Survey
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Business Ethics: A European Review Individual, collective and social responsibility of the firm Tuomo Takala and Paul Pallab Introduction In today's world of increasing consumerism, egoism and self-absorption of individuals, protecting the natural environment for our future generations has become a critical issue. As economic activities of firms have contributed to the depletion of the environment, we feel that the firms have a moral responsibility to restore the health of our natural environment. Safe environment is a long-term goal that will be difficult to achieve, but if we fail to achieve it there might be no human species left to produce and enjoy economic plenty. Firms are well equipped to implement proenvironment actions. Given the abundance of resources at its disposal and its capacity to mobilize a large group of people, the firm as a collective unit is more efficient and effective than any one individual. To enable appropriate actions, the firm needs to inculcate in all employees a moral consciousness and responsibility towards the environment. Every member of the firm, not simply the `employers/owners,' definitely stands to gain from such an initiative. There would be shortterm gain of enhanced social image and profitability that accompanies it. In the long run also, a safe environment will ensure that there is natural abundance and a constant supply of raw materials required for manufacture of products, and a thriving human community to purchase that product. But beyond the objective of making such tangible gains, one has to remember that moral value and action are intrinsically valuable and need to be fostered irrespective of material gains. # Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000. 108 Cowley Road, Oxford OX4 1JF, UK and 350 Main St, Malden, MA 02148, USA. A firm, however, cannot possibly promote a pro-environment attitude that would benefit society and the business world, without full support from its employees across all ranks. Positive and confirmatory action within a firm can be achieved only when individuals are committed to the goals and values of the organization. To ensure commitment, the organization has to acculturate its employees into its dominant ideas. Employees have to be socialized into the fact that along with the firm, they are equally responsible for morally right, proenvironmental actions. The firm definitely benefits from cultivation of moral values. `A better alignment of organizational policy and employee's values holds possibilities for enhanced motivation and work performance' (Maclagan 1999). To achieve this synchronization of values, the firm can resort to informal insemination of moral values. In that case, group dynamics of informal friendship networks through peer pressure and codes of loyalty would ensure that every individual within the firm would consciously evaluate their moral positions. The firm can also resort to formal processes to announce the fact that it consciously solicits and supports ethical behavior even if it goes against its economic interests. Formal means of establishing moral values could include development of formal incentive programs (financial or otherwise) and the conducting of educational seminars and workshops. Thus we see that for the firm to make collective moral action feasible, it also needs the compliance of all the individuals who participate in its collective identity. Compliance is secured not merely through enticing financial incentives but 109 Volume 9 Number 2 also by cultivating a desire to do the right thing. A firm cannot possibly promote a pro-environment attitude by merely luring or forcing its employees to follow legally defined standards of environmental safety. First of all, legal restrictions on exploitation of the environment are often not sufficiently protective measures. Second, in the case of absence of a moral conscience among individuals of the firm, laws will not be sufficient restrictors of or guides to individual actions. It is not sufficient for the firm's employees to align themselves to the moral agenda of the firm simply because the firm dictates it. The employees have to be given sufficient flexibility and autonomy to avoid `herd mentality', take initiative, responsibility and make a choice about doing the right thing. Self-selected goals are easier to achieve, and when individuals are conscious of the responsibility bestowed on them they are more likely to adhere to the path of justice. Moreover, we can argue that morally relevant actions also satisfy higher, spiritual, self-actualizing goals of employees. We then argue that for true environmentally beneficial ethics to develop there has to be a conscious cultivation of this attitude among all members of a firm. It goes without saying that along with the development of a moral attitude there also have to be concrete steps taken to transform that attitude into action. Above all, the burden of taking the initiative to raise ethical consciousness lies not simply with the firm but also with the individuals within it. It is a mutual process. If the firm ignores ethical dictates, it is the employee's duty to take the initiative, protest against unethical activities of the firm, organize collectively and make the firm conscious of its obligation to save the environment. If the employees remain silent despite being conscious of the firm's malpractice, they are as culpable as the firm is for the entire harm