,
Statesman, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1995, 302e-303a, p. 163; Aristotle,
Politics, Book IV:8, pp. 325-327; Dionysius, Roman Antiquities, Book V:70, p. 211. Raymond
Weil, “De la tyrannie dans la pensée politique grecque de l’époque classique,” Dictatures et
Légitimité, p. 38. For an insightful discussion of nomos, anomie, and tyranny, see Angel Sanchez
de la Torre, La tyrannie dans la Grèce antique, Paris: Éditions Bière, 1999, pp. 23-124.
39. P.-M., Martin, L’idée de royauté à Rome. Vol. II. Haine de la royauté et séductions
monarchiques (du IVe siècle av. J.-C. au principat augustéen), Clermont-Ferrand: Adosa, 1994,
pp. 104-105.
40. Hinard, “De la dictature à la tyrannie. Réflexions sur la dictature de Sylla,” pp. 89-92;
Ferrary, “Cicéron et la dictature,” pp. 101-105.
41. Martin, L’idée de royauté à Rome. Vol. II. Haine de la royauté et séductions monarchiques
(du IVe siècle av. J.-C. au principat augustéen), pp. 104-105.
42. For a brief but clear comparative presentation of the two accounts, see Kaplan,
Dictatorships and “Ultimate” Degrees in the Early Roman Republic 501-201 BC, pp. 18-20;
Fox, “History and Rhetoric in Dionysius of Halicarnassus,” pp. 134-135; H. Hill, “Dionysius
of Halicarnassus and the Origins of Rome,” The Journal of Roman Studies, 51:1-2 (1961),
p. 92; Emilio Gabba, “Diogini e la dittatura a Roma,” Tria Corda. Scritti in onore di Arnaldo
momigliano, Como: Biblioteca di Athenaeum, 1983, pp. 215-228.
43. Emilio Gabba, Dionysius and the History of Archaic Rome, pp. 140-141; Lintott, The
Constitution of the Roman Republic, p. 110; Mommsen, Le droit public romain, Vol. III,
p. 163; Paul M. Martin, L’idée de royaté à Rome. Vol. I. De la Rome royale au consensus
républicain, Paris: Adosa, 1982, p. 302.
44. Dionysius of Halicarnassus, Roman Antiquities, Books V: 70, p. 211. Cicero proposes
a different account of Publius Valerius and his legislation. Cicero, De Re Publica, Book II:31,
p. 165.
45. A. W. Lintott, “Provocatio: From the Struggle of the Orders to the Principate,” Aufstieg
und Niedergang der römischen Welt, 1:2 (1972), pp. 226-267; A. W. Lintott, Violence in
Republican Rome, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999, pp. 12-13; A. W. Lintott, The
Constitution of the Roman Republic, p. 33. Also see, A. H. J. Greenidge, “The Procedure of the
‘Provocatio,’” The Classical Review, 9:1 (1895), pp. 4-8; A. H. J. Greenidge, “The ‘Provocatio
Militiae’ and Provincial Jurisdiction,” The Classical Review, 10:5 (1896), pp. 225-233;
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
438
Political Theory
E. S. Staveley, “Provocatio during the Fifth and Fourth Centuries BC,” Historia, III (19541955), p. 412-428. Cloud J. Duncan, “The Origin of Provocatio,” RPh, 72:1 (1998), p. 25-48.
46. M. Humbert, “Le tribunat de la plèbe et le tribunal du people: remarques sur l’histoire de
la provocation ad populum,” Mélanges de l’École Française de Rome, 100 (1988), pp. 431-503;
Michèle Ducos, Les Romains et la Loi. Reserches sur les rapports de la philosophie grecque et
de la tradition romaine á la fin de la République, Paris: Les Belles Lettres, 1984, pp. 71-79.
47. Dionysius of Halicarnassus, Roman Antiquities, Books V: 70, pp. 211-215; Livy,
History of Rome, Book II: 7-8, pp. 239-245; Plutarch, “Publicola,” Lives, Vol. I, Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1998, sections xi-xii, pp. 531-535.
