* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Darwin after Malthus
Survey
Document related concepts
Transcript
Darwin after Malthus DOV OSPOVAT University Lincoln, of Nebraska Nebraska In the Origin of Species (1859) natural selection is presented as an autonomous biological process which is, potentially, in continuous operation. No organism is perfect. There is always room for improvement. At any time or place a species, however well adapted it may seem to be, may give rise to still better-adapted forms. New variations may appear that are better suited for existing conditions, and when this happens the pressure of population will work to select them and their similarly favored offspring until a new, improved form is created. Natural selection, Darwin said in the Origin, is “daily and hourly scrutinising, throughout the world, every variation”; it is “silently and insensibly working, whenever and wherever opportunity offers, at the improvement of each organic being in relation to its organic and inorganic conditions of life.” * In the “Essay of 1844,” on the other hand, selection is depicted as confined and limited in its operation. Compare the statement I have just quoted with this description of the evolutionary process from the “Essay”: if there are variation and struggle in nature, then “new races of beings will, - perhaps only rarely, and only in some few districts, - be formed.“2 One’s first reaction is probably to dismiss this contrast by saying that in 1844 Darwin was less confident or merely more cautious in his exposition. But there is much more to it than this. In 1844 natural selection was limited by what I would like to call structural constraints, which were eliminated sometime before 1859. By structural constraints I mean those imposed by the framework of beliefs about nature within which Darwin supposed that his evolutionary mechanism operated. To be more precise, Darwin in 1844 still believed in perfect adaptation. Perfectly adapted forms are not capable of further improvement. They vary little; so, among them, natural selection has little material on 1. Charles Darwin, On the Origin of Species (London: John Murray, 1859), p. 84. 2. Francis Darwin, ed., The Foundations of the Origin of Species: Two Essays Written in 1842 and 1844 by Charles Darwin (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1909), 1844, p. 109. Journal of the History 0022-5010/79/0122-0211 Copyright 0 1979 vol. 12, no. 2 (Fall 1979), pp. 211-230. $02.00 of Biology, by D. Reidel Publishing Co., Dordrecht, Holland, and Boston, U.S,A DOV OSPOVAT which to work. The checks caused by population pressure fall evenly on all, except for occasional misfits, which are weeded out. Consequently, the action of natural selection is restricted to a few situations - those in which there is geological change, or those in which organisms are transported into new regions, so that they are no longer perfectly adapted, The idea of perfect adaptation, which Darwin shared with most of his contemporaries, had its roots not in the naturalist’s examination of organisms, but in his belief that organisms were created either directly or indirectly - by a wise and benevolent God. This belief also Darwin shared for some time with most of his contemporaries; and even after he began to modify it, he continued to suppose that organisms are perfectly adapted. In short, for a number of years, Darwin conceived of natural selection as operating in an essentially natural theological framework. The fact that Darwin continued to believe in perfect adaptation from his pre-Malthus period until after 1844 will require, I think, a new analysis of the character and development of Darwin’s theory. But since it has not been noticed before, and has been implicitly denied by most Darwin scholars who have discussed the problem of adaptation, the first task must be to establish the fact. That is the limited aim of this paper. It will, perhaps, be best to begin with my conclusions, because the argument will then be easier to follow. First: Until he read Malthus, at the end of September 1838, Darwin believed that adaptation is perfect and that the universe is a harmonious whole. This, I must note, was David Kohn’s conclusion before it was mine.3 I find his arguments on this point unassailable, and I am convinced that Darwin’s notebooks admit of no other interpretation. Second: When Darwin read Malthus and hit upon the idea of natural selection4 he did not immediately 3. E. David Kohn, “Charles Darwin’s Path to Natural Selection,” Ph.D. diss., University of Massachusetts, 1975. 4. I use the term natural selection for the sake of convenience, but it should be borne in mind that at first Darwin spoke only of “wedging,” not “selection” or “picking.” Gavin de Beer, et al., eds., “Darwin’s Notebooks on Transmutation of Species. Part VI. Pages Excised by Darwin,” Bull. Brit. Mus. (Nat. Hist.), Hist. Ser., 3 (1967), 131-176. All references to Darwin’s notebooks will be to the de Beer edition, ibid., 2 (1960), 41-183,3 (1967), 131-176. De Beer’s “First,” “Second,” “Third,” and “Fourth” notebooks correspond to Darwin’s B, C, D, and E note books. Throughout I will cite the notebooks by Darwin’s letter and page number, followed by a small e in the case of excised pages: in the present instance, D, p. 135e. Camille Limoges in La sdection naturelle (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1970), pp. 104-105, notes that as far as he has found, the earliest use by Darwin of the term “selection” is in marginal annotations of W. Youatt’s Cattle, 212 Darwin after Malthus abandon his belief in perfection and harmony.5 Although he would later do so, he did not immediately view the organic world as a scene of struggle and discord, productive only of relatively, that is, less-thanperfectly, adapted creatures. Instead, he initially envisaged natural selection as operating in precisely the same natural theological context in which Malthus had set his principle of population - the context of a system of beneficent laws. Third: Within a few months of reading Malthus, Darwin gave up the idea that every natural effect of nature’s laws was included in the original design for which the whole system of laws was established. But he continued until some time after 1844 to believe in perfect adaptation, and this determined the structure of his entire theory in its early years. In the “Essaapiof 1844” that structure is the same one that Darwin laid down in his first transmutation notebook, at a time when he still adhered to traditional views on the harmony of the creation. My argument falls into three parts, corresponding roughly to these three conclusions. In the first, it is necessary to explain in what sense Darwin throughout his pre-Malthus notebooks believed in harmony and perfection, for it is fairly widely held that he rejected such notions some time before September 1838.