inflicted on the society and environment. Literature on business ethics usually focuses on the responsibility of the firm, but in this paper, a major focus will also be the responsibility of the employees. In the process of promotion of environmentfriendly attitudes, the firm may lose some of its profits as environmentally safe acts can be costly and the firm may not be able to sell a product for 110 April 2000 the cheapest price. But the firm definitely gains a favorable social and business image, which might boost sales among `environmentally conscious consumers'. The path to building up consciousness is a long and difficult one. Individuals have conflicting opinions and priorities. Moreover, the burden of consciousness does not rest only with the firm and its employees. For an environmentally friendly firm to survive in a competitive market atmosphere there has to be a growing body of conscious consumers who would patronize the socially responsible firm despite its slightly more expensive products. The consuming public has the obligation to make the trade-off between cost and environmental integrity. The responsibility for a safe environment lies with the entire society. However, in this paper we will focus only on the moral responsibility of the firm and its employees. The concept of responsibility When analyzing the issue of responsibility within organizational life, one should consider several issues. First, it is not sufficient to simply consider an individual's (and also an organization's) awareness and observance of the formal laws laid down by social and legal institutions of the society. It is also important to focus on the informal moral principles operative in social life. Moral principles, such as ensuring the welfare of other people even when there are possibilities of economic losses to oneself, guide the conscience of individuals and act as constraints on the rational actions which seek to maximize material satisfaction, profitability and efficiency for themselves. Sometimes an individual's moral sense might even conflict with socially designated formal laws. For example, a government hospital's doctor who believes in pro-life might be forced to conduct an abortion simply because the law of his/her country allows that privilege to women and because s/he works in a government institution where s/he is bound to follow the rules. The dilemma that arises from such a conflict of values can create moral oppression for the actor. Second, while analyzing the logic behind responsible actions, one should also consider a # Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000 Business Ethics: A European Review distinction between egoistic and altruistic motives. When an individual seeks to do the `right' thing because s/he stands to gain something out of it, his/her motives are based on egoism and his/her action might be labeled as egoistic. However, eliciting responsible actions from people by enticing them with the promise of personal benefits is not a reliable or ethically viable method for ensuring responsibility in social organizations. Responsibility should basically stem from altruism. And true altruism involves the will or sincere desire to act in the right way without giving priority to one's own benefits. Altruistic acts can be considered to be not just responsible but morally responsible acts. However, in the field of ethical theories, there is a controversy over whether altruistic motive is a sufficient judge of the moral correctness or the rightness or wrongs of a human deed. Some philosophers believe that a deed ought to be judged by its consequences. This has given rise to two diverging fields of thought ± deontological and utilitarian. Deontological theory (Kant 1997) propounds that deeds are good only when they are carried out on the basis of a `universal' sense of duty or the will to do right, e.g. respect for other human beings. Utilitarianism considers that a deed is good only when, in comparison to all possible alternative actions, it has the best possible positive benefits and when there are no adverse consequences that outbalance the quantum of benefits (Quinton 1989). There is a major difference between deontological theory and utilitarian theory. Deontological theory simply argues about how an individual ought to realize his/her ethical duty. Unlike utilitarian theory, it does not take into consideration the achievement of maximum utility or goodness from any act, i.e. there is no account of relative evaluation of a deed. In the absence of any evaluative measure for a deed, deontological theory also fails to provide an explanation about how to distribute the benefits and burdens of deeds among the members of the society. In short, deontological theories do not take into account differential degrees of rewards and punishments for actors, which are typically based on evaluation of external utility of any act. However, allowing # Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000 for an analysis of the value of an act does not necessarily elevate utilitarianism over deontological theory. At any one point in time, evaluation is influenced by particularistic and often elitist cultural norms of a society, as well as by individual subjectivity. As a result, there is always scope for injustice. So, when analyzing an act, one should consider pure, universally just motives along with external utility. Some theorists, like Frankena (1973), have tried to go beyond the dichotomized style of thought by