48. Livy, History of Rome, Book III:55, p. 183; Cicero, De Re Publica, Book II:31, 53,
p. 165; Cicero, De Oratore, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, Book II:199, p. 343.
Also, see Ch. Wirszubski, Libertas as a Political Idea at Rome during the Late Republic and
Early Principate, Cambridge, Mass.: Cambridge University Press, 1950, pp. 25-27.
49. Dionysius of Halicarnassus, Roman Antiquities, Books V: 70, p. 211.
50. Dionysius of Halicarnassus, Roman Antiquities, Books V: 70, p. 213.
51. Dionysius of Halicarnassus, Roman Antiquities, Books V: 70, p. 213.
52. Livy, History of Rome, Book II:18, 29-30, p. 277, 313-315; Mommsen, Le droit public
romain, Vol. IV, p. 461.
53. Dionysius of Halicarnassus, Roman Antiquities, Books V: 70, p. 215.
54. Dionysius of Halicarnassus, Roman Antiquities, Books V: 75, p. 229.
55. Gabba, Dionysius and the History of Archaic Rome, p. 140.
56. Dionysius of Halicarnassus, Roman Antiquities, Books V: 70, 71, pp. 215, 213, 217.
57. Dionysius of Halicarnassus, Roman Antiquities, Books V: 73, p. 223. Also, see Forte,
Rome and the Romans as the Greeks Saw Them, p. 200; Nicolet, “Dictateurs Romains, stratégoi
autokratores et généraux carthaginois,” pp. 30, 34-37, 42; Hinard, “De la dictature à la tyrannie.
Réflexions sur la dictature de Sylla,” pp. 94-96; Ferrary, “Cicéron et la dictature,” p. 103.
58. Dionysius of Halicarnassus, “Thucydides,” Critical Essays. Vol. 1: Ancient Orators,
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1973, 51, p. 617; Hurst, “Un critique grec dans
la Rome d’Auguste: Denys d’Halicarnasse,” pp. 841-843; Gabba, Dionysius and the History
of Archaic Rome, p. 147.
59. Gabba, Dionysius and the History of Archaic Rome, p. 140.
60. Mommsen, Le droit public romain, Vol. IV, p. 187.
61. Gabba, Dionysius and the History of Archaic Rome, p. 140; Mansfield, Taming the
Prince. The Ambivalence of Modern Executive Power, pp. 84-85; Hugh J. Mason, “The Roman
Government in Greek Sources: The Effect of Literary Theory on the Translation of Official
Titles,” Phoenix, 24:2 (1970), pp. 153-154.
62. Cicero, De Re Publica, Book I:63, p. 95; Cicero, De Legibus, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press, Book III:3, p. 467; Lintott, The Constitution of the Roman Republic, p. 110;
Giuseppe Valditara, Studi sul magister populi. Dagli ausiliari militari del rex ai primi magistrati
repubblicani, Milano: Giuffré, 1989.
63. Mommsen, Le droit public romain, Vol. III, pp. 187.
64. Clinton Rossiter, Constitutional Dictatorship. Crisis Government in the Modern
Democracies, p. 25.
65. Xenophon, “Hieron,” Scripta Minora, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press,
2000, 4, p. 35; 6, p. 29.
66. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, Book VIII: 12, pp. 497-499; Lucian, “The Downward
Journey, or the Tyrant,” Lucian, Vol. II, 11, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1999,
p. 23; Melvin Richter, “A Family of Political Concepts: Tyranny, Despotism, Bonapartism,
Caesarism, Dictatorship, 1750-1917,” p. 224.
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
Kalyvas / The Tyranny of Dictatorship
439
67. Aristotle, Politics, Book V:9, p. 463.
68. Mommsen, Le droit public romain, Vol. III, pp. 187; Rossiter, Constitutional
Dictatorship. Crisis Government in the Modern Democracies, p. 25.
69. Dionysius of Halicarnassus, Roman Antiquities, Books V: 70, p. 211; Nicolet,
“Dictateurs Romains, stratégoi autokratores et généraux carthaginois,” pp. 34-35. For the concept of “voluntary tyranny,” see Jim MacAdam, “Voluntary Tyranny,” University of Ottawa
Quarterly, 56:2 (1986), pp. 153-161.
