* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Conflicting Theories of Self: Dickinson and Neuroscience
Survey
Document related concepts
Embodied cognitive science wikipedia , lookup
Neural correlates of consciousness wikipedia , lookup
Donald O. Hebb wikipedia , lookup
Brain Age: Train Your Brain in Minutes a Day! wikipedia , lookup
Holonomic brain theory wikipedia , lookup
Neurophilosophy wikipedia , lookup
Transcript
Lenkei 1 Alex Lenkei Professor Noble LIT 496 28 April 2014 Conflicting Theories of Self: Dickinson and Neuroscience Philosophers, theorists, and authors have struggled with the question of who we are for millennia. During the 19th century, Emily Dickinson bravely confronted this question as she pondered and probed the philosophy of self. When most scholars examine the subject of self in her poetry, they tend to focus on her spiritual and metaphysical language and her use of concepts such as the soul. But both during and after Dickinson’s lifetime, the examination of nerves and senses as well as the discovery of specific brain functions gave rise to the notion of a corporeal self, one whose selfhood is deeply intertwined with his or her body in the world. Dickinson incorporated these findings into her poetry by thinking deeply about the brain and its relationship to the self. Like other writers of her time, she tended to place the self within this corporeal framework, often conflating the bodily and the divine, the material and immaterial. Recent scientific progress has only cemented these early thoughts on the body, and today neuroscience often characterizes the self as emerging from consciousness in a material brain (Edelman 134). But conflicting theories of self in neuroscience, such as whether the self is a single entity or multiple, limit research of the self. The self that is evident in Dickinson’s poetry appears fragmented yet cohesive. This sense of self she puts forth is characterized by a negotiation of two sets of opposing ideas: spiritualism and materialism as well as unity and division. But how can such negotiations alleviate the conflicts between theories of self in neuroscience today? By understanding these Lenkei 2 two ways in which Dickinson grapples with the idea of self, the “limits to growth,” as Thomas Insel calls them, of neuroscience may be alleviated. Specifically, Dickinson’s merging of these disparate ideas may be a model for how merging conflicting theories of self in neuroscience can lead to collaboration across disciplines and “large-scale science” that can result in “rapid progress in understanding the brain and its disorders” (Insel 426). While Emily Dickinson was composing poetry in the seclusion of her Massachusetts home, the issue of selfhood troubled her greatly as advancements in science challenged her way of thinking. Established ideas from mental scientists such as Thomas Brown and Thomas Upham argued that the self was whole, healthy, and endowed by God, but examination of the brain challenged these assumptions (Kearns 23). Unlike Brown and Upham, Dickinson argued for a divided self, one characterized by dissociation and a frightening, conflicted interior. As these ideas developed, psychology, cognitive science, and neuroscience were making moderate advances as these fields began to separate from the introspective philosophy of the Enlightenment and form their own scientific fields that relied on empirical research. As science writers Judith Hooper and Dick Teresi describe in The Three Pound Universe, research into the source of consciousness made slow advancements until the 1980s. But throughout Dickinson’s life, scientists and physiologists mapped personality traits, located the source of human speech in the brain, explored electrical impulses between neurons, and examined personality changes resulting from traumatic head injuries (Hooper and Teresi xvii). Evidence from scholars like Sabine Sielke suggests that these scientific advancements may have contributed to Dickinson’s conception of a divided self. In “‘The Brain—is wider than the Sky’ or: Re-Cognizing Emily Dickinson,” Sielke argues that Dickinson’s preoccupation with a divided self is the result of exploring memory and emotion in the brain as well as identifying various parts of the brain, Lenkei 3 including the cerebellum and cerebrum, and the human sensory apparatus (Sielke 76). This division and compartmentalization of the anatomy of the brain may have allowed Dickinson to imagine