following a middle-path. Frankena's mixed-deontological theory evaluates deeds by drawing on the normative principles of both the above-mentioned theories. It is then clear that there is no single definition of responsible actions or morally good deeds. Helkama's (1981) description of three usages of moral responsibility is a case in point: a) `Responsible' as an attribute of persons and actions. In saying, `X is a responsible person', `Y was a responsible action' we say something favorable about the person and about the action. Here responsibility is described as a personality disposition, where a person can be counted on to fulfill obligations and willingly accept the consequences of his behavior. b) `Responsible' as a synonym for `accountable', connected with blame (praise) and punishment. `X is responsible for Y (e.g. damage)' is usually interpreted as meaning that it is right or justified to blame or punish X for Y (or, if Y is something good, to praise X for it). Here there is responsibility attribution. c) `Responsible' as meaning having a duty, an `obligation'. `As a father, X is responsible for his children' means that it is X's duty to care for his children. One difference between this use of the term and the preceding one is that responsibility (b) refers to past acts (or arises out of a performed action) while responsibility (c) designates something still to be done (as part of an established role-system). Another difference is that you are always responsible (b) for individual past actions but you may be responsible (c) for both particular acts and generic classes of acts. 111 Volume 9 Number 2 Among the above mentioned types of responsibility the third type is probably the most interesting to us. This is because there is a presumption that the individual X is not simply capable of carrying out the deed, but also, that he is acting voluntarily, willingly and intentionally. According to Aristotle (1995), an individual can be said to be responsible for morally good deeds that benefit the wider community only when they are carried out voluntarily and with full cognizance of the relevant circumstances and personal repercussions. Volition here is not synonymous with arbitrariness. It essentially refers to the fact that the individual is aware of what an act entails and carries it out willingly. One cannot be held responsible for deeds conducted against one's own will. Constraints to free action may arise out of external physical conditions set by nature or out of physical coercion imposed by other individuals, groups and organizations like the state. It may also arise out of `inner compulsion', e.g., a deed done in a state of strong surge of emotion or emotional derangement may at least afterwards seem strange to the actor, and he may deny the deed as his own. Deeds are also involuntary when conducted under ignorance due to no fault of one's own. (The importance of volition in an act will become clear when, later on in our paper, we discuss individual performance under the aegis of collective identity of a firm.) Even though an individual's moral responsibility is contingent upon volition in carrying out an act, the debate that crops up is whether an act can be truly voluntary or whether all choices and expressions of an act are deterministically constrained by other existing conditions as well as preceding events. Since we know that under normal circumstances, any action is influenced by multiple causes, we cannot obviously argue totally against determinism. To do so would be to acknowledge indeterminism and admit to an extreme and irrational explanation of events, i.e. occurrence of phenomena without any necessary reason. In a scenario where indeterminism prevails, there will be solely impulsive and arbitrary individual actions but no prudent and rational actions. Obviously that is not a feasible scenario as 112 April 2000 there would be no coherent social action and social life would be impossible. But neither can we admit to total determinism because then there would be no scope for individual volition, choice or action. Moreover, if we admit to either absolute determinism or indeterminism, we would be unable to pinpoint any individual for responsibility of actions undertaken. The individual would be either totally helpless against external circumstances or totally clueless about why he had undertaken an act. Under such circumstances, there would be no way to socially mete out `justice' in terms of rewards and punishments for individual acts. In this context, the utilitarian practice of judging an act by its utility regardless of absolute juridical principles might come in handy, though it is not necessarily the best solution. One good way to solve this dilemma between irrationalism and absolute determinism is probably to try and find a middle ground, one that acknowledges deterministic events and individual decision. It would be easier to try to tread a middle ground if we make a conceptual distinction between deed and process. A deed is necessarily intended, right from its inception, and the conditions for its possibility are the intentional objects of the deed. In contrast, a process is non-directed; something or someone else other than the focal individual carries out action. For example, we cannot pinpoint a machine as being responsible for a deed since it is a soulless automaton. However, the person responsible for implementing the process of operation of the machine can be held responsible for all outcomes of