70. Aristotle, Politics, Book III: 9, p. 251, Book IV: 8, pp. 325-326; Book V: 8, p. 441;
Book V: 8, p. 457; Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, Book VIII: 10, p. 491; Xenophon,
Memorabilia, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, Book: IV: 6, p. 345.
71. Herodotus, Histories, Book I: 8-15, pp. 11-19.
72. Jászi and Lewis, Against the Tyrant: The Tradition and Theory of Tyrannicide, pp. 7, 26-27.
73. Aristotle, Politics, Book III: 9, p. 247.
74. Aristotle, Politics, Book III: 9-10, pp. 251-253, 261-263, Book IV: 8, p. 325. Also, see
Raymond Weil, “De la tyrannie dans la penseé politique grecque de l’époque classique,”
Dictatures et Légitimité, pp. 42-47; Roger Boesche, “Aristotle’s ‘Science’ of Tyranny,” History
of Political Thought, 14 (1993), pp. 1-25.
75. Aristotle, Politics, Book III: 9, p. 251.
76. Aristotle, Politics, Book IV: 8, pp. 325-327.
77. Aristotle, Politics, Books III: 9, p. 251. For the tyranny of Pittacus, see A. Andrewes,
The Greek Tyrants, New York: Harper Torchbooks, 1956, pp. 92-99; Claude Mossé, La tyrannie dans la Gréce antique, Paris: PUF, 1969, 14-15; H. W. Pleket, “The Archaic Tyrannis,”
Atalanta, 1 (1969), pp. 19-61. Dionysius supplements Aristotle’s observation about this extraordinary office by reporting an additional broader function, that of restoring the Republic to
its foundational principles against the destructive force of corruption. Here, the dictator
assumes the form of the founder and legislator.
78. For a different, less sympathetic, interpretation of Dionysius’ appropriation of this
Aristotelian term, see Mason, “The Roman Government in Greek Sources: The Effect of
Literary Theory on the Translation of Official Titles,” pp. 153-154, 159.
79. Dionysius of Halicarnassus, Roman Antiquities, Books V: 77, p. 235; Gabba, Dionysius
and the History of Archaic Rome, p. 143; Nicolet, “Dictateurs Romains, stratégoi autokratores
et généraux carthaginois,” p. 30.
80. Mommsen, Le droit public romain, Vol. IV, pp. 425-470.
81. Istvan, Hahn, “Appians Darstellung der sullanischen Diktatur,” Acta classica Universitatis
Scientiarum Debreceniensis, 10-11 (1974-1975), pp. 111-120.
82. For Appian’s interest in emergencies and conflicts, see Gowing, The Triumviral
Narratives of Appian and Cassius Dio, p. 280; Bucher, “The Origins, Program, and
Composition of Appian’s Roman History,” p. 420.
83. Appian, The Civil Wars, Book I: 99, pp. 183-185; Mommsen, Le droit public romain,
Vol. IV, p. 440.
84. Appian, The Civil Wars, Book I: 3, 99, pp. 7, 183-185; Kaplan, Dictatorships and
“Ultimate” Degrees in the Early Roman Republic, p. 144.
85. Appian, The Civil Wars, Book I: 99, 3, p. 183, 7. On Appian’s conceptual equation, see
James Luce Jr., “Appian’s Magisterial Terminology,” Classical Philology, 56:1 (1961), pp. 25-27.
86. Appian, The Civil Wars, Book II:137, p. 481.
87. Nicolet, “Dictateurs Romains, stratégoi autokratores et généraux carthaginois,”
pp. 37-39, 42.
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
440
Political Theory
88. Appian, The Civil Wars, Book I: 99, p. 185. Also, see Kaplan, Dictatorships and
“Ultimate” Decrees in the Early Roman Republic 501-202 BC, p. 144; Frédéric Hurlet, La
dictature de Sylla: Monarchie ou magistrature Republicaine? Brussels: Institut Historique
Belge de Rome, 1993, pp. 93-108; Mommsen, Le droit public romain, Vol. IV, pp. 425-470.
