Download Ways of Learning about Leisure Meanings

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts

False consensus effect wikipedia , lookup

Social dilemma wikipedia , lookup

Albert Bandura wikipedia , lookup

Team composition wikipedia , lookup

Philosophy of experience wikipedia , lookup

Group dynamics wikipedia , lookup

Social perception wikipedia , lookup

Social tuning wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
Leisure Sciences, 22:93 – 107, 2000
Copyright ° C 2000 Taylor & Francis
0149-0400/00 $12.00 + .00
Ways of Learning about Leisure Meanings
MICHAEL WATKINS
School of Leisure Studies
GrifŽ th University
Nathan, Queensland, Australia
This article examines the epistemological claims made by four paradigms used to study
leisure meanings: behaviorism, cognitivism, individual constructivism, and social constructivism.These paradigms represent diverse and contrasting theoretical explanations
of how individuals gain knowledge about and give meaning to the phenomenon of leisure
and of how these meanings differ and change. Analysis of each paradigm illustrates limitations in their capacity to explain how individuals learn about leisure and suggests the
need for alternative explanations. Arguments are advanced in favor of an experientialist
paradigm characterized by a research specialization called phenomenography as an
additional and complementary theoretical approach to studying the multiple meanings
of leisure.
Keywords leisure meanings, leisure experiences, behaviorism, cognitivism, constructivism, phenomenography
The purpose of this article is to frame the analysis of leisure meanings within the discourse
of learning theory and to answer three questions:
1. How do individuals gain knowledge about and form a meaning of leisure?
2. How do individuals form different meanings of leisure?
3. How do individuals change their meanings of leisure?
These questions are based on two assumptions: Individuals form a meaning of leisure
from knowledge learned about the phenomenon, and individuals have the capacity to learn
different leisure meanings. Given the validity of these assumptions, it may be inferred that
various accounts of leisure meanings reported in the literature correspond with different
theoretical explanations of how individuals learn about leisure.
How individuals learn is an epistemological question in which attention is directed
toward determining not only the nature and sources of knowledge but also the strengths
and weaknesses of particular ways of knowing. To this end, four theoretical paradigms of
learning are described in terms of their respective accounts of learning and then illustrated
with examples drawn from research on leisure meanings. These paradigms are referred to as
behaviorism, cognitivism, individual constructivism, and social constructivism (after Bower
& Hilgard, 1981; Bredo, 1993; Marton & Booth, 1997; Reynolds, Sinatra, & Jetton, 1996).
Received 25 July 1999; accepted 14 January 2000.
The author wishes to thank Ference Marton from the University of Gothenburg, Sweden, and Ray Hibbins
from GrifŽ th University, Australia, for their insightful contributions during the preparation of the paper. A draft
version of the paper was presented at the Fourth Conference of the Australian and New Zealand Association for
Leisure Studies, University of Waikato, Hamilton, New Zealand, January, 1999.
Address correspondence to Michael Watkins, School of Leisure Studies, GrifŽ th University, Nathan,
Queensland 4111, Australia. E-mail: [email protected]
93
94
M. Watkins
Particular reference is made to the viability of the epistemological assumptions or claims
each paradigm makes in relation to the acquisition of knowledge and to their accounts of
difference and change in knowledge. Thus, the central question guiding this review is How
do individuals learn their meanings of leisure?
To foreshadow the answer to this question, I contend that the four paradigms provide
only partial explanations of how people learn about leisure. This problem suggests the need
to consider alternative explanations, and, subsequently, I present an additional paradigm
of learning as a possible way forward. This paradigm is referred to as the experientialist
paradigm and is characterized by a research specialization called phenomenography.
The approach adopted in this article contrasts with previous reviews that have typically
focused on methodological aspects of studying leisure meanings (e.g., Burton, 1996; Ellis
& Witt, 1991; Harper, 1981; Hemingway; 1995, Howe, 1990; Mannell, 1980; Mannell &
Iso-Ahola, 1987). Although these reviews have made important and varying contributions
toward analyzing the epistemological assumptions of methods used to study leisure, the
present review aims to complement and extend this work by analyzing the epistemological
claims of theories about how individuals learn to experience their meanings of leisure.
Given the a priori status of human experience over the methods used to study experience,
analysis of the formation of meanings as a learned experience represents a justiŽ ed and as
yet unreported approach toward clarifying some of the deŽ nitional issues surrounding the
study of leisure.
In presenting the review, the reader’s attention is drawn to several limitations. First,
although the paradigms represent major theoretical differences among various explanations
of learning, they are in fact composed of several related theories that sometimes overlap with
theories forming other paradigms. For example, some aspects of behaviorism are included
in some cognitivist theories, and some aspects of cognitivism are present in some constructivist theories (cf. Cobb, 1994; Overskeid, 1995). In this review, overlap is acknowledged
as evidence of the interrelatedness among paradigms and is dealt with by emphasizing
their essential differences while simultaneously viewing their existence as a coalition of
approaches that permit their respective epistemological foundations to be compared (after
Shaw, 1998).
Second, the process of linking a particular study of leisure meanings to a particular
paradigm requires the reviewer to interpret the theoretical basis of the study and to then
allocate it to a relevant paradigm. In some cases, this is readily achieved where researchers
have identiŽ ed the theoretical basis of their work. This process is limited in many cases,
however, given that much of the research on leisure meanings is either atheoretical or
theoretically ambiguous in nature. In these situations, my approach has been to make an
informed judgment about the theoretical orientation of a particular study, for example, by
analyzing the researcher’s vocabulary and by contrasting the purpose and results of the
study with similar and different studies.
A third limitation is that this review draws from Western intellectual traditions of
knowledge and as a result excludes non-Western ideas. Hultsman (1995) and Ibrahim (1982),
for example, have respectively offered Taoist and Islamic explanations and, in doing so,
have suggested how culturally divergent perspectives of leisure are based on different views
of intellectual thought. Although these and other explanations might provide a richer source
of comparison, their inclusion is beyond the scope of this article.
