Download The Formula of the Universal Law

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts

Philosophy of history wikipedia , lookup

Crime wikipedia , lookup

Autonomy wikipedia , lookup

Ethics wikipedia , lookup

Antinomianism wikipedia , lookup

Bernard Williams wikipedia , lookup

Jurisprudence wikipedia , lookup

Divine command theory wikipedia , lookup

Moral development wikipedia , lookup

Internalism and externalism wikipedia , lookup

Consequentialism wikipedia , lookup

Moral responsibility wikipedia , lookup

Moral relativism wikipedia , lookup

Lawrence Kohlberg's stages of moral development wikipedia , lookup

Morality throughout the Life Span wikipedia , lookup

Morality wikipedia , lookup

Thomas Hill Green wikipedia , lookup

Secular morality wikipedia , lookup

School of Salamanca wikipedia , lookup

The World as Will and Representation wikipedia , lookup

Emotivism wikipedia , lookup

Ethical intuitionism wikipedia , lookup

John McDowell wikipedia , lookup

Immanuel Kant wikipedia , lookup

Kantian ethics wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
Kant’s Formula of the Universal Law: A Consideration of Its Capacity to Require
the Moral Law
Kant, in the First Section of his Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (GMM),
argues that a good-willed person must act from the motive of duty in order for her
actions to have moral worth. The argument is summarized in his famous conclusion,
the Categorical Imperative (CI): “[One] ought never to act except in such a way that
[one] can also will that [one’s] maxim should become a universal law.”1 I will show in
this paper, however, that Kant fails to reach his goal of establishing the CI (or one of its
formulations) as the “supreme principle of morality” because, even if the argument is
assumed to be sound in its essentials, it does not result necessarily in the moral law
that Kant believed it did.
1. Introduction
Kant’s moral theory is widely commended as one of the boldest endeavors in
modern philosophy. Unlike the ethical thinkers who had preceded him, he did not seek
to establish what the Good was, and then give rules for applying it. Rather, he intended
“to seek out and establish the supreme principle of morality” (hereafter SPM), whereby
any rational being could determine what actions were moral through the application of
this one rational principle.
1 Immanuel Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. and analyzed by H.J. Paton (New
York: Harper, 1964), 70 [17, 402]. Throughout, I will list the page number for Paton’s version first,
followed in brackets by the page number for Kant’s 2nd edition, then that for the edition published by the
Royal Prussian Academy in Berlin (GMM appears in volume 4 of this latter work).
2
Despite the boldness of Kant’s effort, it has been criticized for its perceived
failings. My task will be to show that the argument for the CI—and specifically the
Formula of Universal Law (FUL)—as being the SPM Kant seeks to establish (call this
argument “T”), does not necessarily result in a conception of the moral law (call it “ML”)
as Kant held it to be, even if one largely abandons the traditional criticisms of T and
instead assumes it to be an essentially valid argument. Drawing on the work of two
recent commentators, I will show that it is possible to draw other conclusions from the
beginning of Kant’s argument in the GMM.
I will assume that the essential statement of Kant’s conclusion can be found in
the FUL, the first formulation of the CI: “Act only on that maxim through which you can
at the same time will that it should become a universal law.” 2 Thus, I will use the FUL to
stand for the conclusion of T.
2. The Possibility of Results Other Than Kant’s Moral Law
Does the CI—and Kant’s arguments in support of it—provide all that is necessary
to produce the kind of ethical system that Kant seems to envision? Or is there some
other principle that Kant assumes that allows for the CI to determine a moral framework
of the sort he intends? If this assumed principle is supplanted with a different one, will
not the CI produce a much different result? In this section, I will explore two variations
on this theme of results other than Kant’s envisioned ML.
Let us entertain a provocative example in order to tease out whether or not the CI
necessarily results in the ML. Kant makes it clear through the FUL that any maxim, in
2
Ibid., 88 [52, 421].
KANT’S FUL: A CONSIDERATION OF ITS CAPACITY TO REQUIRE THE MORAL LAW
3
order to meet the requirements of a categorical imperative, must be able to be willed
universally. One of Kant’s famous examples of this test is the false promise. He