89. Appian, The Civil Wars, Book I: 99, p. 183.
90. Appian, The Civil Wars, Book I: 99, p. 183. In addition, the exceptional trait of Sulla’s
tyranny also was due, according to Appian, to the unparalleled fact that “he was the first man,
so far as I know,” who “desired to turn himself . . . from a tyrant into a private citizen” and
“had the courage to lay down his tyrannical power voluntarily.” Appian, The Civil Wars, Book
I: 3, 104, p. 7, 195.
91. Plutarch, “Caesar,” Lives VII, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1994, 53:1-2,
pp. 575; Plutarch, “Lysander and Sulla,” Lives IV, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press,
2000, 1:1, p. 447.
92. Turchetti, Tyrannie et Tyrannicide de l’Antiquité à nos jours, p. 163.
93. Appian, The Civil Wars, Book I: 3, p. 7.
94. I say “almost all” because there are three recorded cases, that of Furius Camillus II (390
BC), L. Aemilius Mamercinus Privenas (316 BC), and M. Servilius Pulex Geminus (202 BC),
which violated the six-month limit. Another irregular dictatorship was that of Minucius in 217
BC. T. A. Dorey, “The Dictatorship of Minucius,” The Journal of Roman Studies, 45: 1-2.
(1955), pp. 92-96. For these and some additional violations, see Saint-Bonnet, L’État d’exception, pp. 59-60.
95. Appian, The Civil Wars, Book I: 99, pp. 183-184.
96. Appian’s tyrannical dictatorship reappears timidly and ambivalently in Jean-Jacques
Rousseau’s republican vision. Although Rousseau approves of the institution and the practice,
he warns, echoing Appian, that “in the crises that call for its establishment the state is soon
destroyed or saved, and once the pressing need has passed, the dictatorship becomes tyrannical or useless.” Departing clearly from his more canonical and “precise” definition of tyranny
as usurpation of royal authority, Rousseau places it in the void opened up by the absence of
temporal limits, suggesting that the tyrant is a permanent dictator. This formulation evokes
Appian in that the affinity between the dictator and the tyrant unfolds in a temporal horizon.
For this reason Rousseau insists that the best protection against this ominous prospect is to
never extend or prolong a dictator’s commission. However, there is an important difference
between the two thinkers. While Appian understands the temporal factor as only one of degree,
Rousseau sees it as a bridge allowing the crossing from one form of rule over to another. In
that sense, although the Roman institution of dictatorship appears to be liable to abuse once it
is abused it is not the same anymore. It has undergone a qualitative transformation into something else: tyranny. Here one can sense the presence of Rousseau’s canonical definition. The
dictator who has violated the law regulating the length of his magistracy has in fact usurped a
title “without having any right to it.” In that sense, the tyrant remains a usurper, he who by violating the temporal restrictions seizes illegally dictatorial power. Tyranny is again a stolen,
degenerated form of a supreme executive rule and not the secret truth of dictatorship, not even
its dark side. Jean-Jacques Rousseau, “Du Contract Social; ou, Principes du Droit Politique,”
Œuvres Complètes, Volume III, Gallimard: Bibliothèque de la Pléiade, 1964, Book IV: 7,
pp. 458, 423; Pierangelo Catalano, “Le concept de dictature de Rousseau à Bolivar: essai pour
une mise au point politique sur la base du droit romain,” Dictatures, pp. 7-25; Jean Ferrari,
“Rousseau, Kant et la tyrannie,” Actes du Colloque: La Tyrannie, pp. 177-189.
97. Appian, The Civil Wars, Book I:16, p. 33.
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
Kalyvas / The Tyranny of Dictatorship
441
98. Cicero, “The Third Speech on the Agrarian Law,” Orations, Vol. IV, Cambridge, Mass.:
Harvard University Press, 1930, III: 5, p. 489.
99. Livy, History of Rome, Book 9:26, pp. 263-267; Kaplan, Dictatorships and “Ultimate”
Decrees in the Early Roman Republic 501-202 BC, pp. 93-94; Lintott, The Constitution of the
Roman Republic, p. 112.