The Behaviorist Paradigm of Learning
Behaviorism can be traced to the ideas of empirical philosophers such as Locke (1690/1995)
and James Mill (1829) and to learning theories proposed by Thorndike (1931), Watson
(1924), and Skinner (1957), among others. The common theme among these scholars is
Learning about Leisure
95
that individuals acquire knowledge about a stimulus event through sensory experience
gained from external information sources (e.g., from family, friends, or the media) and by
associating the stimulus with a particular behavioral response. When behavior such as a
verbal response is repeatedly reinforced, it may become habitual to the point that the verbal
contents (i.e., the words) of the response infer meaning for the individual. Differences in
meaning are subsequently operationalized as variations in the content of verbal habits and
are attributed to different histories of reinforcement. Changes in meaning represent the
acquisition of a modiŽ ed set of verbal habits that enable individuals to comply with the
demands of their environments.
Behaviorist theory has received limited empirical attention from leisure researchers,
with the most notable contributions being made by Mobily (1989) and Mobily and Bedford
(1993). On the basis of Noble’s (1952) theory of association, Mobily interpreted a meaning
of leisure as the habit strength of words semantically associated with or used as synonyms
for a given stimulus word (e.g., leisure, play, or work). Response words associated with
leisure included fun, relaxing, sleeping, and TV, whereas work was related to terms such
as hard, money, labor, and cleaning. Although not using the word leisure, a comparison
of elderly male and female respondents’ verbal meanings of the word play in Mobily and
Bedford’s study indicated some minor but insigniŽ cant differences.
Although the strength of the behaviorist paradigm appears to be its ability to elaborate
the commonly held words used by individuals to denote leisure, behaviorist explanations
suffer from several weaknesses. Most important, the claim that meanings are acquired from
the environment and conditioned by external agents rejects the possibility that individuals
can learn through conscious thought or insight (Bredo, 1993). In effect, individuals are
portrayed as passive and compliant recipients who simply absorb ideas obtained from
external sources and respond uncritically to them (Reynolds et al., 1996). This view therefore
contrasts with alternative conceptions such as that individuals are independent and freethinking agents capable of generating their own existentially relevant meanings of leisure.
Furthermore, the failure of behaviorism to attribute the formation of meanings to individuals’ cognitive capabilities raises the issue of whether behaviorism is capable of discerning anything other than broad and superŽ cial differences in meanings. This issue is
highlighted by the fact that the paradigm cannot account for the semantic meanings of the
response words, nor for more deeply held psychological meanings (Bredo, 1993). Yet such
information may be necessary to distinguish subtle qualitative variations that can turn the
meaning of the word leisure into an evocation of pleasure and power on the one hand or of
boredom and powerlessness on the other hand.
The contention that repeated and therefore stable histories of reinforcement are required to form verbal habits limits the capacity of the paradigm to explain how meanings
might change in anything other than a kind of slow evolutionary process, and only then as
determined by the in uence of external agents. Although this may be how change operates,
the idea of forming habits reduces the possibility that meanings can change in response to
immediate short-term situational in uences or that individuals are capable of knowing how
to deŽ ne novel or ambiguous situations. These situations might occur when individuals
move into a new social group or when leisure is seen to overlap with other aspects of life
such as in work and family situations.
Finally, the application of the paradigm is based on the assumption that stimulus words
are used in everyday language and shared by all members of the community. However,
a number of leisure scholars have pointed out that the word leisure does not appear in
everyday language (e.g., Anderson, 1975; Burden, 1997), whereas others have questioned
its appropriateness in relation to particular social groups such as women and some nonAnglo subcultures (e.g., Chick, 1998; Wearing & Wearing, 1988). This assumption further
highlights limitations with using behaviorism to account for leisure meanings.
96
M. Watkins
The Cognitivist Paradigm of Learning
Whereas behaviorists have claimed that knowledge is acquired from ideas obtained outside
the individual, cognitive learning theorists have claimed that knowledge is acquired from
within the mind (e.g., Bruner, 1960; Chomsky, 1957; Simon, 1957). Individuals then use
this knowledge to help them make sense of phenomena that they initially take as being
unstructured or undifferentiated (Bower & Hilgard, 1981). Although cognitivists conceptualize knowledge in different ways (e.g., as personality dispositions, dimensions of contrast,
schemas, or rules), the contents of these mental representations are claimed to provide the
basis for determining the meanings of a phenomenon. According to Markova (1991), this
view is based on the rationalist philosophy of Plato and Descartes. Central to the ideas of
these philosophers is the claim that knowledge exists as an innate and eternal set of universal forms or essences in the mind of a person, in the environment (i.e., in the minds or
behaviors of other individuals), or in both. Differences in meaning can be realized in terms
of individuals possessing higher or lower amounts of a particular disposition or a more or
less developed set of dimensions, schemas, or rules and appear to be related to variations
in individuals’ genetic characteristics. Changes in meaning represent the acquisition of a
more universally accepted representation and attaining new knowledge by learning to apply
the representation to recognize similar and dissimilar phenomena.
Leisure meanings research exemplifying the cognitivist approach includes Neulinger’s
(1974) leisure paradigm, Iso-Ahola’s (1976, 1979) description of the in uence of personality
dispositions in forming leisure meanings, Mannell’s (1984) leisure as self-entertainment
concept, Weissinger and Iso-Ahola’s (1984) exposition of intrinsic motivation, and Ellis
and Witt’s (1986) Leisure Diagnostic Battery. Although it is somewhat harder to classify
the epistemological bases of empirical studies conducted by Pierce (1980); Unger and
Kernan (1983); Kleiber, Larson, and Csikszentmihalyi (1986); and Gunter (1987), these
authors’ respective characterizations of leisure appear consistent with the cognitivist goal
of locating a universal representation of leisure.
Iso-Ahola’s (1976, 1980) ideas are particularly relevant to consider as they provide an
extensive exposition of a cognitivist explanation of leisure meanings and re ect the work
of many earlier and contemporary leisure scholars. In proposing a theoretical basis for the
deŽ nition of leisure, Iso-Ahola drew on the work of attribution theorists (e.g., H. Kelly, 1973)
to suggest that individuals acquire knowledge about leisure on the basis of dispositional
characteristics that they attribute to their own behavior or observe in other individuals’
behavior. Iso-Ahola (1980) also asserted that deŽ nitions of leisure situations are determined
by a number of common dimensions that “hold true of people, situation and time” (p. 186)
and, elsewhere, that some aspects of social behavior are “universal and enduring” (p. 20).
