
Section 3 - The Open University
... This shows that x + y is an even integer. We have seen that a sequence P, P1 , P2 , . . . , Pn , Q of statements forms a proof of the implication P ⇒ Q provided that each statement is shown to be true under the assumption that P is true. In Examples 3.3 and 3.4 each statement in the sequence was ded ...
... This shows that x + y is an even integer. We have seen that a sequence P, P1 , P2 , . . . , Pn , Q of statements forms a proof of the implication P ⇒ Q provided that each statement is shown to be true under the assumption that P is true. In Examples 3.3 and 3.4 each statement in the sequence was ded ...
On the greatest prime factor of n2+1
... the authors [1] investigated linear forms in Kloosterman sums S(/iQ,w;c) with the variables of the summation n, m and c counted with a smooth weight function, showing (see Lemma 3) that there exists a considerable cancellation of terms. In the paper we inject this result into the Chebyshev-Hooley me ...
... the authors [1] investigated linear forms in Kloosterman sums S(/iQ,w;c) with the variables of the summation n, m and c counted with a smooth weight function, showing (see Lemma 3) that there exists a considerable cancellation of terms. In the paper we inject this result into the Chebyshev-Hooley me ...
n - Read
... 8.2 Fermat’s and Euler’s Theorems Euler’s Totient Function Table 8.2 Some Values of Euler’s Totient Function (n) ...
... 8.2 Fermat’s and Euler’s Theorems Euler’s Totient Function Table 8.2 Some Values of Euler’s Totient Function (n) ...
2439 - Institute for Mathematics and its Applications
... Proof. We count the maximum number of possible crossings in an alternating 3-line drawing of Kn1 ,n2 ,n3 . There are two types of pairs of points that can result in crossings, (2,2) and (2,1,1), arising from choosing points partitioned among the partite sets as (2,2) and (2,1,1). Throughout this pro ...
... Proof. We count the maximum number of possible crossings in an alternating 3-line drawing of Kn1 ,n2 ,n3 . There are two types of pairs of points that can result in crossings, (2,2) and (2,1,1), arising from choosing points partitioned among the partite sets as (2,2) and (2,1,1). Throughout this pro ...
p. 1 Math 490 Notes 4 We continue our examination of well
... empty set φ is a well-ordered set (vacuously), and the ordinal containing φ is naturally denoted 0 (zero). Now consider all well-ordered sets with exactly n elements for some n ∈ N. It should be easy to see that all such well-ordered sets are similar to each other, and thus they all belong to the sa ...
... empty set φ is a well-ordered set (vacuously), and the ordinal containing φ is naturally denoted 0 (zero). Now consider all well-ordered sets with exactly n elements for some n ∈ N. It should be easy to see that all such well-ordered sets are similar to each other, and thus they all belong to the sa ...
Max Lewis Dept. of Mathematics, University of Queensland, St Lucia
... (This equation should be slightly modified if one of the primes is 2.) Obviously if (9) always held then k would be surjective. Unfortunately, an extra factor, F (M ), may also occur on the right hand side. For example, k(34 · 53 ) = 33 · 52 , but k(33 · 53 ) = 2 · 32 · 52 . Nonetheless, for any M w ...
... (This equation should be slightly modified if one of the primes is 2.) Obviously if (9) always held then k would be surjective. Unfortunately, an extra factor, F (M ), may also occur on the right hand side. For example, k(34 · 53 ) = 33 · 52 , but k(33 · 53 ) = 2 · 32 · 52 . Nonetheless, for any M w ...
Marian Muresan Mathematical Analysis and Applications I Draft
... The basic notion of set theory which was first introduced by Cantor1 will occur constantly in our results. Hence it would be fruitful to discuss briefly some of the notions connected to it before studying the mathematical analysis. We take the notion of a set as being already known. Roughly speaking ...
... The basic notion of set theory which was first introduced by Cantor1 will occur constantly in our results. Hence it would be fruitful to discuss briefly some of the notions connected to it before studying the mathematical analysis. We take the notion of a set as being already known. Roughly speaking ...
Chapter 5 - Stanford Lagunita
... from a conjunction of any number of sentences, any one of its conjuncts. This inference pattern is sometimes called conjunction elimination or simplification, when it is presented in the context of a formal system of deduction. When it is used in informal proofs, however, it usually goes by without ...
... from a conjunction of any number of sentences, any one of its conjuncts. This inference pattern is sometimes called conjunction elimination or simplification, when it is presented in the context of a formal system of deduction. When it is used in informal proofs, however, it usually goes by without ...
