* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Argument - University of Warwick
Transactionalism wikipedia , lookup
Argument from nonbelief wikipedia , lookup
Philosophy of space and time wikipedia , lookup
Private language argument wikipedia , lookup
Direct and indirect realism wikipedia , lookup
Watchmaker analogy wikipedia , lookup
List of unsolved problems in philosophy wikipedia , lookup
Philosophy in Practice Simon Scott Room S2.49 Email: [email protected] Critical reasoning lectures Reading: Kemp and Bowell, Critical Thinking: A Concise Guide, 2nd or 3rd edition. In course-handbook-speak: To equip you with the concepts and techniques required to identify, reconstruct, and evaluate arguments. In more down-to-earth-language: To make you better at assessing the attempts people make to persuade you to do/believe certain things, and to become better at it yourself. The first 3 lectures Lecture One: introduces you to some basic concepts required for assessing attempts to persuade: arguments, validity, soundness Lecture Two: equips you with the skills needed for identifying and reconstructing arguments. i.e., knowing how people are trying to persuade you Lecture Three: equips with the skills needed for evaluating arguments. i.e., knowing whether these attempts to persuade are any good. Good reasons? “You should take Philosophy at university. Why? Because the study of philosophy equips graduates with all sorts of analytical, critical, and verbal skills. Not only does this help them succeed at university, but it also makes them extremely attractive to potential employers: the civil service, banking, journalism, to name but a few. More generally, studying philosophy makes you smarter: there are numerous studies showing that philosophy students come out top along a whole host of parameters as compared to students from other subjects.” Tasks of the Critical Thinker Argument: the attempt to persuade by giving reasons. Two main tasks of the critical thinker: (a) Distinguish argumentative and non-argumentative attempts to persuade. (b) Assess whether arguments do in fact succeed in providing you with good reasons for believing/acting. Being able to do (a) and (b) means that you are a critical thinker. Arguments vs. unsupported claims One very basic skill in critical thinking is being able to differentiate arguments from unsupported claims... Arguments involve giving reasons. You can think of giving reasons as essentially providing support for the thing you are arguing for. So an argument will always involve at least one claim being offered in support of another claim; the former is to provide reasons for believing that the latter is true. Arguments vs. unsupported claims Here is an unsupported claim: “I think that gay marriage is something that should be between a man and a woman.” (Arnold Schwarzenegger, Aug 27th, 2003) Arguments vs. unsupported claims “Marriage should be between a man and a woman. Thousands of years of history and tradition underpin this principle. We should not ignore our heritage. Marriage is also a reflection of the biological necessity of one-to-one sexual union for procreation and the raising of children. Same sex-couples can’t have children.” (one of the standard arguments against gay-marriage) Key point: regardless of whether you think this is any good as an argument, there is at least an attempt being made to offer reasons. Arguments vs. unsupported claims “I’ve always opposed gay marriage. I believe that we should provide equal rights to people regardless of their sexual orientation but I do not believe that marriage should be between two people of the same gender.” (Mitt Romney, Jan 16th, 2012) Diagnosis: the ‘reasons’ being offered in support are essentially a restatement of the thing being argued for. A poor attempt to persuade. Arguments or unsupported assertions? (a)People who don’t support our operations in Iraq are unpatriotic and want our troops to fail. (unsupported) (b)Despite repeated attempts, no-one has ever come up with a proof of God’s existence. Hence, we can conclude that God doesn’t exist. (argument) (c)If we deal with the nation’s debt quickly and decisively then we will provide the basis for a more secure economic future. (unsupported) (d)Backwards time-travel is impossible. If it were at all possible then people from the future would have visited us. But as we all know, this has never happened. (argument) Arguments Arguments have two components: (i) The supporting claims (premises) (ii) The claim for which the supporting claims are being given (conclusion) This enables us to formulate a more precise definition of what an argument is: Argument: a set of propositions, one of which is the conclusion, and the remainder are premises. The premises are intended to support (provide reasons for) the conclusion. Propositions ‘The snow is white’ and ‘La neige est blanche.’ In more precise language: these sentences have the same factual content. That is, they both depict the world in a certain way that could be either true or false: depending on what colour the stuff is that falls in winter. The factual content = the proposition expressed by the sentence. Propositions Proposition: the factual content expressed by a declarative sentence (or utterance, if spoken), on a particular occasion. Propositions can be true or false. Different sentences can express the same proposition. (e.g., ‘The snow is white’ and ‘La neige est blanche’) The same sentence can express different propositions. (e.g., ‘I saw her duck’) Arguments A slightly more refined definition of an argument: Argument: Arguments are sets of propositions (which can be true or false), one of which is the conclusion, and the remainder are premises. The truth of the premises is intended to support the truth of the conclusion. Standard form The clearest way to set out an argument is to put it into what is called Standard Form. This involves setting out the premises in the order that the occur in the reasoning, and then the conclusion, with an inference bar separating the two (signifying therefore). P1: If backwards time travel were possible, then people would have come back from the future to visit us. P2: People haven’t come back from the future to visit us. --------------------------------------------------------------------------------C: Backwards time travel is impossible. standard form Note the contrast with: “Backwards time-travel is impossible. The reasons for thinking this are obvious. If it were at all possible then people from the future would have visited us. But as we all know, this has never happened.” - The move from this to the same argument in standard form is called a reconstruction. - Part of being a good critical thinker is being able to reconstruct arguments into standard form. Reconstructing an argument • • • • First, identify whether there is an argument(s) Identify the conclusion Identify the premises of the argument(s) Reconstruct the argument in standard form • • • • Number the premises and write them out in order Draw in the inference bar Write out the conclusion Evaluate the argument Descartes’ indivisibility argument “There is a great difference between the mind and the body, inasmuch as the body is by its very nature always divisible, while the mind is utterly indivisible. For when I consider the mind, or myself in so far as I am merely a thinking thing, I am unable to distinguish any parts within myself; I understand myself to be something quite single and complete… By contrast, there is no corporeal or extended thing that I can think of which in my thought I cannot easily divide into parts; and this very fact makes me understand that it is divisible. This one argument would be enough to show me that the mind is completely different from the body…” (Descartes, Meditations, Meditation 6) Descartes’ indivisibility argument P1: The mind is by its very nature indivisible. P2: The body is by its very nature divisible. --------------------------------------------------------------------------------C1: The mind and body have different properties. P3: X is identical to Y if, and only if, for any property had by X at time t, Y also has that property at time t (and vice versa). --------------------------------------------------------------------------------C2: The mind and the body are distinct. What makes a good argument? There are two ways in which an argument might succeed: 1. There might be a particularly tight connection between the supposed truth of the premises and the truth of the conclusion (related to the idea of the premises supporting the conclusion). 2. The premises are in fact true. Focus on (1) Deductive validity A more specific way of cashing out (1) is to say that a good argument will be deductively valid. Deductive Validity: an argument is deductively valid just in case it would be impossible for the premises to all be true but for the conclusion to be false. Alternatively: Deductive Validity: to say that an argument is deductively valid is to say that if the premises were all true, then the conclusion would have to be true. Both definitions amount to the same thing Deductive validity P1: The prime minister’s dog is infested with fleas. P2: All fleas are bacteria. -------------------------------------------------------------------C: The prime minister’s dog is infested with bacteria. Valid argument P1: Colette owned a dog. P2: All French bulldogs are dogs. ---------------------------------------------------------------------C: Colette owned a French bulldog. Invalid argument Invalidity Invalidity is just the negation of validity: Invalidity: an argument is invalid just in case it is possible for the premises to all be true and for the conclusion to be false. Alternatively: Invalidity: to say that an argument is invalid is to say that if the premises were all true, then the conclusion need not be true. Both definitions amount to the same thing.