‘j In the second part 1 examine Darwin’s reaction to Malthus, in order to indicate how Darwin initially fit his new theory into his old framework of beliefs. And in the third I attempt to show the persistence, in the “Essay of 1844,” of the idea of perfect adaptation and of the theoretical structure that from the first was associated with it. DARWIN BEFORE MALTHLJS When I say that Darwin believed in perfect adaptation, I must at once introduce a distinction. Darwin, it is true, rejected the PaleyBreeds, Management and Disease (18341, which Darwin read in March 1840. The earliest I have seenis in a loose note dated “Jan 1840”; Darwin MS& Box B, C40f, CambridgeUniversityLibrary. Their 5. It is here that I part company with David Kohn. I must point out also that Kohn and I are not entirely in agreement about the reasons for Darwin’s preMalthus belief in perfect adaptation. 6. Most notably by Camille Limoges, S&ection naturelle, pp. 69-85, and “Darwinisme et adaptation,” Revue des Questions Scientifiques, 141, 5th ser., 31 (19701, 353-374. See also Silvan Schweber, “The Origin of the Origin Revisited,” J Hist. Biol, 10 (1977), 235; Sandra Herbert, “Man in the Development of Darwin’s Theory of Transmutation, Part II,” ibid., p. 200; and Howard Gruber, Darwin on Man (New York: E. P. Dutton, 1974), p. 158. 213 DOV OSPOVAT Bridgewater variety of perfect adaptation long before he read Malthus. For Charles Bell, William Buckland, or Charles Lye& as for Cuvier, adaptation to purpose was the only acceptable explanation of organic structure. When Darwin became a transmutationist, he of necessity became an opponent of their “principle of adaptation,” for it is strictly incompatible with the theory of descent.’ But the Bridgewater variety of perfect adaptation was not the only possible one. I have pointed out elsewhere that, like Darwin, many biologists from the 1830’s through the 1850’s repudiated the teleological approach of Bell and Cuvier while retaining a belief in perfect adaptation.8 They argued that there are structural similarities among organisms that cannot be explained satisfactorily in purely functional terms and that consequently one must recognize a law of unity of type. Organisms are as perfect as is possible within the limits set by the necessity of conforming to the type.9 Their perfection is part of a “teleology of a higher order,” which is to say that it is produced by a system of laws established by God.” Here, for instance, is Richard Owen’s idea of perfection as he expressed it in 1838: It is a groundless fear that some have expressed when a physical explanation of the form and condition of an organ has been offered, that it blunts our appreciation of the Wisdom which adapted that organ I. While the “principle of adaptation” allows no other explanation but adaptation, in all descent theories heredity is a major part of the explanation of structure. The inadequacy of the principle of adaptation is a constant theme in the transmutation notebooks (it is this that Limoges and Gruber, in the works cited above, have interpreted as a rejection of perfect adaptation - which is only partly true). Darwin insists that adaptation alone cannot explain unity of type, rudimentary organs, geographical distribution, or the relation of recent with extinct animals in the same continent, although adaptation plus heredity can do so. See, e.g., B, pp. 12-15, 4647, 84, 98-99, 110-117, 130, 193-194, and C, pp. 76-17,99. 8. “Perfect Adaptation and Teleological Explanation: Approaches to the Problem of the History of Life in the Mid-Nineteenth Century,” Sfud. H&r. Biol., 2 (1978), 33-56. 9. This is only one of several sorts of “laws” that antiteleologists pointed to as being incompatible with the strictly teleological approach. Others include the lawr of geographical distribution and geological succession. See, e.g., Louis Agassiz. Essay on Classification (London: Longman, Brown, Green, Longmans, and Roberts and Trubner, 1859), chap. 1, where the teleological approach is criticized at length. 10. [Richard Owen], “Generalizations of Comparative Anatomy,” Quart. Rev., 93 (1853), 80; see also William B. Carpenter, Principles of General ana Compurative Physiology (London: John Churchill, 1839), p. 461. 214 Darwin after Malthus to its special office. On the contrary - the higher and more general are the laws regulating the structure of animals of which we can obtain a conception, the more will the Contemplative Mind be struck with the vastness of that designing intelligence which in originally ordaining them could produce such harmony and adaptation amongst their innumerable results.” According to such a view as this, the creator established laws in order to produce just those phenomena in this world that he desired, and it is from this, rather than a “principle of adaptation,” that the phenomena derive their perfection,. This is neither a doctrine of relative nor of imperfect adaptation. It is rather a doctrine of perfection limited by general laws. This was also Darwin’s view until he read Malthus.12 Darwin denied that organisms are “so closely adapted” as the teleologists assumed. l3 But he held that the product of transmutation is “complete adaptation.” l4 He imagined a great hierarchy of causes subordinate to causes, down to “certain laws of harmony” by which organisms “keep perfect.” l5 Together, the organic and inorganic worlds, with all their changes, constituted, in Darwin’s words,a “system of great harmony.” r6 So, while Darwin and many of his contemporaries abandoned the teleological interpretation of perfection characteristic of the school of Paley, they continued to share with that school a general view of the world, that it is a harmonious system, the creation of a benevolent God. Darwin’s adherence to the harmonious view of nature, which nowhere appears more clearly than in the weeks just before he read Malthus,” was not merely an unimportant survival from that youthful period when he was captivated by Paley’s arguments. On the contrary, it informs the whole of his early speculations on transmutation. Darwin’s 11. Richard Owen MSS, Hunterian Lectures for 1838, Royal College of Surgeons. 12. This was first suggested to me by Kohn’s study. He argues that throughout the pre-Malthus period, Darwin’s concept of adaptation was a revision, rather than a rejection, of the Paleyan idea of perfect adaptation (“Path to Natural Selection,” pp. 84-87, 157). My own study of the notebooks confirms that Darwin’s pre-Malthus position was identical to the antiteleological version of perfect adaptation I described in “Perfect Adaptation,” cited above. 