100. It is worth noting, however, that Diodorus of Sicily (80-20 BC), another Greek historian
contemporary of Livy, does not confirm this interpretation. Although Diodorus recounts the dictatorship of Gaius Manius, he does not mention the story of his impeachment. Diodorus of Sicily,
Library of History, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2002, Book 19:76, p. 43.
101. It seems that Dionysius and Appian’s re-interpretation of tyranny is empirically contradicted by the lex repetundarum or recovery law, contained in a fragmented bronze tablet,
and which suggests that the dictator could be brought to trial after the end of his tenure in
office. Without knowing, however, the exact dating of the law, its duration, and most importantly its author, it is difficult to ascertain with certainty the extent and character of its legal
impact on dictatorship. For example, most scholars have suggested that the law was authored
by Gaius Gracchus in his struggle to weaken the senatorial class and thus has been interpreted
as an instrument in the political warfare between the orders. Two questions are relevant here:
(1) How did the demise of Gracchus affect this law? (2) Is it not the case that the law itself is
a telling instance of how the institution of dictatorship was turned into a site of political struggle and that the problem of the accountability of the dictator was a contested, open-ended
issue, depending on relations of power and political interests? On this see, Emilio Badian,
“Lex Acilia Repetundarum,” The American Journal of Philology, 74:4 (1954), pp. 374-384;
A. N. Sherwin-White, “The Date of the Lex Repetundarun and its Consequences,” The Journal
of Roman Studies, 62 (1972), pp. 83-99; A. N. Sherwin-White, “The Lex Repetundarum and
the Political Ideas of Gaius Gracchus,” The Journal of Roman Studies, 72 (1982), pp. 18-31.
102. Lintott, The Constitution of the Roman Republic, p. 112.
103. Richter, “A Family of Political Concepts: Tyranny, Despotism, Bonapartism, Caesarism,
Dictatorship, 1750-1917,” pp. 221-248.
104. Mommsen, Le droit public romain, Vol. III, pp. 193-194; Vol. IV, pp. 425-470; Carl
Schmitt, Die Diktatur, Berlin: Duncker und Humblot, 1994, p. 3; Saint-Bonnet, L’État d’exception, pp. 47-70; Nicolet, “Dictatorship in Rome,” pp. 265-276; Andrew Arato, “Good-bye
to Dictatorship?” pp. 925-933.
105. Hinard, “De la dictature à la tyrannie. Réflexions sur la dictature de Sylla,” pp. 87-105.
106. Appian, The Civil Wars, Book I:11, p. 185; Plutarch, “Comparison of Solon and
Publicola,” Lives, II-III, pp. 569-575; Dio Cassius, Roman History, Book IV:13 (Zonaras),
p. 109; Ch. Wirszubski, Libertas as a Political Idea at Rome during the Late Republic and
Early Principate, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1968, p. 64. As Aristotle perceptively observed regarding Greek tyrants, “a mode of securing tyranny is to make it more like
kingship.” Aristotle, Politics, Book V: 9, p. 467.
107. Martin, L’idée de royauté à Rome. Vol. II. Haine de la royauté et séductions monarchiques (du IVe siècle av. J.-C. au principat augustéen), pp. 3-11.
108. Mommsen, Le droit public romain, Vol. III, p. 193; Dio Cassius, Roman History,
Book IV: 13 (Zonaras), p. 107.
109. Dio Cassius, Roman History, Book IV: 13 (Zonaras), p. 107.
110. Thomas Jefferson, “Notes on Virginia: Query XIII,” Joyce Appleby and Terence Ball
(eds.), Jefferson. Political Writings, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999, p. 332.
Michael Zuckert offers an illuminating interpretation of Jefferson’s objections to Roman
dictatorship within the context of the neo-republican revival. See, Michael P. Zuckert, The
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011
442
Political Theory
Natural Rights Republic. Studies in the Foundation of the American Political Tradition, Notre
Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 1996, pp. 212-219.