concludes that a moral agent cannot will the maxim, “a person who believes himself to
be in need can make any kind of false promise he desires,” without self-contradiction.
Let us assume for the moment Kant’s principle of universalization and its illustration in
the false promise example.
Let us expand on a provocative illustration from David Martyn by supposing that
someone (call him “Jones”) proposes a maxim of an entirely different kind, one that
appears initially to be absurd: one should murder anyone who gets in one’s way. 3
Jones argues that murder is not destruction, after all, but merely the altering of a natural
form. Nothing is lost or annihilated, according to Jones; it merely metamorphoses into
some other form of its constituent chemical components. Jones maintains that his
maxim passes the universalization test and becomes the law of the universal
metamorphosis of forms. When questioned on this, Jones replies that this law already
exists in nature; indeed, Jones says, “Nature is the universal metamorphosis of forms.”4
Let us assess Jones’s argument. First, does it meet the requirement of FUL?
That is, can it be universalized? Initially, it appears to fail this test. How could anyone
will that humans have a duty to kill one another for almost no reason at all? However,
this is not the correct question to ask. Jones maintains that he does will his maxim to
be universal law. In response, the correct question is: Does his law result in a
3 See David Martyn, Sublime Failures: The Ethics of Kant and Sade, Kritik (Detroit: Wayne State
University Press, 2003), 15-18. His overall thesis, that the ethics of Sade and Kant overlap to the extent
that both conceive of universal standards for behavior in reductionistic and formalistic ways, is beyond the
scope of this paper.
4 Ibid., 16-17. Emphasis in the original.
4
contradiction? It appears that it does not. The principle of the metamorphosis of forms
is consistent with Jones’s murder maxim and its elevation to universal status.
Kant, of course, would object. It is interesting to ask: “On what grounds?” Most
apparently, his objection would be based on his formulation of the CI as the Formula of
Humanity as End in Itself (FH): “Act in such a way that you always treat humanity,
whether in your own person or in the person of any other, never simply as a means, but
always at the same time as an end.”5 Clearly, one cannot murder someone and still
treat him as an end in himself. It is evident that Jones’s proposed universal law does
not obtain once a full Kantian approach is considered.6
However, it must be noted that neither the CI nor its formulation in the FUL, by
themselves, necessarily precludes this intuitively reprehensible “law.” It is only when
the FH is applied that the murder maxim clearly fails.
This prompts us to consider whether or not the FH is entirely consistent with the
bare CI. Though a full evaluation is beyond the scope of this paper, an initial
assessment is possible. First, it must be remembered that Kant, in the preface of GMM,
places high demands on his own reasoning as he goes about developing his ethical
theory. One of the premises of his quest for the SPM was that his argument must be
accomplished with pure rational thought: the metaphysic must precede the empirical,
“each metaphysic having to be scrupulously cleansed of everything empirical if we are
to know how much pure reason can accomplish . . . and from what sources it can by
itself draw its own a priori teaching.”7
5
GMM, 96 [66-67, 429].
Martyn, too, acknowledges the “incompleteness” of the example (see 18, 222n7). He offers it only
as an introductory illustration.
7 GMM, 56 [v, 388-389].
6
KANT’S FUL: A CONSIDERATION OF ITS CAPACITY TO REQUIRE THE MORAL LAW
5
Second, any observation from nature would clearly be empirical. That is, if one
makes a claim based on observations of facts external to oneself, such a claim is said
to be empirical.
Third, Kant’s argument for FH hinges on an observation from nature. In his
reasoning which leads to the FH, Kant states:
Rational beings . . . are called persons because their nature already marks them
out as ends in themselves—that is, as something which ought not to be used
merely as a means—and consequently imposes to that extent a limit on all
arbitrary treatment of them (and is an object of reverence).8
As much as one might desire to agree with Kant about persons being ends in
themselves, it is not at all intuitively clear that his judgment could be determined a priori.
It appears implausible that one could assess a being’s nature without using empirical
evidence. At the very least, it seems that Kant did not provide a sound argument to