13. B, p. 130. 14. B, p. 210e. 15. D, pp. 36-37. 16. D, p. 74e. 17. D, pp. 36-37 (Aug. 16, 1838); D, p. 74e (Sept. 8, 1838). 21.5 DOV OSPOVAT usual way of proceeding in the transmutation notebooks was to inquire “what is the final cause” of each mechanism or process he examined. The final cause of transmutation was, for Darwin, the maintenance of harmony; and the principal problem he set himself was to find the means by which adaptation is preserved amidst the changes of the external world. This is the burden of the opening pages of the B notebook. Darwin was convinced from an early stage that the key to the solution was the process of generation. His argument for this is in the form of an answer to the question: what is the purpose of generation? l8 We know, he said, that the world goes through cycles of changes in temparature and all the circumstances that influence living beings. Full-grown individuals with futed organizations might be unable to adapt themselves to new conditions. Therefore, generation exists “to adapt and alter the race to changing world.” l9 Darwin’s theory of generation, which has been ably discussed by David Kohnzo is much too complex to go into here, but its essential character may be simply enough stated. A change in the conditions under which an organism lives affects its reproductive system, causing it to produce varying offspring. These variations differ from their parents in ways that serve to adapt them to the new circumstances; that is, the generative system automatically produces offspring that are adapted to the changed conditions.*l This remained Darwin’s view throughout the pre-Malthus period. A second major part of Darwin’s solution, introduced in the C notebook, is the notion that environmental changes induce changes in habits, and these in turn cause changes in structure.22 This Lamarckian theory is in one fundamental respect similar to Darwin’s theory of generation: both theories postulate an automatic organic response to changes in inorganic conditions. They describe mechanisms by which nature provides that geological change does not disrupt the adaptation 18. B, p. 2. “Why is life short, why such high object - generation.” 19. B, pp. 2-4 (Darwin’s emphasis). 20. “Path to Natural Selection,” pp. 52-61, 90-135. 21. This character of Darwin’s theory of generation was noted by Gruber in the B notebook, but he concluded that it had disappeared before Darwin read Malthus; Darwin on Man, p. 157. See, however, C, p. 236, D, pp. 166-167, and D, p. 175, where Darwin seems to restate his early views. 22. See especially C, pp. 51, 62-63, 124, 163, 171-173, 199 and D, p. 107. Although this appears to be scarcely compatible with Darwin’s theory of adaptation by generation, Darwin treated his two theories as complementary; see D, pp. 174e-177. Sandra Herbert and David Kohn have both emphasized Darwin’s adoption of Lamarckian views in 1838; Herbert, “Man, Part II,” p. 204; Kohn, “Path to Natural Selection,” pp. 126-l 32. 216 Darwin after Malthus of the organic to the inorganic world.23 In this, both reflect Darwin’s commitment to the harmonious view. From this too-brief glance at Darwin’s early speculations we can see that the idea of harmony furnished not only the final cause of transmutation, but also the framework and constraints within which Darwin’s mechanisms operated. Transmutation here is not constant and ubiquitous change. It occurs only in response to environmental change, which, by causing organisms to be less well adapted, triggers the production of new, well adapted forms. It is this pattern and this limited action of the mechanism for change that we find carried over into the post-Malthus period. “THE FINAL CAUSE OF ALL THIS WEDGING” The notebook passages in which Darwin recorded his new insight upon reading Malthus so obviously contain the basic elements of the theory of natural selection that we are prone to see in them virtually the whole of Darwin’s mature theory, with its emphasis on chance, struggle, and imperfection. But if we read these passages not from the perspective of 1859, but from that of 1838, they appear in a different light. The sentence in which the new theory is announced is itself an unambiguous reiteration of the harmonious view of nature. After describing the “warring of the species” that must result from the pressure of population, Darwin wrote, “The final cause of all this wedging, must be to sort out proper structure, & adapt it to changes, - to do that for form, which Malthus shows is the find effect (by means however of volition) of this populousness on the energy of man.“24 This passage points directly to the hopeful, or harmonious, interpretation of the principle of population that was common to Malthus and to the natural theologians of Darwin’s day. Darwin had already encountered several varieties of this interpretation elsewhere. He found it, for instance, in Paley’s Natural 7heoZogy, and in William Kirby’s Bridgewater Treatise, in each of which it took a somewhat different form.25 Its principal element in Malthus’s Essay is the proposition that superfecundity promotes useful human activity. 23. The preservation of harmony was not, of course, the only function of these mechanisms. Darwin wanted to believe, for instance, that the generative process operated in such a way as to assure organic progress and, ultimately, the production of man; see D, pp. 49, 57-58. 24. D, pp. 134-135e (my italics). 25. William Paley, Natural Theology, ed. Charles Bell and Lord Brougham, 217 DOV OSPOVAT Malthus is remembered chiefly for his pessimism. But he, like most of the political economists of his school, supposed that society runs according to divinely appointed laws, which laws must, therefore, be on the whole good. The enunciator of such laws frequently chose not merely to explain their operation, but to show how they fit into the established order of things - or, what is their final cause. In the case of a law such as the principle of population, which could be seen to have unpleasant effects, it was further necessary to explain how this partial evil was conducive to universal good. This was especially important for Malthus, who aimed to persuade the poor by such an argument that riotous behavior and insubordination could not improve their condition.26 In the first edition of his Essay Malthus devoted the two concluding chapters to natural theological reasoning on his principle, an attempt, as he put it, to give a view of the situation of man on earth that is consistent with our ideas of the “power, goodness, and foreknowledge of the Diety.