For Iso-Ahola and many other cognitive researchers, these dispositions or dimensions are
identiŽ ed as perceived freedom of choice, intrinsic motivation, and perceived control or
competence (cf. Mannell & Kleiber, 1997). Thus, despite claiming to reject approaches
that aim to discover the generalizable and static characteristics of human behavior, and
while emphasizing the dialectical and changing nature of human beings, the essence of the
cognitivist’s claim seems to be that leisure meanings are largely innate and Ž xed.
By emphasizing the importance of the mind, cognitivism appears to offer a more
independent role for individuals with respect to learning about leisure meanings compared with behaviorism. Moreover, the success with which cognitivist researchers appear
to have achieved consistency in terms of conceptualizing and operationalizing the common
determinants of leisure situations adds credibility to their theoretical explanation. While
acknowledging the signiŽ cant body of knowledge built on these contributions, cognitive
explanations of leisure meanings are subject to a number of criticisms.
Learning about Leisure
97
By claiming to have identiŽ ed the common determinants of leisure, cognitivism offers an explanation of the antecedents that causally determine situations to be recognized
as leisure. However, this is not the same as deŽ ning the conceptual meaning of leisure
experiences per se. Moreover, although cognitivism adopts the view that individuals can
subjectively determine the meaning of particular situations, Dreyfuss (1972) pointed out
that the paradigm presupposes a Ž xed way of deŽ ning these situations at their base structure. Consequently, it is difŽ cult to understand how individuals can acquire their own unique
representations or negotiate or redeŽ ne the contents of their representations. Thus, like the
behaviorist, the cognitivist’s explanation is problematic because it too characterizes individuals as relatively compliant learners who take the meaning of leisure situations as being
initially deŽ ned.
The cognitivist paradigm also fails to explain where representations acquire their initial
semantic status. Put another way, if individuals obtain undifferentiated sense data in relation
to a situation and then use an already acquired internal representation to confer meaning
to that situation, then from where do the contents of the representation derive their original
meaning? The basis of the cognitivist position suggests that the derivation of leisure dimensions emanates from phylogenetic coding, either through direct inheritance or through the
absorption of ideas from other individuals and from there into the genes as naturally selected
dispositions. Although this may be a valid claim, the explanation highlights the cognitivist’s
propensity for ignoring the potential structuring in uences of immediate personal and social contexts on meanings. Furthermore, the claim also suggests that meanings might have
transhistorical properties that are independent of ongoing and broader cultural changes, a
point that is disputed by those who contend that meanings are socially conditioned and
historically situated (e.g., Hemingway, 1995; Rojek,1995).
If the claim that meanings are genetically determined is taken seriously, then the cognitivist explanation of differences in meaning implies that deŽ nitions of leisure situations are
largely invariant across human experience. More precisely, cognitivism can only logically
account for differences in numerical or quantitative terms, such as how much of a situation is
perceived to be like or unlike leisure or that members of one subgroup have higher or lower
levels of a particular disposition compared with another subgroup. The problem with this
explanation is that it offers a narrow conceptualization of difference by excluding the possibility that people can hold multiple representations of the same situation or that different
representations might be described as being qualitatively dissimilar (cf. Freysinger, 1995).
To change the meaning of a given situation (e.g., from leisure to nonleisure), an individual would need to select an appropriate representation in order to come to a decision about
the deŽ nition of that situation. How then do individuals know how to retrieve and apply
the correct representation? Some scholars have pointed out that conceptualizing knowledge
as a mental representation implies the need for a representation to handle the selection of
representations of a situation (e.g., Reynolds et al., 1996; Costall & Still, 1991). However,
this further implies the need for a representation to handle the representation that handles
the selection of representations of situations, and so on, ad inŽ nitum. This idea ultimately
leads to the questionable proposition that humans come equipped with a homunculus, or a
small human in the head, and that this entity operates the selection of an appropriate representation in much the same way as computers mindlessly process information according to
preestablished operating instructions.
The Individual Constructivist Paradigm of Learning
In comparison with behaviorism and cognitivism, individual constructivism proposes that
knowledge is not passively acquired from the outside world or implanted as an a priori
98
M. Watkins
representation in the mind but is constructed by the mind’s ability to actively explore and
develop its own meaningful accounts of phenomena. The source of knowledge is generated from individuals’ previous and concurrent interactions with their social and physical
environments and through their ability to reason about and symbolically transform these
interactions into personally constructed interpretations. Knowledge of a phenomenon is
subsequently represented as a conceptual or symbolic interpretation that conveys meaning for the individual. Differences in meaning are characterized as different interpretations
of the same phenomenon and are related to variations in individuals’ conceptual abilities.
Changes in meaning are understood as the ability to develop more complex interpretations
that Ž t with individuals’ changing needs.
The major theoretical contributions to this paradigm are found in Piaget’s (1983) genetic
epistemology, von Glasersfeld’s (1995) radical constructivism, the Mead-Blumer theory of
symbolic interactionism (Blumer, 1969; Mead, 1934), and George Kelly’s (1963) personal
construct theory. The philosophical basis of the paradigm has been attributed to ideas of
Hegel (Markova, 1991). It is worth mentioning some of Hegel’s key ideas as they help
to elaborate the individual constructivist paradigm, or what is sometimes called cognitive
constructivism, and to distinguish the paradigm from the traditional version of cognitivism
presented earlier.
Both the Platonic-Cartesian and Hegelian frameworks are based on the idea of universals, although universals are theoretically treated in quite different ways. As described
in the cognitivist paradigm, universals are static and eternal entities, generalizable across
individuals, and serve as the basis for determining the meanings of a phenomenon. In comparison, Hegel described universals as dynamic entities that are a product of interactions
between individuals; they can be both individually and collectively distributed, and they
correspond with the direct conceptual deŽ nitions of a phenomenon. From this latter perspective, individuals learn about a phenomenon by comparing it to other phenomena, and
there is no end point to development because they can learn new knowledge and consider
the phenomenon from other conceptual perspectives. Thus, whereas the Platonic-Cartesian
framework emphasizes learning as the process of discovering or recollecting eternal forms
of knowledge that are ontologically independent of the learner, the Hegelian view stresses
the development and agency of learners who ontologically evolve with changing forms of
knowledge that they themselves can create (Markova, 1991).