establish that he could completely determine a priori what marks persons as ends in
themselves.
Therefore, Kant’s argument for the FH is unsound because it is based, at least
partly, on apparently empirical grounds, a form of reasoning he had previously
prohibited himself from using. Therefore, Kant does not reason from the bare CI (or its
relative, the FUL) to the FH using only pure rational thought. Therefore, the FUL does
not seem—either in itself or via pure rational extension—to necessarily preclude a
potential universal law based on an intuitively amoral, and distinctly non-Kantian,
maxim. Thus, it appears to be somewhat plausible that the ML does not necessarily
follow from the CI/FUL.
8
Ibid., 96 [65, 428]. Emphasis in original.
6
It is also possible to expose a breach between the CI/FUL and the ML by means
of a second argument. Here, I will explore the idea that Kant’s ethical theory represents
a ‘dualism of practical reason.’ This argument, recently made by Hills, draws on the
dualism argument of Sidgwick, who argued that “utilitarianism was not rationally
required because it could not be shown that a utilitarian theory of practical reason was
better justified than a rival egoist theory of practical reason.”9
In short, the dualism argument also can be applied to Kant’s moral theory. A
self-regarding imperative can be formulated that is as justified by Kant’s rules of
practical reasoning as is his own other-regarding imperative. We can label these
parallel positions as the K-prudential law (hereafter, KPL) and the moral law (our
“ML”).10
I will begin my explanation of the dualism argument by describing Sidgwick’s
original usage. Next, I will show (at some length) how it might be applied to Kant’s
practical reasoning. I will conclude this section by evaluating the dualism argument and
showing whether it—similar to the fanciful murder maxim that I previously described—
plausibly exposes certain weaknesses that exist in Kant’s argument for the CI/FUL on
the path to his intended ML.
Sidgwick’s argument is remarkably powerful because it “assumes that the theory
of practical reason endorsed by the candidate ethical theory is almost entirely correct.”11
In its original formulation, Sidgwick conceded much of the theory of practical reasoning
9 See Alison Hills, “Is Ethics Rationally Required?” Inquiry 47 (March 2004): 1-19. The quotation is
from page 1. Sidgwick’s dualism argument was originally proposed in H. Sidgwick, The Methods of
Ethics, 7th ed. (London: Macmillan, 1907).
10 It is important to note here only that Hills’s use of the term ‘prudence’ differs markedly from Kant’s
usage. More will be said about this difference in terminology below.
11 Hills, 1.
KANT’S FUL: A CONSIDERATION OF ITS CAPACITY TO REQUIRE THE MORAL LAW
7
that supports utilitarianism, while showing that utilitarianism itself is not rationally
required. He argued that just as utilitarianism maintains that one ought to maximize
everyone’s happiness, a parallel claim can be made for egoism—which holds that one
ought to maximize only one’s own happiness—based on the same reasoning. Thus,
unless someone can show either that there is no actual conflict between the two
theories or that one is better justified than the other, it is not possible to argue that either
candidate theory is rationally required. In addition, he argues that any justification
offered must be “strong” enough so as to convince a moral skeptic. This strongjustification requirement, coupled with the close parallelism of the competing theories
makes it difficult to justify either one without justifying the other at the same time and to
the same extent.
It is possible to expand Sidgwick’s argument by applying it to Kant’s ethical
theory. Before I show how the dualism can be constructed, the argument requires that I
reject the traditional criticisms of Kant’s ethics and concede many elements of his
reasoning, including:
that ‘duty’ is a fundamental ethical concept;
that ‘humanity’ (the capacity to act rationally) is the source of value;
that duties can be derived from the FUL without invoking desires;
that the different formulations of the ML (particularly the FH and the FUL) are
equivalent;
that, if we have duties, we must be able to decide independently from our
desires;
that humans can be autonomous;
that an autonomous will must act on a law; and
8
that no desire-based law of practical reason could be a law of autonomy, and
consequently, the correct theory of practical reason must depend on
something other than desire.12
It will seem as if the dualism argument has conceded the entire argument, but it has not.
Now, let us review Kant’s distinction between categorical and hypothetical