a self that was just as divided. Dickinson’s treatment of the brain in her poetry reflects her “deep interest in science” and a desire to understand “the immense scope of our mental universe” (Sielke 74, 68). Reflective of the time period she was living in, Dickinson often situated her poetry between the philosophical and the scientific. Perhaps as a result, the self that Dickinson imagines seems contradictory at best: divided yet also cohesive, material yet also spiritual. In some of her poems, such as “One need not be a Chamber—to be Haunted” and “I felt a cleaving in my mind,” Dickinson portrays a divided self, one whose numerous faculties and entities were “at times in conflict, at times in concert, always multiple” (Kearns 29). According to Simone du Plock in “Emily Dickinson: Metaphorical Spaces and the Divided Self,” Dickinson’s poetry is an attempt “to describe the experience of being a ‘divided self’ – of fragmentation or splitting of the mind” (du Plock 268). But as Kearns notes, her experiences of fragmentation seem to “take place within a unitary ‘I,’” which implies Dickinson’s uncertainty as to whether the self was divided and whole (Kearns 21). In other poems, such as “The Brain—is wider than the Sky” and “I felt a Funeral, in my Brain,” illustrating the debates of her day, Dickinson is also skeptical of whether the self is material or immaterial, biological or spiritual. In “Emily Dickinson: Anatomist of the Mind,” Michael Kearns writes, “There was a true conflict here, between identifying the mind with the brain and localizing functions within the brain, on the one hand, and on the other treating the mind as divine, immaterial, and unified” (Kearns 20). Here, Kearns illustrates a tension that is central in many of Dickinson’s poems, a tension she wrestled with and encountered in her reading and education (Kearns 20). These two sets of conflicted concepts Dickinson seems to Lenkei 4 have incorporated into her thinking of the self suggest that merging similarly conflicting theories of self can lead to “rapid progress” in the field of neuroscience (Insel 426). In “The Brain—is wider than the Sky,” Dickinson illustrates the two sets of opposing ideas she seems to grapple with regarding the nature of the brain and the self, and understanding how she merges these two ideas may lead to greater collaboration between neuroscientific theories of self. The Brain—is wider than the Sky— For—put them side by side— The one the other will contain With ease—and You—beside— The Brain is deeper than the sea— For—hold them—Blue to Blue— The one the other will absorb— As Sponges—Buckets—do— The Brain is just the weight of God— For—Heft them—Pound for Pound— And they will differ—if they do— As Syllable from Sound— Dickinson’s exploration of materialist and spiritualist perspectives, and her merging of the two, are recurring themes throughout her poetry. In the first two stanzas, Dickinson describes the brain’s material capacity to comprehend and mentally construct physical phenomena much larger than itself, such as the sky and sea. The second stanza expands Dickinson’s materialist conception of the brain by comparing it to physical objects like a bucket and sponge. Both metaphors, when scrutinized, seem to suggest two different descriptions of the brain. As a bucket, the brain appears static and as something merely to “fill up.” On the other hand, as a sponge, the brain appears more flexible with the ability to grow, expand, and adapt rather than merely contain. The incongruity of these metaphors perhaps represents the still-limited information Dickinson had on the brain. She is also unclear as to what this metaphorical water Lenkei 5 may be, what actually fills the brain—knowledge, experiences, memories, cultural influences, or some combination—but she clearly imagines the brain as a material organ capable of forming mental representations of both physical phenomena and the self. The last stanza turns from the material to the divine, illustrating her struggle with the role of spirituality in the brain and self. She writes, “The Brain is just the weight of God,” drawing on the tension between two popular ideas: the Biblical idea that man was created in God’s image and the humanist idea that man has psychological need of a God and so invents one (9). The difference between this weight, if they differ at all, Dickinson writes, is the difference between “Syllable” and “Sound” (12). Brunner argues that the fact