operating the machine. In the literature on business ethics, the firm is usually treated as a social and legal entity, which is responsible for all its deeds. Any claim that a firm can be construed as being above all demands of responsibility, as it is an `abstract entity' that is the target of intangible processes like market forces, is not accepted. However, we argue that beyond a singular socio-legal entity, a firm is also a collective unity composed of multiple conscious and willing individuals who independently strategize, organize and implement its actions. This holds true in spite of the separation # Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000 Business Ethics: A European Review of ownership and management in the current era. The very existence of a firm implies a deed; individuals have intentionally constructed it. A firm is neither an object of abstract forces nor an abstract entity. If the firm is considered as a moral community then, by extrapolation, not only the firm but also its various employees, particularly the top management, are responsible for the deeds of the firm. One cannot absolve individuals in the firm of all responsibilities simply because they automatically follow the rules laid down by the firm. Both the firm and its employees' moral responsibility have to be acknowledged. The relation between moral and legal responsibility The importance of the need to consider the distinction between deed and process can be further reviewed by considering the relation between moral and legal responsibility. A crucial question that has occupied the minds of researchers is the distinction and relation between moral and politico-legal responsibility. When discussing responsibility in a political or legal sense rather than an ethical sense, responsibility gets redefined. In ethical responsibility an individual is responsible for his/her actions without being specifically responsible to anybody other than himself/herself (Ewing 1957). The individual's actions are automatically regulated by his/her inner moral conscience. In the case of a politico-legal definition of responsibility, there are two things that one needs to look out for. It is not just sufficient to look for what things an individual is responsible for, it is also necessary to give weight to the question `to whom is the individual responsible?' Politico-legal responsibility entails `liability to be called to account', and it is always responsibility for something (Ewing 1957). Although laws are mostly based on certain universal ethical principles of justice, a legal definition of `right action' may not always match ethical standards of justice. Despite substantial overlap between morality and law, many an act may be legally correct but morally dubious or even controversial, e.g. the issue of retrenchment in corporations. The danger then is # Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000 that ethically unjust actions (from a universal standpoint) may go unpunished or unreformed simply because the laws of a particular society do not recognize the criminality of the deed. We argue that `law' is analogous to `process', as it constrains or licenses an individual to act in a particular manner. Similarly, `moral' is analogous to a `deed', since in the context of morality, an individual has some control over the way he acts and also a choice about acting in the right manner. Laws regulate a `soulless individual' but morals reinstate the soul as the guiding force in an individual. Some theorists have claimed that there is no relevant distinction between juridical and ethical responsibility (Abbagno 1957). They illustrate the invalidity of the distinction by pointing to the relation between ethical and juridical norms. The juridical norm defines an `illegal' deed, its minimum conditions, and the associated punishment for breaking the normative commitments of social life. For example, the norm `do not kill' is a legal norm. Kelsen (1990) points out that this legal norm is not detached from ethics. It is only a secondary norm that supports a primary ethical norm, `respect the life of other people'. Though legal norms can complement ethical norms we feel that the distinction between legal and ethical norms is still valid. An individual may be a fully acceptable citizen in a legal sense but still highly immoral. The distinction is particularly important in our analysis of the firm's role in ethical issues. In the context of a firm, which has multiple duties to perform, it is not just sufficient to look at the supervisory politico-juridical regulations that constrain and determine the acts of the firm. It is also important to look at the `social and moral conscience' that guide those activities of the firm that affect the wider social populace (by extrapolation, one should also consider the social conscience of individuals who execute the various activities of the firm). It is true that the firm is accountable to the state as a political institution as well as to its judiciary, which executes the laws formulated by the state. Legal rules of the society constrain harmful acts of a firm. In its absence, a firm would not have an important motivation ± the fear of prosecution for 113 Volume 9 Number 2 destructive activities, for accepting responsibility for its actions. However, this is not a sufficient precondition for ensuring that the firm conducts socially enriching activities. In this paper, our focus is on corporate decisions that affect the natural