Empirical support for an individual constructivist interpretation of leisure meanings
appears in studies by Brook (1993); Lee, Datillo, and Howard (1994); Roadburg (1983);
Samdahl (1992); and Shaw (1985). For example, Shaw postulated the deŽ nition of leisure
as a mentalistic or subjective phenomenon that arises out of interaction and to be a function
of individuals’ capacities to symbolically transform or modify their interpretations of these
interactions. Shaw also asserted that meanings possess a dynamic quality for individuals in
that they can be redeŽ ned, but they may also be shared and represent a stable conŽ guration
for both an individual and groups within a society. The results of Shaw’s study demonstrated
that perceived choice, intrinsic motivation, enjoyment, relaxation, and lack of evaluation
were important dimensions deŽ ning leisure situations. Subgroup comparisons based on
the family structure, age, employment, and occupational status of the study respondents
indicated a high level of shared meaning.
By focusing on the individual’s role in making his or her own existentially relevant
meanings, individual constructivism suggests a tenable theoretical account of the formation
of meanings if one subscribes to the primacy of human agency over external or innately
determined sources of knowledge. Some critics, however, have pointed out that if knowledge
of a phenomenon is a product of an individual’s unique interpretation, then how is it possible
for one individual to truly know what another individual means when engaged in the act
Learning about Leisure
99
of communication (e.g., Gergen, 1995; Hardy & Taylor, 1997)? As suggested by Schwandt
(1994), the logical extension of this idea is that meanings are solipsistic constructions
belonging only to the individual constructor and cannot be intersubjectively shared (cf.
Glancy, 1993, for a counterexample to this argument).
Relying on sociodemographic comparisons to determine differences in meaning as
used in individual constructivist accounts of leisure is epistemologically inconsistent if
one accepts the claim that individuals interpret and make sense out of their own unique
experiences. Rojek’s (1995, p. 104) statement that “we cannot assume that all car workers
and waitresses see the world in the same way” and Burton’s (1996) caution against the
overuse of sociodemographic indices in leisure research highlight the nature of this problem
for individual constructivist explanations.
Additionally, some scholars (e.g., Gergen, 1995; Ogborn, 1997) have contended that
individual constructivism promotes the relativist position of democratizing different meanings such that one individual’s meanings are viewed as as good as any other and provides
no basis for being able to critically compare different meanings (Schwandt, 1994). On this
point, it is timely to recall the advice of the Greek philosopher Socrates in his deliberations
on the matter of relativism. According to Socrates, relativist views are intellectually intolerable because they lead to a confusion of thought and are morally reprehensible because
they provide no sense of direction as to what constitutes acceptable or useful ways to think
about, in this context, the meanings of leisure (cited in Guthrie, 1956).
In regard to changes in meaning, individual constructivism claims that individuals
continually redeŽ ne their deŽ nitions. However, the claim does not appear to be supported by
empirical studies of leisure meanings, which in fact suggest a high degree of shared meaning.
Marton and Booth (1997) argued that the problem is highlighted by the paradigm’s failure
to show how individuals learn to develop more complex meanings while still operating
with less developed meanings, if, as has been suggested, individuals do not have access to
others’ constructions in the Ž rst place.
The Social Constructivist Paradigm of Learning
Social constructivists emphasize the making of knowledge by communities of individuals
rather by individuals, as claimed by individual constructivists. Knowledge is viewed as
a collaborative intersubjective construction and is appropriated by individuals from the
socially organized practices of the group in which they participate (Cobb, 1994). Thus,
knowledge or meaning is embedded in participatory forms of social practice and is subject
to the structuring in uences of historical processes and sociocultural beliefs that surround
these practices. Differences in meaning are subsequently held to represent variations in
social practice and re ect different normative beliefs held by different groups. Changes in
meaning are associated with evolving social practices and indicate individuals increasing
enculturation in these practices.
Scholars contributing to this paradigm include situated learning theorists (e.g., Lave
& Wenger, 1991; Vygotsky, 1978), social constructionists (e.g., Gergen, 1995), feminist
scholars (e.g., Gilligan, 1982), and sociocultural scholars of varying theoretical persuasions
(e.g., Berger & Luckman, 1966; Foucault, 1974; Habermas, 1971). Schegloff (1991) identiŽ ed Durkheim’s notion of the “collective conscience” as providing an important source
of philosophical inspiration for this paradigm. This idea posits that social groups have cognitive properties that differ from those of its individual members and that these properties
act to bind members together and reinforce social order.
Leisure scholars including Clarke and Critcher (1985), Hamilton-Smith (1991),
Henderson (1994), John Kelly (1983, 1994), and Rojek (1995) have argued for the socially
100
M. Watkins
constructed nature of leisure meanings. J. Kelly’s (1994, p. 91) assertion that “leisure actors
have learned systems of meanings that re ect the dominant ideologies that serve class interests” is indicative of this approach. Studies of leisure meanings framed within this paradigm
elaborate on the function of broader cultural processes (e.g., capitalism) and describe how
these processes historically situate meanings (e.g., within an ideology of consumption).
Moreover, they tend to focus on speciŽ c examples of social practices (e.g., power relationships among groups of individuals) in order to demonstrate how meanings are used to
promote or resist sexism, ageism, or racism within these groups.
Empirical support for social constructivist explanations of leisure meanings exists
in studies by Freysinger (1995), Rapoport and Rapoport (1975), and Wearing (1990).
Freysinger’s study exempliŽ es the general tenets of the paradigm by locating leisure meanings within the socially constructed arena of age and gender and in practices of afŽ liation
(e.g., interacting with others) and agency (self-determining forms of experience). Although
Freysinger adopted the explicit stance of recognizing the existence of individual differences
in meaning, the study described a single multidimensional model that depicted the commonality of leisure across the study sample. This depiction described leisure as an experience
of change that was freely chosen and that provided feelings of relaxation, enjoyment, and
rejuvenation.