Dickinson does not know if they will differ is significant and adds to her internal conflict regarding the possible divinity of the brain. She writes, “One part of her consciousness insists that the brain ‘will differ’ from the Holy, but some other part of her mind questions the equation and implies equivalence” (Brunner 4). Dickinson’s consistent ambiguity about whether the brain is completely material or somehow endowed by God suggests her deep conflict with these opposing ideas. By arguing that the “brain is just the weight of God,” she is effectively merging the two by implying a sense of equivalency. Dickinson also explores the conflict between a unified self that mental scientists uphold and a divided self that scientific advancements seem to suggest, and this poem appears to illustrate a self that seems whole. In the first stanza, Dickinson argues that the brain can “contain / With ease” the sky and “You—beside” (3-4). If the poem is read with the brain belonging to the addressee, then it shows that Dickinson locates the self, one that seems healthy, unified, and selfaware, explicitly in the brain. Furthermore, her portrayal of a self that seems whole and unified comes into conflict with later poems that stress division and fragmentation. Ultimately, Lenkei 6 Dickinson’s merging of materialist and spiritualist ideas signals her ability to negotiate between the two perspectives and perhaps offers a method for how neuroscience can approach conflicting ideas of the self. Dickinson’s “I felt a Funeral, in my Brain” is another poem that shows the poet’s conflict with ideas of materialism and spiritualism as well as fragmentation and cohesion. I felt a Funeral, in my Brain, And Mourners to and fro Kept treading - treading - till it seemed That Sense was breaking through And when they all were seated, A Service, like a Drum Kept beating - beating - till I thought My mind was going numb And then I heard them lift a Box And creak across my Soul With those same Boots of Lead, again, Then Space - began to toll, As all the Heavens were a Bell, And Being, but an Ear, And I, and Silence, some strange Race, Wrecked, solitary, here And then a Plank in Reason, broke, And I dropped down, and down And hit a World, at every plunge, And Finished knowing - then The location of the funeral illustrates that, for Dickinson, the brain is the site of activity for the self. Like the previous poem, Dickinson mediates between two popular ideas: a unified, healthy self and a fragmented self. But unlike “The Brain—is wider than the Sky,” this poem draws an important distinction between different parts of the self—the brain, mind, and soul—with the brain “containing” the two latter entities. These multiple entities, or multiple selves, are also reflected in the fact that there are multiple people, mourners, at the funeral. In Lyric Time: Lenkei 7 Dickinson and the Limits of Genre, Sharon Cameron suggests, “the mourners represent that part of the self which fights to resurrect or keep alive the thought the speaker is trying to commit to burial” (Cameron 97). This notion of multiple selves “contained” in the brain reflects Dickinson’s conflict with a unified and divided self as well as her efforts to merge them into what Kearns refers to as a “unitary ‘I,’” a self that can narrate its experiences by hearing and feeling the sensation of the funeral (Kearns 21). This poem also illustrates Dickinson’s struggle with merging materialism and spiritualism. While thinking of a material self, Dickinsons relies heavily on the body’s senses, and throughout this poem, there is a strong indication to suggest that these senses are central to the self. Not only is the narrator continuing to feel, hear, and think during the funeral despite the apparent death, but there are also a number of images that conjure up the senses, particularly sound—lead boots, tolling bells, creaking floorboards, and the drumming service. Later, “Being” is reduced to “an Ear” and, in “Silence,” the “I” becomes “Wrecked, solitary” (14-16). Since the brain is the interpreter of our senses, it follows that without them our idea of self breaks down. Other scholars, such as Katie Peterson in “Surround Sound: Dickinson’s Self and the Hearable,” have made similar connections between sense and self. “Stranded inside an overpowering moment of extreme sensation, Dickinson finds herself alone but deeply present to herself.” While “engaged in a dramatic relationship with Silence as its