imperatives. Prudential reasons, based on the agent’s desires, are hypothetical: they
apply only to those agents who have certain desires. Moral imperatives are categorical,
in the sense that their normative force is not dependent on the agent’s desires and that
they obtain for every rational agent, no matter what he desires. Most importantly for
Kant’s argument, categorical imperatives always take precedence over hypothetical
imperatives. Thus, from Kant’s perspective—in terms of Sidgwick’s argument—there is
no dualism between categorical moral imperatives and prudential hypothetical
imperatives because: (1) they are grounded differently, with moral imperatives based on
duty to universal laws and prudential imperatives based on desires; and (2) moral
imperatives always supersede prudential imperatives.
At this point, the dualism argument has seemingly conceded Kant’s entire
argument except the formulations of the ML itself. The break comes in considering the
FH formulation. It demands that an agent treat humanity, whether himself or someone
else, always as an end and never simply as a means. This results in duties to others,
such as the duty not to make false promises, and duties to oneself, including the duty
not to commit suicide.
It is possible, however, to replace the FH with a theory of practical reason (the
KPL) which consists in this formulation:
12
Ibid., 5.
KANT’S FUL: A CONSIDERATION OF ITS CAPACITY TO REQUIRE THE MORAL LAW
9
Always treat humanity in your own person as an end, never as a mere
means.13
Unlike the FH, this theory produces self-regarding imperatives only, but does not
generate other-regarding duties. It is said that self-regarding imperatives (generated by
the KPL) are based on “agent-relative” reasons, while other-regarding imperatives
(generated by the ML) are based on “agent-neutral” reasons.
Owing to the fact that the KPL is self-regarding, Hills finds it more plausible to
classify the imperatives which result from this formula as prudential than as moral (the
latter better describing imperatives which contain duties toward others). It is a
prudential principle in the sense that it produces reasons for action based on an agent’s
interests; however, “these reasons are not concerned with [one’s] interest in [one’s]
desires, but with [one’s] interests as a rational agent, for instance, [one’s] interest in
having well-developed talents.”14 Thus, for Kant, prudence is a hedonistic concept, but
the KPL usage embodies duties arising from a law of self-regard.
With the construction of KPL, it is possible to assess whether or not a dualism of
practical reason exists between the KPL and the ML. As noted above, according to
Sidgwick, there is a dualism unless it can be shown that either there is no actual conflict
between the two theories, or that one is better justified than the other. At a minimum,
the two theories are quite apparently in theoretical conflict,15 having different bases for
the duties they produce: the KPL is based on respect for the agent’s own humanity only,
whereas the ML is based on respect for everyone’s humanity.
13
Ibid., 7.
Ibid.
15 Hills, 9, argues that the two theories are also in practical conflict; however, her example is open to
question.
14
10
There are at least two ways the ML could be shown to be better justified than the
KPL. First, it might be shown that only agent-neutral reasons are valid. But:
No such argument is available, because a theory of agent-relative reasons like
the [KPL] can satisfy all the plausible demands we might make on a theory of
practical reason. [KPL] imperatives are universal (every agent has a reason to
respect her own rational agency) and can be acknowledged as real reasons by
other rational agents.16
Thus, through their ability to be universalized and to be recognized by others, KPL
imperatives are said to be equally justified by the validity of reasons test.
Secondly, the dualism might be solved by showing that the KPL is somehow
inadequate when compared to the ML. Kant’s concepts of freedom and autonomy
seem to be the best candidates for exposing such an inadequacy. For example, if it
could be shown that the notion of freedom requires an agent to accept the ML, then the
KPL would be rendered inadequate in a clear way. Kant’s conception of freedom says
that a positively free will cannot be determined by the agent’s desires, but rather must
be determined by a law.17 The argument for the KPL notes that an agent whose will is
determined by the KPL is operating from a basis of law and not desire.18 Therefore,
Hills argues that there is no valid reason on the basis of freedom (or the related
argument from autonomy) to prefer the ML to the KPL.