Although the social constructivist paradigm has made important advances in understanding the historical and sociocultural qualities of leisure meanings, the paradigm has
been subject to a number of criticisms. For example, individual meanings tend to disappear
in favor of collective meanings, which, as Bredo (1993) suggested, fails to acknowledge
that individuals can have meaning-making experiences in multiple and often con icting
communities. Ogborn (1997) contended that this problem is reinforced by the paradigm’s
emphasis on the social making of meanings and its tendency to understate individual modeling, Ž nding or interpreting metaphors of gaining knowledge. Although a collective may
experience a change in the meaning of social practice, the claim that change occurs in
a structuring process of normative beliefs assumes each individual sees these in uences
and responds to them in the same way as do others. This raises the idea of social determinism, a position that theoretically parallels the behaviorist’s contention that meaning is
environmentally determined.
Problems with the Coalition of Paradigms
Although the respective paradigms provide different and competing explanations of how
people learn about leisure, when viewed as a coalition of approaches each paradigm contributes a viable and important explanation for some particular aspect of meaning that is
unaccounted for by other paradigms. Thus, behaviorism produces linguistic accounts of the
everyday words used to denote leisure, and cognitivism identiŽ es the common and underlying dispositional tendencies that cause situations to be represented as leisure. Individual
constructivism, on the other hand, emphasizes individuals’ conceptual interpretations of the
meaning of these situations, whereas social constructivism suggests how these meanings
are historically and socioculturally structured. To rephrase Shaw’s (1998) contention, it is
as if the coalition of paradigms serves as the background against which each respective
paradigm can be foregrounded and understood in terms of its speciŽ c contribution.
However, treating the paradigms as a coalition of approaches highlights four common problems that appear to be fundamentally linked to resolving questions about leisure
meanings. First, the nature of knowledge or the units of description conceptualized by each
paradigm (i.e., as verbal habits, mental representations, conceptual interpretations, or social
practices) do not focus on the phenomenon of leisure as experienced by individuals. Instead,
Learning about Leisure
101
they focus on the researchers’ prescriptive theorizing about how people might experience
leisure, for example, as forming habits, mental representations, and so on (cf. Sylvester,
1987). The extent to which one or another unit of description can be claimed as being
any more or less viable is overshadowed by the absence of a theoretical explanation of
learning about leisure that takes the individual’s life world experience as the primary unit
of description.
Second, the coalition of paradigms is based on an outmoded dualistic conception of
the individual– world relationship as indicated by their explanations as to the source of
knowledge about leisure meanings (cf. Burton, 1996; Searle, 1992). Both cognitivism and
individual constructivism are similar in that they claim knowledge is acquired from within
the individual’s mind and thus they downplay the in uence of the social world. Behaviorism
and social constructivism do the opposite by claiming that knowledge is gained from the
outside world, and subsequently they downplay the role of individuals’ mental processes.
The implication of this view is that once individuals and the world are seen to exist as
two separate realities, they cannot be philosophically reunited (Marton & Booth, 1997).
Thus, the two dominant traditions in leisure meanings research—that leisure is subjectively
determined or, alternatively, that leisure is socially constructed—commit their respective
proponents to maintaining a philosophical dilemma that has remained unanswered since
Socrates Ž rst grappled with the issue in the Meno some 2,500 years ago.
Third, although differences in meaning are theoretically attributed to variations in
reinforcement histories, genetic inheritances, conceptual abilities, or normative beliefs,
the subsumption of these factors to individuals’ sociodemographic status maintains the
questionable proposition that all members of a particular subgroup share the same meanings
of leisure. However, not only do sociodemographic variables turn out to be somewhat
insensitive to predicting interindividual difference in meanings (e.g., Donald & Havighurst,
1959; Iso-Ahola, 1979; Kleiber, Caldwell, & Shaw, 1993; Shaw, 1985; Unger & Kernan,
1983), but they also fail to illuminate intraindividual differences.
The fourth and Ž nal problem concerns the ability of the paradigms to account for
changes in meaning. The primary concern lies in the fact that different forms of knowledge represented by the paradigms (i.e., as habits, dispositions, interpretations, or social
practices) can be difŽ cult to change. Moreover, if individuals’ meanings are sociodemographically related, then this logically implies that individuals would have to change their
sociodemographic status in order to change their meanings of leisure. Although individuals do experience change in their personal and social circumstances, the capacity of the
paradigms to describe the dynamics of change is particularly problematic.
In summary, if the descriptions of the paradigms are accepted as a reasonable summation
of their fundamental epistemological claims, limitations associated with these paradigms
indicate the need for additional explanations that address four areas. These are theoretical explanations of leisure meanings that (a) incorporate an experientialist perspective, (b) adopt a
nondualist view of the individual– world relationship, (c) are sensitive to individual and collective differences, and (d) are responsive to capturing the dynamics of change in meaning.
The Potential Contribution of an Experientialist Paradigm
In response to perceived limitations with existing theoretical accounts of learning, phenomenography has been advocated as an alternative approach to explain learning (Marton,
1981, 1986, 1996; Marton & Svensson, 1979). Phenomenography was initially developed as
a research specialization for mapping the qualitatively different ways that people experience
the meaning of aspects of their world. More recent developments have seen the approach
extended to incorporate a theoretical account of learning (cf. Marton & Booth, 1997) that
is consistent with what is referred to in this article as the experientialist paradigm.
102
M. Watkins
According to this paradigm, knowledge is viewed as an experience of the relationship
formed between an individual and some aspect of his or her world (e.g., the phenomenon
of leisure). The relationship is internal in the sense that it is established or constituted in
the individual’s awareness as an individual– world relationship and conveys meaning for
the individual. Philosophers such as A. N. Whitehead (1929) and Birch (1995) used the
term internal relation to describe this relationship and claimed that when individuals take
account of the relationship they have direct access to the feelings experienced in relation to
that aspect; that is, they experience an internal relation. Internal relations can therefore be
considered as the basic units of awareness or, in Whitehead’s language, as actual occasions
of experience.
The source of an individual’s knowledge or experience of a phenomenon is gained
through participating in the constitution of situations in which the phenomenon is present.