environment. We believe that `Saving The Earth For Our Future Generations' is a fundamental social activity that a firm needs to focus on. Some academicians, as well as environmental activists, claim that society should push for environmentally conscious corporate decisions by framing laws that sustain rights of human beings to live in a clean, healthy and constantly prosperous natural environment. But there are also some academicians and some environmentalists like Raymond Dassman (Chiras 1995), who argue that laws only define the minimum principles of individual action. By themselves, they are insufficient guarantee for the materialization of ethical principles. Individuals have to also develop a conscious moral tenor to all their activities. Morals supplement law by bringing softer and subtler social and interpersonal pressures to bear (Walsh 1970). Those who subscribe to a complement of law and morality would point out that since morality is an imperative in environment protection, the firm itself should also consciously cultivate a culture where morally responsible actions are championed. But we would also like to point out that morals should not be cultivated simply as a supplement to law, or as a constraint that enforces good actions. Morals are valuable in themselves. Ethics should not be a separate and optional management discipline added onto basic management principles. It should be integral to good business practice. A sense of justice and morality develops best under circumstances where people have a choice and are free to make moral decisions. The firm should cultivate such an atmosphere of freedom and autonomy through corporate decentralization. Given an easy and flexible ambience, employees can take initiative and rationally juggle multiple responsibilities for the benefit of not just the firm but also the wider society. A firm treading a path of morality for the first time, typically goes through a developmental path of accountability- 114 April 2000 imputability-freedom-rationality (MacKeon 1957). The firm first becomes aware of the fact that it is accountable for all its actions to the legal bodies of the society. It then follows a defined path of `correct action' simply out of a fear of punishment. It does not undertake good actions out of true and unfettered volition. The need for legal approval is gradually accompanied by a need for social approval, a socially uplifting image for the firm. This typically happens when the firm comes under pressure from consumers who are aware of wider moral issues and lobby to the government for action against the firm's morally unacceptable practices. For example, in 1989, morally active American consumers consciously boycotted the firm Exxon and its petroleum products when Exxon refused to acknowledge its responsibility in a major ocean oil spillage. The company ultimately had to back down under severely negative media image, compensated all the concerned parties for its actions, and undertook a commitment to clean up the ocean. Thus the firm initially undertakes moral actions out of socio-legal compulsions. Good actions are defined by the firm as being in accordance with the `rules of the game'. They are a means to an end, the end being maximizing profitability and growth. However, over time, the firm internalizes ethical practices as good business moral, cherishes them for their intrinsic value and voluntarily commits itself to environmentally safe actions. The firm chooses to do the right thing as it cultivates an inner will and duty to do good. Both the motive and the deed become pure and useful as economic rationality and morality become concurrently valuable principles (Goodpaster 1989). The organization's adoption of environmental safety does not go unrewarded since there can be mutually profitable exchange between the environment and the organization that will ensure the survival of the system as a whole. From the above analysis we see that we can end up with both deontological orientation and utilitarian action. Even though the firm starts out with selfish motives, it can end up nurturing truly altruistic motives as an end in itself and consequently enacting utilitarian deeds. The firm typically begins with low levels of responsibility # Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000 Business Ethics: A European Review and goes on to achieve higher levels of morally responsible actions. In this process, there can be renewed perception about existing facts and available alternatives, emergence of new styles of analysis and synthesis of those facts, cautious and well-thought out methods of implementation of a chosen path as well as evaluation of outcomes for clues to further betterment of the environment. In the end the firm might achieve a `progressive' definition of what constitutes healthy environmentally pro-active changes. In order to achieve a revolutionary ideal about the environment, `respect' for the environment can act as a good guide (Goodpaster 1989). Respect prompts all members of the firm to choose rational, benevolent and responsible ends. Conscious development of respect for the environment and resultant moral actions can also help close gaps that usually exist between ideal and actual corporate values and between corporate values and personal values of the employees (Goodpaster 1989). The firm is a powerful actor in society. Given that, it is very important that this particular `citizen' achieves and demonstrates a reasonable degree of