“*’ In subsequent editions these chapters were dropped and the natural theology distributed into several other parts of the Essay. The bulk of it came to rest in Book IV. There Malthus argued that the human activity that produces all the advantages and improvements of civilized life is the result of the powerful and universal desire for food, clothing, houses, and so forth. But this desire alone is an insufficient stimulus to elicit the sort of actions that the creator’s purposes require: The desire of the means of subsistence would be comparatively confined in its effects, and would fail of producing that general 2 ~01s. (New York: Harper and Bros., 1839), 11, 138-139, 147-156; William Kirby, On the Power, Wisdom, and Goodness of God, as Manifested in the Creation of Animals, and in Their History, Habits, and Instincts, rev. ed. by T. R. Jones, 2 ~01s. (London: H. G. Bohn, 1853), I, 157-159 (Darwin read Kirby during the periodin which he kept the B notebook;B, p. 141). John Bird Sumner, A Treatise on the Records of the Creation and on the Moral Attributes of the Creator, 6th ed. (London: J. Hatchard and Son, 1850), pp. 214-275, also includes a discussion harmonizing Malthus and natural theology. Darwin read his Evidence of Christianity (see Gruber, Darwin on Man, pp. 125-I 26) and may have known his Treatise (first edition, 1816). On the hopeful interpretation of Malthus, see Robert Young. “Malthus and the Evolutionists: The Common Context of Biological and Social Theory,“Past andpresent no. 43 (May 1969), 109-145. 26. Thomas Robert Malthus, An Essay on the Principle of Population: or a View of Its Past and Present Effects on Human Happiness, 3rd ed., 2 ~01s. (London: J. Johnson, 1806), II, 498499. 27. Thomas Robert Malthus, An Essay on the Principle of Population (1st ed.), ed. Philip Appleman (New York: W. W. Norton, 1976), p. 116. 218 Darwin after Malthus activity so necessary to the improvement of the human faculties, were it not for the strong and universal effort of population to increase with greater rapidity than its supplies. If these two tendencies were exactly balanced, I do not see what motive there would be sufficiently strong to overcome the acknowledged indolence of man, and make him proceed in the cultivation of the ~oil.*~ This is clearly the discussion to which Darwin was referring when he wrote that population pressure in nature would “do that for form, which Malthus shows is the final effect . . . of this populousness on the energy of man.” For Malthus, the potential increase of population beyond the means of subsistence produces that human activity which is required to accomplish the creator’s aims. For Darwin, similarly, the final cause of populousness is the production of that constant adaptation of organisms to conditions which he believed to be characteristic of “this perfect world.“29 Influenced by the Darwin of the Origin of Species, we have grown accustomed to think of natural selection as necessarily implying a universe of imperfection and disharmony. It may have been this assumption that led Camille Limoges to argue that Darwin’s crucial step in constructing the theory of natural selection was the dismantling of the traditional conception of the economy of nature. This was accomplished, he argued, before Darwin’s reading of Malthus, that event merely serving to bring together the various elements of Darwins’s theory.30 David Kohn, who recognized that until he read Malthus Darwin saw nature as a harmonious system, identified the destruction of that conception as Malthus’s principal contribution to natural selection.31 But in fact there is in Darwin’s notebook entries for September 28 1838, no suggestion that he then ceased to believe in a “system of great harmony.” Instead, we find a direct analogy drawn between Darwin’s new theory and those arguments that Malthus used to incorporate the principle of population into that very system. For a month or two after he read Malthus Darwin continued to believe in a “perfect world,” whose changes, both inorganic and organic, 28. Malthus, Essay, 3rd ed., II, 315-316. 29. The quoted phrase is from E, p. 48. 30. Limoges, Sdlection nafurelle, pp. 77-80. Limoges did not distinguish between the two main varieties of perfect adaptation. He saw that Darwin abandoned the Paley-Bridgewater variety and took this to mean that Darwin gave up the harmonious view. 31. Kohn, “Path to Natural Selection,” pp. v, 144. 219 DOV OSPOVAT “ALL PARTS OF THE GREAT SYSTEM.“32 A comment on man from this period suggests that, as was true before he read Malthus, Darwin meant by “system” all of the laws, extending down to the lowest level, by which the creator achieved his purposes, including the existence of man. Man, he said, “is one great object for which the world was brought into present state.” The “law of transmutation” and the separation of sexes are means by which the creator has realized this object - which is to say that Darwin believed still that the ends were known before the system of laws was established.33 These same months, however, were the period when Darwin, according to his journal, “thought much upon religion.“34 He began to doubt whether he should “talk of Final causes.“35 And he concluded, presumably as a result of reflecting on the implications of natural selection, that the details of the system were the result of chance. The production of an intellectual being was perhaps inevitable, he said, but “what a chance it has been . . . that has made a man.“36 If it is chance that made man, he could hardly be considered a final cause of the laws of change. In a general way, Darwin continued to hold to the hopeful view of things even in the 1850s. The theodicy of the Origin is essentially the theodicy of Malthus: “From the war of nature, from famine and death, the most exalted object which we are capable of conceiving, namely, the production of the higher animals, directly follows.“37 But in the fall of 1838 Darwin seems to have come to believe that natural selection could not be reconciled with the supposition that the effects of particular laws are 32. E, p. 48; Darwin MSS, vol. 71, fois. 53-58, Cambridge University Library (these reading notes, transcribed by Paul Barrett, are published as “Essay on Theology and Natural Selection” in Gruber, Darwin on Man, pp. 416420). 33. E, pp. 49-51. 34. Gavin de Beer, ed., “Darwin’s Journal,” Bull. Brit. Mus. (Nat. Hist.), Hist. Ser., 2 (1959),8. 35. Darwin MSS, vol. 71, fol. 58, Cambridge University Library (Gruber, Darwin on Man, p. 4 19). 36. E, p. 68. Sandra Herbert (“Man, Part II,” p. 200) saysthat B, pp. 214215, indicates that Darwin at this time believed already that man “was accidental in his particulars.” I do not think B, pp. 214-215, implies this; and E, pp. 48-49, I think, clearly implies the contrary. 