This suggests that knowledge is acquired as Heidegger (1962) proposed, through being
in the world, in which case individuals not only experience their own understandings of
a phenomenon as argued by the cognitivists and individual constructivists, but also share
others’ understandings as contended by the behaviorists and social constructivists. However,
this is theoretically different from claiming that individuals discover an independent reality
or construct a private reality within their own self or that they adopt behaviors or appropriate
practices from an already established world. Consequently, the experientialist paradigm does
not address how knowledge is gained from within the mind or how knowledge is gained
from the world, but rather posits the existence of internal relations as part of the individual’s
ongoing constitution of the world. By understanding the individual and the world as being
internally related, the paradigm adopts a nondualist perspective of there being one world, the
world as it is experienced by individuals. Free from dualism, the experientialist paradigm
focuses on how individual – world relations differ and change (Marton, 1996).
In describing the nature of consciousness, Gurwitsch (1964, p. 4) advanced the idea
that the object of attention or “that which engrosses the mind of the experiencing subject”
stands to the fore of, and is embedded in, a background of contextual factors. These factors
may alter over time and provide the object with its particular qualitative character. According to this idea, differences in awareness are understood as contextually related shifts in
the Ž gure – ground relationship. The experientialist paradigm draws on this idea to represent
different meanings of a phenomenon as different ways of experiencing the individual– world
relationship and of re ecting variations in both the content and the structure of the relationship at a particular point in time. The content of the relationship refers to the aspects
or parts focal in the individual’s awareness of the phenomenon. Although individuals are
not consciously aware of the different parts, they are argued to be aware of the wholelike
quality of the experience that is formed by the parts. Thus, the content of the relationship
translates into the literal meaning of the phenomenon; that is, what the phenomenon means
to the individual. The structure of the relationship describes how the parts are understood,
how the parts are related or temporally organized in awareness, and how the phenomenon
is differentiated from its background context and from other phenomena (Svensson,as cited
in Marton, 1986). This aspect of the relationship, then, refers to how the meaning is experienced or understood by the individual. By adding a structural component to the content
of experience, the experientialist paradigm provides a theoretical framework in which to
situate empirical descriptions of qualitative differences in individual– world relationships,
both within the same individual and between different individuals. Such an approach is
therefore argued to be sensitive to describing variations and to reduce the need to rely on
sociodemographic variables as the primary method for determining differences in meaning.
At this point, it is timely to ask if the individual– world relationships constituted in
awareness are relative to the knowledge of individuals such that there can exist an inŽ nite
Learning about Leisure
103
number of ways of experiencing a phenomenon, or whether such relationships are perhaps limited in number? The experientialist paradigm proposes that the number of ways
of knowing about a phenomenon is potentially inexhaustible due to individuals’ ongoing
constitution of the world, no matter how little or how much, from birth until death. However,
the capacity of individuals to know about a phenomenon is also limited by two pragmatic
conditions. The Ž rst is that individuals are constrained in their ability to be focally aware of
all the possible ways of experiencing a phenomenon. Indeed, if individuals were aware of
all there is to know about a phenomenon, then meaning would logically cease to exist as it
is rendered from there being different ways of understanding the phenomenon. The second
reason is that individuals share common social contexts and can therefore be expected to
constitute similar experiences of phenomena that emerge from these contexts. Thus, the two
seemingly contradictory conditions, difference and commonality in experience, are argued
to restrict knowledge about phenomena to a limited but not Ž nite number of meanings.
Given that meanings are limited, the experientialist paradigm makes the further claim
that different experiences of these meanings can be understood as an interrelated and logically ordered continuum of experience. The justiŽ cation for positing the interrelated nature
of experience is based on the contention that different combinations of the same constituent
parts appear in different experiences of the phenomenon (Marton, 1996). However, this
does not mean that all individuals are capable of sharing exactly the same experiences.
In other words, individuals within a given population cannot be expected to share a web
of common meanings (cf. Hemingway, 1995), but, more accurately, they can be expected
to share an experiential Ž eld of differentially constituted meanings. As argued by Marton
and Booth (1997), this means that experiences can be ordered according to the increasing
complexity with which different ways of experiencing the phenomenon can be deŽ ned as
subsets of more or less inclusive or complex ways of being aware of the phenomenon. More
complex experiences accord with the ability to simultaneously discern and hold in awareness more parts or more ways of experiencing the phenomenon. In contrast, less complex
experiences are partial representations in which fewer parts or fewer ways of experiencing the phenomenon are discerned in awareness. However, the ordering of experience on
a continuum implies more than simply determining the degree of complexity apparent in
particular experiences. It also implies making value judgments about the relative worth of
experience and stating what it is about complex experiences that make them more desirable than less complex experiences. Such judgments cannot rely on objective propositions
of truthfulness, but need to be argued for using criteria that are relevant to the subjective
context of the particular situation.
Subsequently, in response to questions about how individuals learn their meanings of
leisure, the experientialist paradigm claims that learning occurs when individuals experience
change in the content and structure of the internal relations formed between themselves and
the phenomenon of leisure. Learning so described means that individuals have developed a
capability for being able to hold more aspects of leisure or more ways of experiencing leisure
in their awareness than they were capable of at some previous point in time. When viewed
from this perspective, different ways of experiencing leisure correspond with changes in
individuals’ ways of seeing the individual –world relationship. Inasmuch as these changes
are seen by individuals against the background of their life worlds, changes in the meaning
of leisure are held to be re ective of, and responsive to, changes in individuals’ life worlds
in general. These changes may also be understood as layers of experience that indicate
increasingly complex ways of experiencing leisure. Consequently, an empirical investigation of leisure meanings framed by the experientialist paradigm would seek to identify and
describe a limited number of experiences. These descriptions would aim to deŽ ne the meanings of the parts that form the experiences, illustrate the arrangement of parts in differing
104
M. Watkins
patterns of temporal awareness, depict differing relations between leisure and other aspects
of life, and demonstrate how leisure experiences are interrelated and ordered according to
their complexity.