listener and its active interlocutor, she doubles herself even as she’s reduced herself to pure perceptual receptivity” (Peterson 76). The result, Peterson suggests, is a complete “collapse of the self into pure perception without personal history” (Peterson 76). Dickinson’s reliance on the body’s senses, and the self’s subsequent collapse without them, demonstrates the role of materialism in her idea of the self. Lenkei 8 In addition to this material perspective, Dickinson also relies on spiritual ideas such as the soul to form her idea of the self. Continuing with her funeral metaphor, Dickinson writes, “And then I heard them lift a Box / And creak across my Soul” (9-10). This line portrays the soul as the creaking floorboards of the funeral home, which may be interpreted as the foundation of the brain and possibly the self as well. The use of the term “soul” here is interesting to note because in an unedited draft she originally used “Brain” instead, but then ultimately crossed it out (Dickinson). While this may have simply been done for rhyming purposes, Dickinson clearly thought quite deeply about the brain, soul, and self and the revision may have more to do with a specific quality or function “Soul” has that “Brain” does not. Her use of “soul” shows how Dickinson still found value in the divine when her materialist views were limited. By having a material brain contain the soul, Dickinson effectively merges these conflicting ideas, and this collaborative technique may prove useful for uniting opposing ideas of the self in neuroscience. In “One need not be a Chamber—to be Haunted,” Dickinson extends her idea of the divided self by imagining multiple selves in conflict with one another. One need not be a Chamber—to be Haunted— One need not be a House— The Brain has Corridors—surpassing Material Place— Far safer, of a Midnight Meeting External Ghost Than its interior Confronting— That Cooler Host. Far safer, through an Abbey gallop, The Stones a'chase— Than Unarmed, one's a'self encounter— In lonesome Place— Ourself behind ourself, concealed— Should startle most— Assassin hid in our Apartment Be Horror's least. Lenkei 9 The Body—borrows a Revolver— He bolts the Door— O'erlooking a superior spectre— Or More— Here, Dickinson portrays a terrifying interior, indicating that the self is complex and perhaps even unknowable. Most notable is the way in which Dickinson conflates the material and spiritual. She writes, “The Brain has Corridors—surpassing / Material Place” (3-4). Here, Dickinson describes the brain as having physical corridors but notes that these pathways “surpass” materialism, implying that the brain has a metaphysical or spiritual component as well. This is a common technique Dickinson used in the previous two poems to merge the two conflicting ideas of materialism and spiritualism that were prevalent in her day. Perhaps more importantly, Dickinson’s depiction of a divided self in this poem conflicts with the more cohesive self found in “The Brain—is wider than the Sky” or “I felt a Funeral.” The poem’s multiple, or divided, selves seem to be at odds with one another. She parodies the Gothic form by arguing that typical Gothic images such as a “Midnight Meeting” or an “Abbey gallop” are “far safer” than meeting one’s self unarmed (5, 9). She writes of a “Cooler Host” and “a superior spectre” in our brains but clearly notes that it is “Ourself behind ourself, concealed” that “should startle most” (8, 13-14, 19). Furthermore, “the stanza… offers no judgement as to which [self] should be running the show, unlike the conviction of mental scientists that God intended the rational mind to be the highest expression of human development” (Kearns 23). By suggesting a self that is divided, Dickinson is continuing to break apart from the spiritualists who believe in a unified self. But despite this, she is still trying to include a sort of metaphysical or spiritual entity in her conception of the self, such as the “a superior spectre,” signaling her attempts to merge these opposing ideas (19). Lenkei 10 Two other Dickinson poems, “I felt a cleaving in my mind” and “The Brain, within its Groove, ” further emphasize the opposing ideas of a divided self and unified self as well as how Dickinson merged them. I felt a cleaving in my mind As if my brain had split; I tried to match it, seam by seam, But could not make them fit. The thought behind I strove to join Unto the thought before, But sequence ravelled