Before evaluating this argument from Hills, I will briefly review its logical flow:
(1) Kant’s approach to ethics is correct (including ‘duty’ as a
fundamental ethical concept, placing humanity as the source of
value, the need for freedom, etc.).
16
Ibid., 10.
See GMM, 114-115 [97-99, 446-447].
18 Hills continues with considerable detail here (see 10-14), including significant dialogue with the
positions of H. Allison, Kant’s Theory of Freedom (Cambridge: CUP, 1990) and ‘On a presumed gap in
the derivation of the categorical imperative’ in his Idealism and Freedom (Cambridge: CUP, 1996).
17
KANT’S FUL: A CONSIDERATION OF ITS CAPACITY TO REQUIRE THE MORAL LAW
11
(2) Kant’s FH is a possible theory which can be constructed according
to his rules of practical reason. Namely, it is other-regarding, and
as such, can be rightly called a ML (for Kant, the ML).
(3) Per Sidgwick’s argument, a dualism of practical reason exists when
two theories are in conflict—either theoretically or practically—and
neither is better justified than the other.
(4) It is possible to construct a self-regarding imperative, i.e., KPL,
which is an equally plausible Kantian theory of practical reason and
is in conflict with the ML, both theoretically and practically.
 (5) Kant’s identification of the ML as the only valid theory of practical
reason is in error.
 (C) No agent is rationally required to accept the ML (or the KPL).
To evaluate this argument, I will first consider the dualism tests of Sidgwick, that is,
those of conflict and justification, then proceed to explore one other potential criticism.
First, there seems to be no question that the KPL conflicts with the ML. It
remains then to assess whether or not the ML can be better justified than the KPL. It
seems that the reasoning from Hills in this section lacks a consistent logical force and it
is not clear that she has established an adequate level of plausibility for the KPL in
order to claim equal status with the ML in terms of justification. Despite the fact that she
seeks to place the onus for justification on the side of Kant and his sympathizers, it must
be acknowledged that Kant’s theory has pride of place (and time-length of dominance);
therefore, an objection such as the KPL theory will require a very strong case in order to
proceed in challenging Kant’s ML.
Finally, I find that Hills fails to address one central question regarding the KPL
and its self-regarding imperatives. The theory can appear on the surface to be only a
word game hiding a “morality” based strictly on inclination and desire. Thus, it would
strengthen the argument considerably to reveal explicitly the ways in which an agent
12
who wills to follow the self-regarding imperatives generated by the KPL might differ in
actuality from one who is motivated only by selfish desire.
Nonetheless, I believe her theory shows at least some promise in questioning
how strong the logical link is between Kant’s ethical theory (as shown in the CI/FUL)
and his intended result, the ML.
3. Conclusion
I have attempted to show in this paper that Kant fails to reach his goal of
establishing the CI (or one of its formulations) as the “supreme principle of morality”
because his argument, even if it is assumed to be sound in its essentials, does not
result necessarily in the ML that Kant believed it did.
I have explored two lines of argument—one seemingly amoral and the other
“prudential”—that do not reject Kant’s argument, per se, but only deviate from his
conclusion, the Moral Law (ML). I found that the case of the murder maxim, while
certainly objectionable to the overwhelming majority of rational agents, did generate
some implausibility around Kant’s line of argument from the CI/FUL to the ML. In the
second argument, that of Hills’s K-prudential Law (KPL), I showed that her argument
presumed too great of a burden to be placed on Kant’s argument for the ML.
Nevertheless, I believe that her theory of practical reasoning shows some level of
implausibility in Kant’s strict equation of the CI/FUL and its presumed result in the ML.
On the basis of these objections to Kant’s reasoning, I conclude that he has
failed to fully establish his sought-for supreme principle of morality (SPM) through his
argument for the CI/FUL.
KANT’S FUL: A CONSIDERATION OF ITS CAPACITY TO REQUIRE THE MORAL LAW
13
Bibliography
Hills, Alison. “Is Ethics Rationally Required?” Inquiry 47 (March 2004): 1-19.
Kant, Immanuel. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. and analyzed by H.J.
Paton. New York: Harper, 1964.
Martyn, David. Sublime Failures: The Ethics of Kant and Sade, Kritik. Detroit: Wayne
State University Press, 2003.