social responsibility. From the overall conceptual descriptions of moral responsibility, we can conclude that, despite partial determination by various events, an individual or a firm can `break' this determination by becoming conscious of the meanings of the various events and deliberately cultivating a morally responsible attitude. This is particularly important if man is to prove to himself that he is a `higher order being', blessed with the capacity for thinking and reflecting, rather than a mindless animal which cannot be held responsible for its actions. Increased consciousness is also important for the survival of our earth ± the abode of mankind. So far, we have been trying to clarify the dilemma of determinism and freedom of action. In the following section we will try to establish the fact that despite the constraints imposed by the larger collectivity ± the firm, an individual, instead of being a willing partner in crime, can employ the power of his consciousness and volition in protesting against immoral actions of a firm. # Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000 Concepts of collective and individual responsibility, and their mutual relation in the context of action within a business organization As we have mentioned before, the firm is not just a singular legal entity, it is also a collective identity since it is composed of multiple active individuals. But the individuals, apparently, are not autonomous units free to pursue their own style of implementing an action. Every individual in the firm is supposedly bound by their professionally defined roles, all of which together contribute to the collective identity of the firm. Individuals act as representatives of the firm, and sometimes they find themselves in situations where they have to do things which they as private individuals they would not choose to do. This is an example of what Aristotle calls `non-voluntary' action (Walsh 1970). The debate about determinism crops up here. If an individual is limited in his/her actions by a role prescribed to him/her by an external entity ± the organization/institution ± how can s/he be free to act, and by extension how can s/he be held responsible for any harmful acts of the firm (Flores and Johnson 1983)? If every individual is bound by a collective identity ascribed to him/her by the firm in which s/he works, how can an individual ever step out of the confines of his/her business role and take responsibility for consciously chosen moral actions? In the last analysis, is it always the firm that is to be held responsible for immoral activities? Some have argued that only individuals can be moral agents and therefore held accountable for the consequences of their actions (Flores and Johnson 1983). Since organizations are `collective bodies', they cannot be treated as morally responsible agents. There is no plausibility in such an argument. We already know that even entire nations like Nazi Germany can be held responsible for atrocious inhumanitarian acts. It is probably safe to claim that collective bodies are as culpable as individuals within that collectivity. The question then is, can collective moral responsibility be proportionally distributed among individuals within the firm? 115 Volume 9 Number 2 A firm is composed of multiple individuals occupying various ranks and performing various complementary functions. Each differential individual output is a small contribution to the overall collective output. However, in typical business literature, the ultimate goal of all the individuals in the firm, irrespective of the kind and size of their contribution, is portrayed to be production and sale of a product for maximum profit. Apparently, the sole motivation that drives all activities of individuals in the firm, both administrative and productive, is competitive advantage of the firm at any cost. Moral concerns do not occupy a primary position in this attempt at profit maximization by either the firm or its employees. Economic literature also typically tends to overlook ethics and endorse only the material functions of a firm. In mainstream economic literature there has been a strong advocacy of freemarket and competition among industries because this widens consumer choice. Not much attention has been given to how irresponsible competition can endanger the environment. Neo-liberals have argued for free markets where people who are industrious, responsible, reliable and enterprising can thrive (Ver Eecke 1982). But along with instrumental virtues which generate enterprise, material choices and better standards of living, the firm should also have higher orders of moral virtues like generosity, magnanimity, and compassion if we are to have the choice of living in a safe environment. As we know, perceptions about responsibilities of a firm have changed over time. It has gradually been acknowledged in academia and the wider society that the firm has a moral duty to protect the environment. However, the focus has been only on the collective responsibility of the firm and not on the virtues of individuals who make possible the existence of the firm. There has been an imbalance in the distribution of moral responsibility. Thus, in the process of production and marketing of the firm's product if there are any environmentally hazardous effects or any threats to common safety, it is usually only the `firm' which has been held responsible and not the individuals who sought to maximize economic benefits for the firm. 