out of reach Like balls upon a floor. The poem describes the sensation of a severed connection with an “I” attempting to “match” the disconnected thoughts “seam by seam” (3). Not only is the self split by the cleaving, but also by distinguishing between discrete entities such as the mind and the brain. By viewing the self as such, Dickinson broke away from the prominent beliefs of other thinkers in her lifetime such as Thomas Brown and Thomas Upham. The ambiguity of “behind” and “before” in the second stanza establishes a temporal and spatial displacement in which thoughts are separated. But for both Brown and Upham, this was impossible. They thought it was absurd to have a person who thought of him or herself as divided (Deppman 100). In addition, the very notion of a split brain suggests that it is typically whole, and the fact that there is an “I” narrating and recording the sensation of fragmentation implies the “unitary ‘I,’” Kearns refers to when discussing “I felt a funeral” (Kearns 21). Dickinson’s merging of these two opposing ideas in this way perhaps offers a method for how neuroscience can approach conflicting ideas of the self. Similar to other poems, “The Brain, within its Groove” explores Dickinson’s conflict between the two competing ideas of self: unified and divided. The Brain, within its Groove Lenkei 11 Runs evenly—and true— But let a Splinter swerve— 'Twere easier for You— To put a Current back— When Floods have slit the Hills— And scooped a Turnpike for Themselves— And trodden out the Mills— The opening lines reveal that the brain’s natural state is to “Run evenly—and true” (2). Such lines harken back to the mental capacities of the healthy, unified self in “The Brain—is wider than the Sky.” (3-4). Sielke notes that Dickinson’s image of the brain simply running along seems to give it a degree of agency, “living a life of its own,” that a divided self would lack, noting that it seems as “detached as Emerson’s eyeball” (Sielke 75). This idea of a unified self comes into conflict when Dickinson postulates the existence of a “Splinter” and notes that “You,” the reader, would have an easier time uniting flood waters back into a single current than connecting a splintered brain (3-4). The self that emerges from the “brain” of Dickinson’s poetry is characterized by her negotiation of two sets of ideas: materialism and spiritualism as well as unity and division. Reflecting the opposing ideas of her time, Dickinson’s poems offer conflicting views of whether the self is material or divine, and she resolves the dilemma by imagining a self in the material brain that is comprised of the body’s senses as well as the divine soul. Dickinson also mediates between whether the self was unified or divided, which she resolves by conceiving the brain as a container of sorts that could form a cohesive and unitary “I” out of the multiple selves she imagined. Dickinson’s blending of these opposing ideas allows her to arrive at a self that is layered and multifaceted, and this may be a model for how merging different theories of self in neuroscience can lead to a self that is similarly layered and complex. Lenkei 12 Though Dickinson appears to have been influenced by scientific conclusions to inform her developing ideas of a corporeal self, there is evidence to suggest that she was quite cognizant of its limits (Sielke 76). For example, Sielke writes, “For her, instruments that measure width, depth, and weight are as fallible as the scientific inquirer” (Sielke 73). But a closer examination reveals that Dickinson’s methods for uniting the opposing ideas in her poems may help neuroscience resolve conflicting theories of self within its field. Ultimately, these conflicting theories in neuroscience hinder progress because they lead to a narrow perspective. In “Imaging the Human Brain: Reflections on Some Emerging Issues,” Marcus Raichle notes, “both neurophysiologists and cognitive neuroscientists, because of the narrowness of the focus of their inquiry, have overlooked a major fraction of the functionally relevant activity in the brain” (Raichle 109). By borrowing Dickinson’s techniques of melding different ideas, neuroscience can conceive of a self that takes advantage of multiple perspectives and overcome its narrow focus. In the journal Nature Neuroscience, Thomas Insel advocates for a call to action in which he urges “collaboration, coordination and computation from a broad neuroscience community” to make “rapid progress in understanding the brain” (Insel 426). He advocates for “large-scale science,” using the Human Genome Project as a model, that can result in widespread advancements (Insel 426). Insel’s call for collaboration can be applied to the self in neuroscience where conflicting theories ultimately undermine the progress he seeks. Within neuroscience, there are a number of different theories regarding the precise nature of the self. Some neurologists, such as Gerald Edelman in his book titled, interestingly enough, Wider than the Sky, suggest that a self emerges only from a higher-order consciousness, which is the ability to be conscious of being conscious and the ability to conceptualize the past and future Lenkei 13 (Edelman 134). This is the self that most people tend to think of, one with beliefs, memories, and life history. It is a more reflective, “content-rich self” and is our “center of narrative gravity;” Antonio Damasio calls it our “autobiographical self” (Asma and Greif 28). In short, “we make ourselves… through the stories we tell ourselves” (Asma and Greif 29). By contrast, in “Affective Neuroscience and the Philosophy of Self,” Stephen Asma and Thomas Greif argue that the source of the self actually resides in primary consciousness, which is concerned with the present. Asma and Greif write, “The self accompanies the content of experience with something like an ‘awareness tone’—and this moment of self-awareness, this crystallization of subjectivity, is a ‘thin subject’ lacking ‘ontic depth.’ Each new activity—indeed each new moment—brings a new self” (Asma and Greif 27). Unlike Edelman and Damasio, they believe the self lies deeper in the brain. By arguing for an “archaic self” that is “based more on affectively rich action than rarefied intellectual reflection,” Asma and Greif suggest a self that includes emotions and a “biological notion of self-identity,” essentially rewriting Descartes’s famous line and claiming “I feel, therefore I am” (Asma and Greif 29). Other theories of self seem quite similar to Dickinson’s. The notion of multiple selves that was so prevalent in Dickinson’s poetry seem just as widespread among some neuroscientists. In “Reconsidering Self and Identity Through a Dialogue Between Neuroscience and Psychoanalytic Theory,” Michael Gerson argues that as research “moves toward greater specificity, the understanding of self has become parceled into more than two dozen subselves” (Gerson 214). He cites a number of scientists who have identified a facial self, verbal self, and emotional self, as well as selves that narrate and interpret our experiences (Gerson 214-215). Other neurologists have also noted the wide range of selves we may have by referring to the brain’s two hemispheres in split-brain patients. It is not uncommon for split-brain patients to Lenkei 14 experience a left hand that seems to have a will of its own, controlled by the nonlinguistic right brain. By examining a number of these cases, Hooper and Teresi in The Three-Pound Universe ponder, “If each hemisphere has an inner life… why does a single, imperious ‘I’ take credit for all our thoughts, beliefs, and actions?” (Hooper and Teresi 220). In one experiment on split-brain patients, researchers flashed the message “smile” on one screen and “frown” on another, and the patient tried to perform both actions at the same time, signaling how both hemispheres attempt conflicting actions without a unified “I” deciding which to do first. Harkening back to the conflicted selves in Dickinson’s “One need not be a Chamber,” Hooper and Teresi propose that the brain may actually consist of an “uneasy coalition of multiple subminds” (Hooper and Teresi 235). Without collaborating with other scientists who have different perspectives, these theories of self ultimately seem isolated and undermine progress with their narrow focuses. The first example of mediation that neuroscientists may look at is between the bodily and the divine. Although Dickinson merges the two ideas in her notion of selfhood, there is no such negotiation in neuroscience, since neuroscience typically disregards the soul and other divine entities as unnecessary for the existence of a self. But in “Science, Technology, and Emily Dickinson,” Christine Avery suggests that Dickinson’s commitment to including the divine in a material brain has value. “Though there is much complexity and imperfection in Emily Dickinson’s reaction to science… the viewpoint