* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Basic Concepts and Distinctions - The University of Texas at Arlington
Survey
Document related concepts
Gettier problem wikipedia , lookup
Watchmaker analogy wikipedia , lookup
Evolutionary argument against naturalism wikipedia , lookup
Teleological argument wikipedia , lookup
Index of logic articles wikipedia , lookup
Truth-bearer wikipedia , lookup
Transcript
Basic Concepts and Distinctions1 Logic Keith Burgess-Jackson 25 August 2016 1. Logic is the science (study) of validity.2 2. Validity (to be explained more fully below) is a property (i.e., feature or characteristic) of deductive arguments. Some deductive arguments possess this (desirable) property and some do not. Those that possess it are said to be valid. Those that do not possess it are said to be invalid. 3. An argument (deductive or otherwise) consists of two or more propositions, one of which, the conclusion, is claimed (by the arguer) to follow from the other or others, the premises. The premises are said to provide reasons, evidence, grounds, or support for the conclusion. The act or process of arguing is known as argumentation.3 4. Every argument, by definition, involves a claim (by the arguer) that its conclusion follows from its premise(s). Some claims are stronger than others: a. If one’s claim is that the conclusion cannot be false, given the truth of the premises, then one’s argument is deductive. b. If one’s claim is that the conclusion is unlikely to be false, given the truth of the premises, then one’s argument is inductive. Deduction is to necessity as induction is to probability.4 What follows is a deductive argument (for almost certainly the arguer in question would I thank my colleague Dan Giberman for helpful comments on this handout. See the Appendix for alternative definitions of “logic.” There is no canonical definition of the term. 3 There is a close connection between inference and argumentation, but the processes (activities) are not identical. Inference, or reasoning, is the (psychological) process by which one draws a conclusion from one or more premises. For example, I may infer from the fact that the roads are icy this morning that UTA will be closed today. Argumentation, by contrast, is interpersonal. To argue is to try to persuade (or convince) someone (perhaps everyone) to accept or believe a particular proposition. When an inference is expressed (i.e., formulated) as an argument, it can be evaluated with the tools of logic. I will focus on arguments in the remainder of this handout, but much of what I say about arguments can also be said about inferences. 4 D:N::I:P. We might also say that deduction is to induction as necessity is to probability, or D:I::N:P. 1 2 1 claim that the truth of the premises necessitates the truth of the conclusion): All mammals are animals. All dogs are mammals. Therefore, All dogs are animals. Here, by way of contrast, is an inductive argument (for almost certainly the arguer in question would not claim that the truth of the premises necessitates the truth of the conclusion): Most professors are atheists. Jones is a professor. Therefore, Jones is an atheist. Strictly speaking, only deductive arguments are valid or invalid. We may, if we like, say that all inductive arguments are invalid, but this is misleading, for it implies that there is something wrong with inductive arguments. There is nothing wrong with inductive arguments. Some inductive arguments are cogent, in the sense that (a) they have true premises and (b) their premises make their conclusions probable. Example: “Most dogs have a tail of at least one inch in length; Shelbie is a dog; therefore, Shelbie has a tail of at least one inch in length.” Perhaps it’s best to say that the terms “valid” and “invalid” don’t apply to inductive arguments, i.e., that inductive arguments are neither valid nor invalid. They belong in category 3 of the following taxonomy:5 5 A taxonomy is a classification scheme. The taxonomy in the text is both jointly exhaustive and mutually exclusive (because of how the categories are defined). To say that it is jointly exhaustive is to say that every argument goes in at least one of its three categories. To say that it is mutually exclusive is to say that no argument goes in more than one of its three categories. It follows that every argument goes in exactly one of its three categories. Every argument, in other words, is either (1) a valid (i.e., truth-preserving) deductive argument, (2) an invalid (i.e., non-truth-preserving) deductive argument, or (3) an argument that is neither valid nor invalid. Category 3 could, of course, be subdivided, for it contains all inductive arguments, some of which are cogent (such as the one in the text) and some of which are not cogent (e.g., “Eighty-five percent of the readers of the New York Times oppose capital punishment; therefore, 85% of Americans oppose capital punishment”). 