37. Darwin, Origin, p. 490. I see no reason to doubt, and several to credit, Darwin’s statement in the Autobiography that at the time he wrote the Origin he believed in “a First Cause having an intelligent mind in some degree analogous to that of man” and that this cause, not “blind chance or necessity,” was responsible for “this immense and wonderful universe”; he deserved, Darwin said, “to be called a Theist.” Nora Barlow, ed., The Autobiography of Charles Darwin, 18091882 (New York: W. W. Norton, 1958), pp. 92-93. 220 Darwin after Malthus could have been precisely known beforehand. From that point on, he held that the creator established “only general laws.” 38 THE PERSISTENCE OF PERFECTION Although Darwin gave up the idea that the details of the world were part of an original plan of creation, he did not for a long time seriously question one of the main assumptions of this conception of nature. In 1844 he continued to believe in perfect adaptation rather than the relative adaptation we find in the Origin of Species. There are several strands of evidence that may be drawn on to support this claim. Two are fairly straightforward but, though suggestive, are ultimately inconclusive. A third is more complex and more decisive. First, there is the fact that Darwin on numerous occasions in the “Essay of 1844” indicated that he considered perfect adaptation to be the norm in nature. Unless there is some change in external conditions to disrupt adaptation, organisms are perfectly suited for the situation in which they live. Geological changes, he said, result in organisms’ ceasing to be “so perfectly adapted . . . as they orginally were.“39 When an island is in process of formation and some plants or animals by chance arrive there, “it is impossible that the first few transported organisms could be perfectly adapted” to all the stations on the new island; “and it will be a chance if those successivelytransported will be so adapted. The greater number would probably come from the lowlands of the nearest country; and not even all these would be perfectly adapted to the new islet whilst it continued low and exposed to coast influences.“40 And again, while an archipelago is forming, its stations will not at first be occupied “by perfectly adapted species.“41 In all these instances perfect adaptation is treated as what is to be expected except when conditions are altered. There are, I should point out, other places in the “Essay” in which Darwin seems to deny perfect adaptation. In reading these, however, it is necessary to keep in mind the distinction between the teleologists’ conception of perfect adaptation and the idea of limited perfection that 38. F. Darwin, 39. Ibid., 1844, “Essay of 1844,” seems that this may 40. Ibid., 1844, 41. Ibid., 1844, ed., Foundations, 1844, p. 134. p. 91, Most of the argument in this section is based on the but examples are drawn from the “Sketch of 1842” when it make Darwin’s position clearer. p. 185. p. 196. 221 DOV OSPOVAT Darwin, Owen, and others espoused.42 To the teleologists, a perfectly adapted form was the best possible form for the conditions under which it lived. Antiteleologists, however, held that the perfection of organisms was limited by certain general laws, such as the law of adherence to a common type, or, in Darwin’s case, the laws of heredity. The idea of limited perfection is nicely expressed in some of Darwin’s early post-Malthus notes: “I look at every adaptation, as the surviving one of ten thousand trials. - each step being perfect - or nearly so (except in isld) although having hereditary superfluities, Man could exist without mammae - to the then existing conditions.“43 Perfection here is limited by the “hereditary superfluities.” In the pre-Malthus notebooks Darwin constantly argued against the teleologists’ explanations, and he continued to do so in the “Essay of 1844.” It is in this context alone that Darwin denied perfect adaptation, and it is the teleological concept of perfection that he denied. For instance, in discussing geographical distribution, Darwin was concerned to show that it could not be explained simply by the adaptation of organisms to external conditions. To prove the teleological explanation inadequate, he cited the case of introduced forms that compete successfully against the native inhabitants: I Although every species is admirably adapted (but not necessarily better adapted than every other species, as we have seen in the great increase of introduced species) to the country and station it frequents; yet it has been shown that the entire difference between the species in distant countries cannot possibly be explained by the difference of the physical conditions of these countries.44 This was a telling blow against the teleologists’ version of perfection, but it left untouched Darwin’s own: that within the limits imposed by the laws of heredity and the accidents of transportal, the native inhabitants are perfectly adapted. In Darwin’s theory of 1844 the natives cannot be further improved, for, being perfectly adapted, they do not vary. Only if some change in conditions causes them to be no longer perfectly adapted will natural selection begin to work. How far Darwin still was in 1844 from the idea that species are only 42. Seethe discussionabove. 43. Darwin MSS, vol. 71, fol. 58, Cambridge University Library (Gruber, Darwin on Man, p. 420. 44. F. Darwin, ed., Foundalions, 1844, p. 171; see also pp. 153-154, and 1842, p. 33n. 222 Darwin after Malthus relatively well adapted, in comparison with their competitors, can be seen by contrasting his conclusions on introduced forms in the “Essay” with those he drew in the Origin ofSpecies. In 1844 he said, “I mean by not being perfectly adapted, only that some few other organisms can generally be found better adapted to the country than some of the aborigines.” 45 In the Origin he added, significantly, “we may safely conclude that the natives might have been modified with advantage, so as to have better resisted such intruders.“% In 1859 Darwin interpreted the phenomenon to mean that the natives were not perfectly adapted in any meaningful sense. There is always room for improvement. In 1844 it meant only that the teleologists’ principle of adaptation was untenable, thus leaving the door open for Darwin’s rival explanation in terms of transmutation and transportal. A second, similar strand of evidence comes from Darwin’s description of the products of natural selection. “My theory,” he wrote, shortly after reading Malthus, “makes all organic beings perfectly adapted to all situations where in accordance to certain laws they can live.