116 April 2000 This is a potentially threatening situation, in which the managers and all other employees, as part of a business collective, are absolved of all responsibility for their behavior. If people are detached from the consequences of their deed and the blame is shifted onto a faceless entity, the firm, there would be no hope of improving people's attitudes. What concerns us here is not that individuals within a firm are escaping legal responsibility, but rather that they are not being made aware of their moral responsibility, which is of course a higher order of responsibility. One cannot absolve individuals in the firm of all responsibilities simply on the basis of the supposition that they follow the rules laid down by the firm automatically rather than voluntarily. This argument holds true particularly for the top management. The `power theory of management' (Donaldson 1995) acknowledges the existence of `power elites' within the organization. Given the fact that the powerful managers within an organization have considerable capacity to manipulate the directions and goals of the organization, one cannot overlook their moral involvement in the actions undertaken by the firm. Usually, as we have described before, managers are portrayed as `collective' representatives of the firm playing a role defined by the firm, rather than as legally responsible `individuals' of a civilian society who are free to act according to their own choice. Given this portrayal, managers are usually redeemed from any liability for morally reprehensible acts of the firm. However, the fact is that despite their fiduciary duties to stockholders the management has sufficient autonomy and is responsible for making independent decisions, formulating strategies, and acting on behalf of the firm. Moreover, the managers have morally significant non-fiduciary obligations to third parties whose freedom and well being is affected by their economic behavior. Since the managers have a substantial degree of autonomy to act in the `right' way they can bring in new values ± environmentally friendly values ± into the various role-sets in the firm. Following an environmentfriendly program not only benefits the firm in the long run but also helps its individual employees to attain higher spiritual needs. # Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000 Business Ethics: A European Review The downside to the above argument for autonomy is that autonomy given to managers can be misused. But pro-active public policies can act as moral and legal constraints on managers, and even if the formal judicial system of a society absolves an individual of responsibility for morally harmful acts, the individual can perhaps be taken to task through moral censure like public exposure and social ostracism. But punishment does not solve all problems. As we keep reiterating, cultivating a self-regulatory moral conscience is far more important for achievement of high ethical standards. We argue that the dictates of moral sensibility applies to both the top and middle management as well as the lower ranked employees who may claim that they are bound by their professional roles and loyalty to the firm. Though constrained by their roles within an institution, we have to remember that, a) Every employee voluntarily chose to be a member of the firm. These people voluntarily committed themselves to act in the roles prescribed for them by the firm. b) Despite being bound by rules and role prescriptions, employees do have flexibility as the rules of a firm only act as general guidelines. The employees can enrich their roles by fulfilling them in a more moral fashion. They can also redefine certain rules or demand the abolition of unacceptable rules. c) Doing what the firm prescribes benefits not only the firm but also the employee and hence the employee cannot deny his/her involvement and responsibility. The moral limits to action are apparent from the fact that although employees have their jobs and usually their livelihood at stake, they may break unwritten rules of loyalty and blow the whistle on harmful acts of the company. Despite pressures, an individual can offer resistance and refuse to commit `immoral' activities. Only in very rare instances is an individual truly coerced (in the physical sense) to commit an immoral act. Until recently, ecology conscious business practices were to be found only in marginal, idealistic `alternative enterprises'. But, things are changing. # Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000 The apparently `normal' firms are also becoming conscious of the considerations of the eco-system and are starting to take first steps in the right direction. However, we have to remember that this is occurring primarily in the developed world. In the developing countries where poverty along with corruption and administrative malpractice dominate, there is still a long way to go. In fact, it is the duty of the First World countries to help the Third World countries avert an ecological disaster. Conclusion `The Limits to Growth' (Meadows et al. 1974), was a pioneering book that alerted humanity to the looming environmental disaster. The authors of this book delineated the disastrous growth trends in world population, the industrialization, pollution output, food production, and extinction of various animal species that threatened to deplete the resources of the environment. The thinning of the ozone layer, emission of greenhouse gases due to indiscriminate