111. Jefferson, “Notes on Virginia: Query XIII,” p. 335 (emphases added).
112. Aristotle, The Art of Rhetoric, Book I: 8, p. 89.
113. Herodotus, Histories, Book III:81, p. 107,
114. Plato, Gorgias, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1996, 493, p. 417;
Plato, The Republic, Book IX: 578, p. 361.
115. Jefferson, “Notes on Virginia: Query XIII,” p. 334.
116. Jefferson, “Notes on Virginia: Query XIII,” pp. 334-335. Also, see Spinoza, A
Political Treatise, New York: Dover Publications, 1951, chapter X:1, pp. 378-379.
117. Jefferson, “Notes on Virginia: Query XIII,” p. 335. For dictatorship as a “remedy,” see
Mommsen, Le droit public romain, Vol. III, p. 169.
118. Polybius, The Histories, Book VI: 10, p. 291; Cicero, De Re Publica, Book II: 57, p. 167.
119. Jefferson, “Notes on Virginia: Query XIII,” pp. 334-335.
120. For the concept of constitutional dictatorship, see Schmitt, Die Dictatur; Frederick M.
Watkins, “The Problem of Constitutional Dictatorship,” Friedrich and Mason (eds.), Public
Policy, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1940, pp. 324-378; Carl J. Friedrich,
Constitutional Government and Democracy, New York: Ginn and Company, 1950, pp. 572-588;
Clinton Rossiter, Constitutional Dictatorship: Crisis Government in the Modern Democracies,
pp. 3-32, 288-314; Bruce Ackerman, “The Emergency Constitution,” The Yale Law
Journal, Vol. 113:5 (2004), pp. 1029-1091. For a recent opposite approach that opposes the
historical and conceptual continuity of constitutional dictatorship, see Giorgio Agamben, State
of Exception, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2005, p. 6-11. Clinton Rossiter,
Constitutional Dictatorship: Crisis Government in the Modern Democracies, pp. 5, 8, 288.
121. Antocides, “On the Mysteries,” Minor Attic Orators: Antiphon, Andocides, Vol. I,
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1982, Book I: 96-98, p. 413; Benjamin D.
Meritt, “Greek Inscriptions: Anti-tyrannical Inscription,” Hesperia, 21 (1952), pp. 355-359;
Lysias, Against Eratosthenes; Lucian, “Tyrannicide,” Lucian. Vol I, Cambridge, Mass.:
Harvard University Press, 1996; Martin Ostwald, “Athenian Legislation against Tyranny and
Subversion,” Transactions of the American Philological Association, 86 (1955), 110-128;
Jaszy and Lewis, Against the Tyrant: the Tradition and Theory of Tyrannicide; Antony J.
Podlecki, “The Political Significance of Athenian ‘Tyrannicide’ Cult,” Historia, 15:2 (1966),
pp. 129-141; F. L. Ford, Political Murder: From Tyrannicide to Political Terrorism, Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985; Michael W. Taylor, The Tyrant Slayers. The Heroic
Image in the Fifth Century BC: Athenian Art and Politics, Salem: Ayer, 1992.
122. Robert J. Bonner, “Emergency Government in Rome and Athens,” The Classical
Journal, 18:3 (1922), p. 144; Saint-Bonnet, L’État d’exception, pp. 45-46.
123. Cicero, De Re Publica, Book II: 26, p. 157; Plato, Republic, Book VIII, 566b, p. 321.
124. Aristotle, Politics, Book IV:8, p. 327.
125. For the continuity between Roman dictatorship and modern theories and practices of
the state of emergency, see Mommsen, Le droit public romain, Vol. IV, p. 187.
Andreas Kalyvas is an assistant professor of political science at The New School for Social
Research in New York City. He is the author of Democracy and the Politics of the Extraordinary:
Max Weber, Carl Schmitt, Hannah Arendt (Cambridge University Press, forthcoming). He is
currently completing a coauthored book manuscript on liberalism and republicanism while
working as a monograph on tyranny and dictatorship in Western political thought.
Downloaded from ptx.sagepub.com at KNOX COLLEGE on April 25, 2011