“47 The fullest discussion of the results of natural selection is in Darwin’s comparison of man’s selection with nature’s. This is a topic that first appeared in the E notebook in December 1838. “If nature . . . had the picking,” she could make a webbed-footed dog “far more easily than man.rr48 Domestic races, Darwin said, “are made by precisely same means as species - but latter far more perfectly & infinitely slower.” No domestic animal, however, “is perfectly adapted,” he said, implying that natural species are.49 In the “Essay of 1844” Darwin contrasted the imperfection of man’s techniques with the operation of the “natural law of selection.” Man, he said, selects chiefly by eye and cannot see whether the internal structure is well suited to the external. Nor can he detect shades of constitutional differences. He has bad judgment and he is capricious: he and his successorsdo not select for the same end for hundreds of generations. Man selects forms that are useful to him rather than those that are best adapted to the conditions under which they live. And he does not keep those conditions uniform. Frequently he is unwilling to destroy an animal which is not up to his standard. And he 45. 46. 47. L&win 48. 49. Ibid., 1844, p. 153. Darwin, Origin, p. 83. Darwin MSS, vol. 71, fols. on Man, p. 417). E, p. 63. E, p. 71; see also p. 75. 53-58, Cambridge University Library (Gruber, 223 DOV OSPOVAT often begins selecting with a sport that departs considerably from the parent form. Nature, by contrast, selects varieties that differ only slightly from the parent forms. Conditions are constant for long periods and change only slowly. Crossing rarely occurs. Nature never fails to destroy forms that are not well adapted and never selects forms unless they are better adapted than their parents. Nature’s selection is not capricious, but goes on steadily for thousands of years adapting the form to the same conditions. The selecting power works on internal structures as well as external, testing the whole organism during its whole life, and if it proves to be less well adapted than its congeners it is inevitably destroyed. “Every part of its structure is thus scrutinised and proved good towards the place in nature which it occupies.” It follows that nature’s productions will be far more perfect than man’s. In domesticated animals, selection for the same ends, steadily, for a number of generations, under suitable conditions, and without crossing, produces forms that are “true,” or subject to little variation. Nature’s forms must be incomparably “truer,” for they have been made by rigid and steady selection, without crossing, continued for thousands of years. The result is forms “excellently trained and perfectly adapted” to conditions. Such forms seldom vary, which Darwin believed to be one sure mark of a species.50 If not carefully examined, Darwin’s description of the process by which these perfectly adapted forms are produced might lead one to think that in 1844 he inconsistently believed at the same time in both perfect and relative adaptation. But this is not the case. When geological changes alter the conditions under which a species lives, or when individuals of a species are transported to a new region, the reproductive system is affected, and the species begins to vary. “Almost every part of the body,” he said, “would tend to vary from the typical form in slight degrees, and in no determinate way.” 51 The variations, that is, are not automatically adaptive, as he had formerly assumed. Some variant individuals will be better adapted than others to the new conditions, and they will have a better chance of survival. Here Darwin clearly is saying that there are differences in adaptedness; some organisms are better adapted, others “less well adapted.“52 But it is important to note that he is not speaking of species. Some variant individuals that 50. 51. 52. 224 F. Darwin, ed., Foundations, Ibid., 1844, p. 85. Ibid., 1844, p. 95. 1844, pp. 94-96. Darwin after Malthus occur under changed conditions will be better adapted than others and than the parent form, which, as a result of the change, ceases to be perfect. But species, the stable, true-breeding end products of selection, are perfectly, not relatively, adapted.53 Considered in isolation, all of the instances in which Darwin described adaptation as perfect would be of little moment, for one can easily imagine that he might have continued to use the term after he had abandoned the concept. 54 More revealing is evidence derived from the structure of Darwin’s theory in the “Essay of 1844,” from which it appears that perfect adaptation, far from being an empty phrase, was an assumption that governed how Darwin would understand the working of natural selection. The channel through which the assumption of perfect adaptation exerted its influence was Darwin’s theory of variation. This was but a slight modification of his pre-Malthus theory of generation. In the first three transmutation notebooks, Darwin suggested that external changes would destroy adaptation if they were not accompanied by corresponding organic changes. The balance was preserved, he thought, because external changes, by affecting the reproductive systems of organisms, cause them to produce offspring that are adapted to the new conditions. After he adopted the theory of natural selection, Darwin supposed that the generative process produces not new adaptations, but merely variations, on which natural selection works. But he continued to believe that offspring unlike their parents are produced only when the reproductive system has been influenced by external changes. This was his explanation of both variation under domestication and variation under nature in his two essaysof the 1840s. Under certain conditions, he said, speaking of domestication, organisms are altered during their individual lives, and these alterations may be passed on to future generations. Habits of body and mind, structural changes resulting from use and disuse of organs, effects of food, climate, and occupational diseases, and the tendency to contract some diseases may all be inherited. But these variations from the direct effect of conditions on individuals are “extremely rare compared with those which are congenital or which appear soon after birth.” These latter are “infinitely numerous,” and it is chiefly on them that the breeder 53. ferences Ibid., where, at the top of the page, Darwin assumes that there are difin the adaptednessof variant forms, while at the bottom of the page he assertsthat the speciesproduced by natural selectionare perfectly adapted. 54. The language of perfect adaptation does in fact occasionallycrop up in the Origin and later works. 225 DOV OSPOVAT works in order to make new races.55 The cause of these “congenital” variations, Darwin said, is “the accumulated effects of a change of all or some of the natural conditions of the life of the species.” 