consumption of fossil fuels, deforestation, soil erosion and spread of deserts has speeded up the clock of environmental disaster at an exponential rate. Despite skepticism about a future disaster as well as optimistic hopes, technology and resource substitution cannot outrun this depletion and pollution (Dallmeyer and Ike 1998). `Sustainable development' has become an important field of research in the academic field of social sciences. The focus in a sustainable society is on quality rather than quantity (Chiras 1995). In our world where individualism is emphasized as a value, individuals need to be made aware of the limits of self-interest and their moral responsibility to the wider community. The firm is one arena where individual responsibility for safeguarding the environment can be emphasized. But organization theory has not focussed significantly on the moral responsibilities of managers for creating a safe environment. Business literature has, however, become increasingly conscious and focussed on the issues of ethics and morality. But, the ethical issues have 117 Volume 9 Number 2 been largely concerned with stakeholders like workers, other firms, and other countries and their culture. In short, an analysis of the environment of the firm has been restricted to its `relationship network'. In addition, whenever issues regarding the natural environment have been addressed, it has always been secondary to the primary concern of ensuring consumer satisfaction. Typical stakeholder theory has never really taken into consideration the natural environment. We feel that here is a big gap that managerial theorizing can fill. A firm's relationship to its environment needs to be re-thematized. As economic activity expands, it threatens the environment in general, systematic, modal, and endemic ways; it strains overall ecological limits and threatens to exceed the `carrying capacity' of the planet (Dallmeyer and Ike 1998). This perspective needs to be reflected in stakeholder theory. Keeping in mind the viewpoints of different stakeholders in society, and also the dictates of justice, human rights and quality of social life; the business community needs to find a harmonious definition of the concept of environmental responsibility, its various forms and objects, and the whole process needs to be re-evaluated continuously over time. The decision-making strategic management in various firms and various interest groups of society should collaborate to shoulder the moral responsibility of saving the environment. To achieve success in the effort to save the Earth, ecological ethics need to be cultivated for its `intrinsic value' and not just for its utility. References Abbagno, M. 1957. `Judgements of responsibility in ethics and in law'. Revue International de Philosophie, 39, 33±50. Barnes, J. (Ed.) 1982. Aristotle. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Borchert, D. (Ed.) 1996. Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Supplement. New York: Simon & Schuster Macmillan. Chiras, D.D. (Ed.) 1995. Voices for the earth: vital ideas from America's best environmental books. Boulder, Colorado: Johnson Books. 118 April 2000 Dallmeyer, D.G. and Ike, F.A. 1998. Environmental ethics and the global marketplace. Georgia: University of Georgia Press. Donaldson, L. 1995. American anti-management theories of organization: a critique of paradigm proliferation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Donaldson, T. and Werhane, P. (Ed.) 1996. Ethical issues in business: a philosophical approach. New Jersey: Prentice Hall. Ewing, A. 1957. `Responsibility towards oneself and others'. Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 39, 51±68. Flores, A. and Johnson, G.D. 1983. `Collective responsibility and professional roles'. Ethics, 93:3, 537±548. Frankena, W.K. 1973. Ethics. Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice Hall. Frankena, W.K. 1982. Ethics and the environment. Cleveland, Ohio: Cleveland State University Instructional Media Services. Goodpaster, K.E. 1989. `Ethical imperatives and corporate leadership'. In Andrews, K.R. (Ed.), Ethics in practice: managing the moral corporation, 212±228. Boston: Harvard Business School Press. Helkama, K. 1981. Toward a cognitive-developmental theory of attribution of responsibility ± a critical review of empirical research and some preliminary data. Helsinki: Suomalainen Tiedeakatemia. Kant, I. 1997. Lectures on Ethics. New York: Cambridge University Press. Kelsen, H. 1990. General theory of norms. Tr. M. Hartney. Oxford: Oxford University Press. MacKeon, R. 1957. `The development and significance of the concept of responsibility'. Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 39, 3±32. Maclagan, P. 1999. `Corporate social responsibility as a participative process'. Business Ethics: A European Review, 8:1, 43±49. Meadows, D.H. et al. 1974. Limits to growth. New York: University Books. Quinton, A. 1989. Utilitarian ethics. London: Duckworth. Takala, T. 1991. Managerial beliefs concerning social responsibility of the firm ± a trial to identify and understand entrepreneur's and manager's social responsibility beliefs as discursive phenomena. Jyvaskyla: University of Jyvaskyla Press. Ver Eecke, W. 1982. `Ethics in economics, from classical economics to neo-liberalism'. Philosophy and Social Criticism, 9:2. Walsh, W. 1970. `Pride, shame and responsibility'. Philosophical Quarterly, 20:78, 1±13. # Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2000