she unmistakably writes from has a comprehensiveness and validity which is both poetically and humanly valuable” (Avery 55). Although discussions of the soul and spirit may be inappropriate for neuroscience because such entities are not considered real, Dickinson’s strong commitment to closing the distance between disparate ideas may prove a beneficial technique since those who research the self often struggle to broaden their perspective and merge ideas from disciplines such as philosophy, psychology, Lenkei 15 and neuroscience. Such an interdisciplinary approach may yield surprising results as further research on the self is conducted. One neuroscientist who is merging these ideas and offering a new perspective of the self is Michael Gerson. His essay, “Reconsidering Self and Identity Through a Dialogue Between Neuroscience and Psychoanalytic Theory,” considers the self from the perspective of two different disciplines, which offers him a broader perspective than many other neuroscientists. Like Dickinson, he argues for the existence of multiple selves while still defining unity and continuity as primary characteristics of selfhood. Unity, Gerson says, “refers to feeling integrated and whole, as opposed to feeling fragmented, dissociated, or depersonalized” (Gerson 221). For Gerson, a unity of self is easily available through simple reflection and introspection. Continuity, on the other hand, is a “sense of ‘going-on-being’ wherein consciousness achieves a temporal dimension” (Gerson 222). Perhaps if other neuroscientists followed Gerson’s model of exploring self through a variety of different perspectives and disciplines, new ideas of the self may arise. The scientific fields that began during Dickinson’s lifetime culminated in a deeper search for self than she could have imagined. For both Dickinson and neuroscientists of the 21st century, the self is a complex entity, at times divided between multiple, conflicted selves, at times unified in an autonomous “I.” Even with advancements in science and technology, the answer to who and where we are, both in the universe and within ourselves, remain out of reach for the moment. But examining Dickinson’s negotiation between opposing ideas in light of the immense strides in neuroscience suggests ways our interrogation of the self can be expanded. By doing so, we move one step closer to uncovering the precise nature of selfhood. Lenkei 16 Works Cited Avery, Christine. “Science, Technology, and Emily Dickinson.” 1964. JSTOR. Web. 23 April 2014. Brunner, Elizabeth. “Dashing Genius: Emily Dickinson and the Punctuation of Cognition.” elizbrunner.tripod.com. Tripod. 1997. Web. 18 April 2014. Cameron, Sharon. Lyric Time: Dickinson and the Limits of Genre. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins UP, 1979. Print. Deppman, Jed. Trying to Think With Emily Dickinson. Amherst: U of Massachusetts P, 2008. Print. Dickinson, Emily. “On 280 (‘I felt a Funeral, in my Brain’).” Modern American Poetry. University of Illinois. n.d. Web. 20 April 2014. du Plock, Simon. “Emily Dickinson: Metaphorical Spaces and the Divided Self.” 2013. Academic Search Alumni Edition. Web. 10 April 2014. Edelman, Gerald M. Wider Than the Sky: The Phenomenal Gift of Consciousness. New Haven: Yale UP, 2005. Print. Gerson, Michael J. “Reconsidering Self and Identity Through a Dialogue Between Neuroscience and Psychoanalytic Theory.” Psychoanalytic Dialogues: The International Journal of Relational Perspectives 24.2 (2014): 210-226. Web. 16 April 2014. Hooper, Judith, and Dick Teresi. The Three-Pound Universe. New York: Dell, 1986. Print. lnsel, Thomas R., et all. “Limits to Growth: Why Neuroscience Needs Large-Scale Science.” Nature Neuroscience 7 (2004): 426-427. Web. 6 May 2014. Lenkei 17 Kearns, Michael. “Emily Dickinson: Anatomist of the Mind.” Emily Dickinson and Philosophy. Ed. Jed Deppman, Marianne Noble, Gary Lee Stonum. New York: Cambridge UP, 2013. Print. Peterson, Katie. “Surround Sound: Dickinson’s Self and the Hearable.” 2005. ProQuest. Web. 20 April 2014. Raichle, Marcus E. “Imaging the Human Brain: Reflections on Some Emerging Issues.” Developing Individuality in the Human Brain. Ed. Michael Posner, Ulrich Mayr, Edward Awh, and Steven W. Keele. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association, 2005. Print. Sielke, Sabine. “‘The Brain—is wider than the Sky’ or: Re-Cognizing Emily Dickinson.” The Emily Dickinson Journal 17.1 (2008): 68-85. Web. 9 April 2014.