56 The indirect effect of these changes on the reproductive system causes the organization of the embryo to become “in a slight degree plastic,” and variations are produced.57 This same cause Darwin believed must also produce variation in nature: “Domestication seems to resolve itself into a change from the natural conditions of the species . . . if this be so, organisms in a state of nature must occasionally, in the course of ages,be exposed to analogous influences; for geology clearly shows that many places must, in the course of time, become exposed to the widest range of climatic and other influences.” 58 The slow changes from geological causes probably act on the reproductive organs during several generations before the accumulated effects cause the species to vary. Sometimes, however, a catastrophic geological change - “as when an isthmus at last separates” - or the dissemination of seeds into a new region will suddenly bring an organism into contact with new conditions and thus produce a tendency to vary.59 “The reproductive system would be affected, as under domesticity, and the struct&e of the offspring rendered in some degree plastic”; or, as he said in 1842, “the mould in which they are cast” would vary slightly. 6o The hereditary type, or “mould,” fixed and stabilized by the long-continued process of generation, would cease, under altered conditions, to govern rigidly the form of new individuals. This theory of variation, carried over with little change from Darwin’s pre-Malthus period, had two important consequences for the theory of natural selection. One is that it sharply limited the availability of materials on which natural selection might work. Geological conditions remain the same for long periods of time.61 And geological change is slow, so that only after a long time will its accumulated effects cause a 55. F. Darwin, ed., Foundations, 1844, pp. 57-59. 56. Ibid., 1844, pp. 77-78. 57. Ibid., 1844, pp. 62-63. 58. Ibid., 1844, p. 83 (Darwin’s emphasis). 59. Ibid., 1844, p. 84; see also 1842, pp. 4-5. 60. Ibid., 1844, p. 85; 1842, p. 5. Darwin supposed that even in the absence of significant external change individuals of a species might not always be exactly alike. But he thought they would vary chiefly in the “external and less important parts”; and for obvious reasons he did not base his theory on these differences. Under changed conditions, however, even the most essential parts of a plant’s or animal’s organization might vary (ibid., 1844, pp. 82-83, 85). 61. Ibid., 1844, p. 95. 226 Darwin after Malthus species to vary. Therefore, there can be very little variation among organisms in a state of nature. This Darwin stated again and again in the two essays of the 1840s: “Wild animals vary exceedingly little”;62 “the proverbial expression that no two animals or plants are born absolutely alike, is much truer when applied to those under domestication, than to those in a state of nature”$j3 “ most organic beings in a state of nature vary exceedingly little “;@ “the amount of variation [is] exceedingly small in most organic beings in a state of nature, and probably quite wanting (as far as our sensesserve) in the majority of cases.“65 This conclusion followed directly from Darwin’s belief that in the absence of external change organisms are perfectly adapted and so do not vary.66 The second consequence, closely related to the first, is that transmutation can occur only in those rare situations in which there is a change in conditions. At all other times population pressure merely operates to weed out misfits. This is not explicitly stated in the “Essay of 1844.” But in both the “Essay” and the “Sketch of 1842”, whenever he discussed variation or gave illustrations of the working of natural selection, Darwin stipulated that there is a change in conditions.67 At the end of the “Sketch” he went so far as to leave himself a note on the need to include a discussion from Lyell, or a reference to him, “to show that external conditions do vary” - a fact that virtually every geologist and naturalist in Darwin’s day fully admitted.@ 62. 63. 64. Ibid., 1842, p. 4. Ibid., 1844, p. 59. Ibid, 1844, p. 81. 65. Ibid., 1844, p. 83. 66. In one respect - the key role of external change - Darwin’s view of variaresembled closely the traditional idea that each species was endowed with some capacity to adapt to changes in its environment; that is, that its form was modified in response to alterations in external conditions. This was Lyell’s view; Principles of Geology, 5th ed., 2 ~01s. (Philadelphia: James Kay Jun. and Brother, 1837), I, 506-515 (Book III, chap. Ill). 67. F. Darwin, Foundations, 1842, pp. l-2,4-5, 8-9,13-15 (Darwin considered crossing to be the equivalent of a change in conditions), 20, 21,30-31, 32-33, 34n, 37; 1844, pp. 57-76, 83,84-85,90-92, 110, 120, 122,145, 153-154, 183-194. 68. Ibid., 1842, p. 53. In Chapter II of the “Essay” Darwin indicated most clearly his view of the difference between the situation in which conditions are changing and that in which they remain the same. Population pressureoperates continually to produce struggle in nature. But with “external conditions remaining the same,” the result of the struggle is stability: each individual of each species merely “holds its place.” However, when “external conditions . . change,” the original inhabitants cease to be perfectly adapted; the change causes variation; and selection favors the variant forms that are better adapted to the new conditions (ibid., pp. 90-91). tion 227 DOV OSPOVAT Francis Darwin long ago called attention to differences between the “Essay of 1844” and the Origin of Species on the questions of the amount of variation in nature and the need for external change to induce variation. The latter contrast was noted by Huxley, too.69 But neither had any inkling of the explanation of the differences, which is simply that in 18.59 Darwin no longer believed in perfect adaptation. In the Origin Darwin said that there was much variability in nature, and he supposed that no change in conditions is necessary for variation and transmutation to occur.7o In 1844 he believed that there is little variation and that changes in conditions are necessary; and this was because in 1844 he still believed that in the absence of change organisms are perfectly adapted. In essence, the effect of change on the reproductive system was, for Darwin, the effect of the organism’s no longer being perfectly adapted. Perfectly adapted organisms have no need to change, and so they do not vary. A passage from the E notebook, written in March 1839, says exactly this: “In the place where any species is most common, we need not look for change, because its numbers show it is perfectly adapted.” ” Seven years