Conclusion
In conclusion, the experientialist explanation of gaining knowledge about and giving meaning to leisure allows us to view individuals as bearers of different experiences rather than
as behaviorist impersonators, bearers of mental representations, or individual or social actors as implied by each of the previously described paradigms. By focusing on the content
and structure of experience, the experientialist paradigm draws from and complements the
cognitivist’s and individual constructivist’s concern with the inner content of experience,
as well as the behaviorist’s and social constructivist’s concern with the outer structuring
of experience. However, it does so in a way that avoids separating people from the phenomenon and the context within which they and the phenomenon are situated. Finally, the
experientialist paradigm complements the existing coalition of approach by providing an
approach to generating descriptions of difference and change in leisure meanings that can
be compared and contrasted in terms of their complexity of experience.
References
Anderson, J. (1975). Leisure: an inappropriate concept for women? Canberra, Australia: Australian
Government Publishing Service.
Berger, P., & Luckman, T. (1966). The social construction of reality. Garden City, NY: Doubleday.
Birch, C. (1995). Feelings. Sydney, Australia: New South Wales University Press.
Blumer, H. (1969). Symbolic interactionism: Perspective and method. Berkeley: University of
California Press.
Bower, G., & Hilgard, E. (1981). Theories of learning. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Bredo, E. (1993). The social construction of learning. In G. Phye (Ed.), Handbook of academic
learning: The construction of knowledge (pp. 3– 45). London, England: Academic.
Brook, J. (1993). Leisure meanings and comparisons with work. Leisure Studies, 12, 149– 162.
Bruner, J. (1960). The process of education. New York: Vintage.
Burden, J. (1997). Living life to the full: A qualitative study of community theatre, older people
and the construction of leisure. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, GrifŽ th University, Brisbane,
Queensland, Australia.
Burton, T. (1996). Safety nets and security blankets: False dichotomies in leisure studies. Leisure
Studies, 15, 17–30.
Chick, G. (1998). Leisure and culture: Issues for an anthropology of leisure. Leisure Sciences, 20,
111 –133.
Chomsky, N. (1957). Syntactic structures. The Hague, the Netherlands: Mouton.
Clarke, J., & Critcher, C. (1985). The devil makes work: Leisure in capitalist Britain. London:
Macmillan.
Cobb, P. (1994). Where is the mind? Constructivist and socio-cultural perspectives on mathematical
development. Educational Researcher, 23(7), 13– 20.
Costall, A., & Still, A. (1991). Introduction: Cognitivism as an approach to cognition. In A. Still &
A. Costall (Eds.), Against cognitivism: Alternative foundations for cognitive psychology (pp.
1– 7). New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf.
Donald, M., & Havighurst, R. (1959). The meanings of leisure. Social Forces, 37, 355 –360.
Dreyfuss, H. (1972). What computers can’t do. New York: Harper Row.
Ellis, G., & Witt, P. (1986). The leisure diagnostic battery: Past, present and future. Therapeutic
Recreation Journal, 20, 31– 47.
Ellis, G., & Witt, P. (1991). Conceptualisation and measurement of leisure: Making the abstract
concrete. In T. Goodale & P. Witt (Eds.), Issues in an era of change (pp. 377 –393). State College,
PA: Venture.
Learning about Leisure
105
Foucault, M. (1974). The archaeology of knowledge. London: Tavistock.
Freysinger, V. (1995). The dialectics of leisure and development of women and men in mid-life: An
interpretive study. Journal of Leisure Research, 27, 61–84.
Gergen, K. (1995). Social constructionism and the education process. In L. P. Steffe & T. Wood,
Constructivism in education (pp. 17–37). New Jersey: Erlbaum.
Gilligan, C. (1982). In a different voice: Psychological theory and women’s development. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Glancy, M. (1993). Achieving inter-subjectivity: The process of becoming the subject in leisure
research. Leisure Studies, 12, 45– 59.
Gunter, B. (1987). The leisure experience: Selected properties. Journal of Leisure Research, 19,
115 – 130.
Gurwitsch, A. (1964). The Ž eld of consciousness. Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press.
Guthrie, W. (1956). Plato: Protagoras and Meno. Middlesex, England: Penguin.
Habermas, J. (1971). Knowledge and human interests. London: Heineman.
Hamilton-Smith, E. (1991). The construction of leisure. In B. Driver, P. Brown, & G. Peterson (Eds.),
BeneŽ ts of leisure (pp. 445– 450). State College, PA: Venture.
Hardy, M., & Taylor, P. (1997). Von Glasersfeld’s radical constructivism: A critical review. Science
and Education, 6(1– 2), 135 – 150.
Harper, W. (1981). The experience of leisure. Leisure Sciences, 4, 113– 126.
Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and time (J. Macquarrie & E. Robinson, Trans). New York: Harper-Rowe.
Hemingway, J. (1995). Leisure studies and interpretive inquiry. Leisure Studies, 14, 32– 47.
Henderson, K. (1994). Perspectives on analysing gender, women and leisure. Journal of Leisure
Research, 26, 1– 7.
Howe, C. (1990). Possibilities for using a qualitative research approach in the sociological study of
leisure. Journal of Leisure Research, 17, 212– 224.
Hultsman, J. (1995). Spelling leisure. Leisure Studies, 14, 87– 101.
Ibrahim, H. (1982). Leisure and Islam. Leisure Studies, 1, 197 –210.
Iso-Ahola, S. (1976). On the theoretical link between personality and leisure. Psychological Reports,
39, 3–10.
Iso-Ahola, S. (1979). Basic dimensions of deŽ nitions of leisure. Journal of Leisure Research, 11,
28– 39.
Iso-Ahola, S. (1980). The social-psychology of leisure and recreation. Dubuque, IA: Wm. C. Brown.
Kelly, G. (1963). A theory of personality: The psychology of personal constructs. New York: Norton.
Kelly, H. (1973, February). The process of causal attribution. American Psychologist, 107 – 128.
Kelly, J. (1983). Leisure identities and interactions. London: Allen & Unwin.
Kelly, J. (1994). The symbolic interaction metaphor and leisure: Critical challenges. Leisure Studies,
13, 81– 96.
Kleiber, D., Caldwell, L., & Shaw, S. (1993). Leisure meanings in adolescence. Society and Leisure,
16(1), 99– 114.
Kleiber, D., Larson, R., & Csikszentmihalyi, M. (1986). The experience of leisure in adolescence.