Chapter 4. Logical Notions This chapter introduces various logical
... and their paraphrases express the same propositions. On the nominalist conception, however, the tightness required of the paraphrase may depend on the purposes at hand. If we want to determine or explain, not merely whether an argument is logically valid, but why it is so, we might require that it a ...
... and their paraphrases express the same propositions. On the nominalist conception, however, the tightness required of the paraphrase may depend on the purposes at hand. If we want to determine or explain, not merely whether an argument is logically valid, but why it is so, we might require that it a ...
Intuitionistic Logic - Institute for Logic, Language and Computation
... may seem somewhat less natural then the other ideas, and Kolmogorov did not include it in his proposed rules. Together with the fact that statements containing negations seem less contentful constructively this has lead Griss to consider doing completely without negation. Since however it is often p ...
... may seem somewhat less natural then the other ideas, and Kolmogorov did not include it in his proposed rules. Together with the fact that statements containing negations seem less contentful constructively this has lead Griss to consider doing completely without negation. Since however it is often p ...
Chapter 4
... We very often encounter binary operations in mathematics, and nearly all of these are associative: addition, multiplication, composition etc. In this chapter we introduce a sufficiently abstract notion to deal with all such operations. 4.1. Definition of a Semigroup 4.1.1 Definition A semigroup is a ...
... We very often encounter binary operations in mathematics, and nearly all of these are associative: addition, multiplication, composition etc. In this chapter we introduce a sufficiently abstract notion to deal with all such operations. 4.1. Definition of a Semigroup 4.1.1 Definition A semigroup is a ...
Basic Metatheory for Propositional, Predicate, and Modal Logic
... than propositional logic, as it enables us to represent the much of the subsentential components of sentences — names, verb phrases, quantifiers, etc. This makes it possible to formally capture the validity of a huge number of arguments whose validity depends on the logical properties of these compo ...
... than propositional logic, as it enables us to represent the much of the subsentential components of sentences — names, verb phrases, quantifiers, etc. This makes it possible to formally capture the validity of a huge number of arguments whose validity depends on the logical properties of these compo ...
Document
... appears unattainable. In addition, whether computers can solve abstract and difficult mathematical problems and develop abstract mathematical theories such as those of mathematicians also appears unfeasible. Nevertheless, in seeking for alternatives, we can study what assistance mathematical softwar ...
... appears unattainable. In addition, whether computers can solve abstract and difficult mathematical problems and develop abstract mathematical theories such as those of mathematicians also appears unfeasible. Nevertheless, in seeking for alternatives, we can study what assistance mathematical softwar ...
Theorem
In mathematics, a theorem is a statement that has been proven on the basis of previously established statements, such as other theorems—and generally accepted statements, such as axioms. The proof of a mathematical theorem is a logical argument for the theorem statement given in accord with the rules of a deductive system. The proof of a theorem is often interpreted as justification of the truth of the theorem statement. In light of the requirement that theorems be proved, the concept of a theorem is fundamentally deductive, in contrast to the notion of a scientific theory, which is empirical.Many mathematical theorems are conditional statements. In this case, the proof deduces the conclusion from conditions called hypotheses or premises. In light of the interpretation of proof as justification of truth, the conclusion is often viewed as a necessary consequence of the hypotheses, namely, that the conclusion is true in case the hypotheses are true, without any further assumptions. However, the conditional could be interpreted differently in certain deductive systems, depending on the meanings assigned to the derivation rules and the conditional symbol.Although they can be written in a completely symbolic form, for example, within the propositional calculus, theorems are often expressed in a natural language such as English. The same is true of proofs, which are often expressed as logically organized and clearly worded informal arguments, intended to convince readers of the truth of the statement of the theorem beyond any doubt, and from which a formal symbolic proof can in principle be constructed. Such arguments are typically easier to check than purely symbolic ones—indeed, many mathematicians would express a preference for a proof that not only demonstrates the validity of a theorem, but also explains in some way why it is obviously true. In some cases, a picture alone may be sufficient to prove a theorem. Because theorems lie at the core of mathematics, they are also central to its aesthetics. Theorems are often described as being ""trivial"", or ""difficult"", or ""deep"", or even ""beautiful"". These subjective judgments vary not only from person to person, but also with time: for example, as a proof is simplified or better understood, a theorem that was once difficult may become trivial. On the other hand, a deep theorem may be simply stated, but its proof may involve surprising and subtle connections between disparate areas of mathematics. Fermat's Last Theorem is a particularly well-known example of such a theorem.