later Darwin’s opinion remained unaltered. A note dated “July [18]46” reads: “When new form introduced into island, it must not be perfectly adapted, else it will not vary.” 72 Darwin’s persistent belief in perfect adaptation dictated that the structure of his theory of transmutation in 1844 would be essentially the same as in the pre-Malthus notebooks. In the period of his early speculations, the purpose of transmutation was to preserve the harmonious adaptation of organisms to their environments. When external change threatened this adaptation, a natural mechanism was automatically called into play to maintain or restore it. The same pattern of 69. Ibid., pp. xxviii-xxix; 1844, p. 81n. 70. Darwin, Origin, pp. 45, 82-83, 113. See also Darwin’s letter to Asa Gray presented to the Linnean Society in 1858 (Gavin de Beer, ed., Evolurion by Nufurul Sekcrion [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 19581, p. 265). This did not mean that Darwin no longer thought it necessary to explain variation or thought that variation was inherent in the generative process; it meant merely that the causes of variation might be more subtle and more varied than he had formerly allowed - that is, variations did not occur only when a form ceased to be “so perfectly adapted” as it had been. 71.. E, p. 122e. In another passage the correlation between less-than-perfect adaptation and variability is drawn explicitly: “No domesticated animal is perfectly adapted to external conditions. - (hence great variation in each birth)” (E, p. 71). 72. Darwin MSS, vol. 16ii, fol. 303, Cambridge University Library. 228 Darwin after Malthus change characterizes the “Essay of 1844.” Before Malthus, Darwin’s mechanisms were the generation of new adaptations and the effect of changed habits. In the “Essay of 1844,” changes in conditions bring variation and natural selection into play. In both cases, the result is the same - the production of new, perfectly adapted forms. There can be no question that natural selection was a decisive breakthrough in Darwin’s theorizing about transmutation. It gave him a new and better mechanism than any he had considered previously for explaining change and adaptation in the organic world. Yet when Darwin’s intellectual progress is viewed from another angle it is evident that there is an underlying continuity in his thought, stretching from the opening pages of his first transmutation notebook, across the Malthusian divide, to beyond the “Essay of 1844”: Malthus and natural selection did not at once succeed in altering the natural theological structure of Darwin’s earliest theories;his new mechanism was mounted, so to speak, in an old housing. FROM 1844 TO 1859 The idea of relative adaptation in the Origin is perhaps the best indication of the extent to which Darwin’s views had by 1859 diverged from those of his fellow naturalists.73 By the same token, the idea of perfect adaptation in the essays of the 1840s is a fair measure of the extent to which Darwin’s views then still reflected the natural theological perspective of most of his contemporaries, the perspective which Darwin brought to the problem of organic change when he opened his first notebook in 1837. One very obvious implication of this is that in 1844 Darwin still had a long way to go before arriving at the position he adopted in the Origin of Species. I will not try to indicate what considerations finally led Darwin to the views we find in the Origin, except to say that I believe one crucial change was his abandoning at last the idea of perfect adaptation. By this I do not mean to imply that there was some single instant between 1844 and 1859 at which a clear break occurred. There is continuity in the development of Darwin’s theory after, as well as before, 1844. For instance, it was, I believe, at just the period when Darwin was moving toward the concept of relative adaptation that he wrote, “By Nature I mean the laws ordained by God to govern the Universe. “74 From this and other aspects of his theory of 73. Except Wallace. 74. Robert Stauffer, ed., Charles Darwin’s Cambridge University Press, 1975), p. 224. Natural Selection (Cambridge: 229 DOV OSPOVAT the 185Os, it appears that Darwin had not completely relinquished the conception of nature that we find in the early notebooks. But his speculations after 1844 gradually produced a new understanding of adaptation that had the effect of freeing natural selection, to a considerable degree, from the constraints I have described. This much said, it may be useful in conclusion to state in summary form some of the contrasts that reveal the distance that separates the Origin and the two essays of the 1840s. In 1844 Darwin believed that there is “exceedingly little” variation in nature; in 1859 he said that variation is common. In the “Sketch” he suggested that there is a common “mould” for all the members of a species; in 1859 he said, “No one supposes that all the individuals of the same species are cast in the very same mould.“75 In the “Essay” he believed that changes in external conditions were necessary to produce variation and transmutation; in the Origin he believed no change was necessary. In 1844 he supposed that transmutation would probably occur “only rarely” and “in some few districts:’ m . the Origin he thought there was no country in which it might not be going on even now.76 In 1844 he believed in perfect adaptation; by 1859 he believed that “organic beings seem to be perfect only in that degree required by our theory, namely to be enabled to struggle with all competitors in their native country.“77 This last contrast, I believe, is the fundamental one, for in it lies a large part of the explanation of all the others. Acknowledgments I am deeply indebted to David Kohn, without whose dissertation and conversation I would never have undertaken a serious examination of the development of Darwin’s theory; and to Sydney Smith, who introduced me to the Darwin collection at Cambridge University Library and has assisted me in numerous ways since then. My thanks are due also to all who participated in the discussion of this paper at the meeting of the History of Science Society at Madison, Wisconsin, in October 1978. Part of the research for the paper was conducted with the help of a Maude Hammond Fling summer research fellowship from the University of Nebraska. 75. Darwin, Origin, p. 45. The alteration in Darwin’s view on this point was due at least in part to his work on barnacles; Francis Darwin, ed., Life and Letters of Charles Darwin, 2 ~01s.(New York: D. Appleton, 1888), I, 397. 76. Darwin, Origin, pp. 82-83. 77. The quotation is from Natural Selection, 102, for the same idea less clearly expressed. 230 p. 386; see Origin, pp. 82-83,