Journal of Leisure Research, 18, 169 – 176.
Lave, J., & Wenger, E. (1991). Situated learning: Legitimate peripheral participation. Cambridge,
England: Cambridge University Press.
Lee, Y., Dattilo, J., & Howard, D. (1994). The complex and dynamic nature of leisure experience.
Journal of Leisure Research, 26, 195 – 212.
Locke, J. (1995). An essay concerning human understanding. New York: Prometheus. (Original work
published 1690)
Mannell, R. (1980). Social psychological techniques and strategies for studying leisure experience. In
S. E. Iso-Ahola (Ed.), Social psychological perspectives in leisure and recreation (pp. 62– 90).
SpringŽ eld, IL: Charles C Thomas.
Mannell, R. (1984). Personality in leisure theory: The self as entertainment construct. Society and
Leisure, 7, 229– 240.
Mannell, R., & Iso-Ahola, S. (1987). The psychological nature of leisure and tourism experience.
Annals of Tourism Research, 14, 314 – 331.
Mannell, R., & Kleiber, D. (1997). A social-psychology of leisure. State College, PA: Venture.
106
M. Watkins
Markova, I. (1991). The concepts of the universal in the Cartesian and Hegelian frameworks. In
A. Still & A. Costall (Eds.), Against cognitivism: Alternative foundations for cognitive psychology (pp. 81– 101). New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf.
Marton, F. (1981). Phenomenography: Describing conceptions of the world around us. Instructional
Science, 10, 177 – 200.
Marton, F. (1986). Phenomenography: A researchapproach to understanding different understandings
of reality. Journal of Thought, 21, 28– 49.
Marton, F. (1996). Cognosco ergo sum: Re ections on re ections. In G. Dall’Alba & B. Hasselgren
(Eds.), Re ections on phenomenography (Gothenburg Studies in Educational Sciences No. 109,
pp. 163 –187). Gothenburg, Sweden: Department of Education and Educational Research.
Marton, F., & Booth, S. (1997). Learning and awareness. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Marton, F., & Svensson, L. (1979). Conceptions of research in student learning. Higher Education,
8, 471 – 486.
Mead, G. (1934). Mind, self and society: From the standpoint of the social behaviorist. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Mill, J. (1829). Analysis of the phenomenon of the human mind. London: Baldwin & Cradock.
Mobily, K. (1989). Meanings of recreation and leisure among adolescents. Leisure Sciences, 8, 11– 23.
Mobily, K., & Bedford, R. (1993). Language, play and work among elderly persons. Leisure Studies,
12, 203 –219.
Neulinger, J. (1974). The psychology of leisure. SpringŽ eld, IL: Charles C Thomas.
Noble, C. (1952). An analysis of meaning. Psychological Review, 59, 421 – 430.
Ogborn, J. (1997). Constructivist metaphors of science learning. Science and Education, 6, 121– 133.
Overskeid, G. (1995). Cognitivist or behaviorist: Who can tell the difference? The case of implicit
and explicit knowledge. British Journal of Psychology, 86, 517 –522.
Piaget, J. (1983). Piaget’s theory. In P. H. Mussen (Ed.), Handbook of child psychology (pp. 103 –128).
New York: Wiley.
Pierce, R. (1980). Dimensions of leisure 111: Characteristics. Journal of Leisure Research, 12, 273 –
283.
Rapoport, R., & Rapoport, R. N. (1975). Leisure and the family life cycle. London: Routledge &
Kegan Paul.
Reynolds, R., Sinatra, G., & Jetton, T. (1996). Views of knowledge acquisition and representation:
A continuum from the experience centred to mind centred. Educational Psychologist, 3(2), 93–
104.
Roadburg, A. (1983). Freedom and enjoyment: Disentangling perceived leisure. Journal of Leisure
Research, 15, 15–26.
Rojek, C. (1995). Decentring leisure: Rethinking leisure theory. London, England: Sage.
Samdahl, D. (1992). Leisure in our lives: Exploring the common leisure occasion. Journal of Leisure
Research, 24, 19–32.
Schegloff, E. (1991). Conversation analysis and socially shared cognition. In L. Resnick, J. Levine,
& S. Teasley (Eds.), Perspectives on socially shared cognition (pp. 150 –171). Washington, DC:
American Psychological Association.
Schwandt, T. (1994). Constructivist and interpretivist approaches to human inquiry. In N. Denzin &
Y. Lincoln (Eds.), Handbook of qualitative research (pp. 105 –107). London: Sage.
Searle, J. (1992). Rediscovery of the mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Shaw, S. (1985). The meaning of leisure in everyday life. Leisure Sciences, 7, 1– 24.
Shaw, S. (1998). Cultural determination, diversity, and coalition in leisure research: A commentary
on Coalter and Mommaas. Leisure Sciences, 19, 277 –279.
Simon, H. (1957). Models of man. New York: Wiley.
Skinner, B. F. (1957). Verbal behavior. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Sylvester, C. (1987). The ethics of play, leisure and recreation in the twentieth century, 1900 –1983.
Leisure Sciences, 9, 173– 188.
Thorndike, E. (1931). Human learning. New York: Century.
Unger, L., & Kernan, J. (1983). On the meaning of leisure: An investigation of some determinants of
the subjective experience. Journal of Consumer Research, 9, 381 – 392.
Learning about Leisure
107
von Glasersfeld, E. (1995). A constructivist approach to teaching. In L. P. Steffe & T. Wood (Eds.),
Constructivism in education (pp. 3– 16). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Vygotsky, L. (1978). Mind in society: The development of higher psychological processes. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Watson, J. (1924). Behaviorism. New York: Norton.
Wearing, B. (1990). Beyond the ideology of motherhood: Leisure as resistance. Australian and New
Zealand Journal of Sociology, 26(1), 36– 58.
Wearing, B., & Wearing, S. (1988). All in a day’s leisure: Gender and the concept of leisure. Leisure
Studies, 7, 111 – 123.
Weissinger, E., & Iso-Ahola, S. (1984). Intrinsic leisure motivation, personality and physical health.
Society and Leisure, 7, 217 – 228.
Whitehead, A. N. (1929). Process and reality. New York: Free Press.