2 Arguments Valid 1 Not Valid Invalid 2 Not Invalid 3 5. Ideally, one would like one’s argument to have both of the following properties: necessity and informativeness. That is, one would like one’s conclusion (a) to follow necessarily from one’s premises and (b) to “go beyond” one’s premises in terms of the amount of information conveyed. Unfortunately, no argument can have both of these properties. To get necessity, one must forgo informativeness. To get informativeness, one must forgo necessity. Let us see why. In a (valid) deductive argument, the conclusion may contain either the same amount of information as the conjunction of the premises or less information than the conjunction of the premises, but it may not contain more information than the conjunction of the premises. Consider the following classic argument: All men (i.e., human beings) are mortal. Socrates is a man (i.e., a human being). Therefore, Socrates is mortal. The conclusion, which is about a particular human being (namely, Socrates), contains less information than the conjunction of the premises. (The first premise alone contains information about many human beings.) Now consider a typical inductive argument: On nine of the past 10 occasions in which weather conditions were as they are now, it rained within six hours. Therefore, It will rain within six hours. The conclusion contains more information than the premise. The premise is about the past; the conclusion is about the future. We might say that deduction purchases necessity at the cost of informativeness, whereas induction purchases informativeness at the cost of necessity.6 Both types of argument confer knowledge: 6 See Wesley C. Salmon, The Foundations of Scientific Inference (Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1967), 8. 3 a. The knowledge conferred by deduction consists in making explicit (in the conclusion) what is implicit (in the premises). b. The knowledge conferred by induction consists in extrapolating (in the conclusion) from what is already known (in the premises). We may think of the choice between necessity and informativeness as the tragedy of logic, because in one of its senses the word “tragedy” means “a sad event” or “a calamity.”7 The calamity is that we can’t have everything we want or need.8 6. Propositions have truth values. In this course, we shall assume that there are two (and only two) truth values: ‘true’ and ‘false.’9 Here are two Laws of Thought:10 a. Every proposition is either true or false, i.e., the truth values ‘true’ and ‘false’ are jointly exhaustive (this is known as the Law of Excluded Middle or, more precisely, the Law of Bivalence); and b. No proposition is both true and false, i.e., the truth values ‘true’ and ‘false’ are mutually exclusive (this is known as the Law of Noncontradiction).11 Sentences, unlike propositions, are linguistic entities, which means that they are always in particular languages, such as English, German, Swahili, or Latin. Propositions, which are in no particular language, are what indicative (declarative) sentences express, assert, or signify.12 Two different indicative (declarative) sentences (e.g., “John loves Mary” and “Mary is loved by John” [both of which are in English], or “It is raining” and “Il pleut” [the former of which is in English, the latter of which is in The Oxford American Dictionary and Language Guide (1999), 1068. You may have heard the term “tragic choice.” Suppose two or more people need life-saving medicine, but that I, a physician, have only enough medicine for one of them. Obviously, I would like to save all the needy people, and would do so if I could, but the situation constrains me. I must make a tragic choice. 9 In what is called a “many-valued logic,” there are more than two truth values. 10 Strictly speaking, they are implications or entailments of the Laws of Thought, but we will ignore that complication here. 11 While every proposition is either true or false and no proposition is both true and false, it doesn’t follow that we always know which truth value a given proposition has. Take the proposition that Abraham Lincoln thought about his son Robert five seconds before he (Abraham) was shot. This proposition is either true or false and it is not both true and false, but we will probably never know its truth value. (Query: What would constitute evidence for its truth? What would constitute evidence for its falsity?) 12 Sentence is to proposition as numeral is to number. 7 8 4 French]) can express, assert, or signify the same proposition. This is called synonymy.13 A given indicative (declarative) sentence (e.g., “Jones is happy”) can express, assert, or signify different propositions, depending on such things as (a) when it is uttered (Jones may be happy at one time but not at another) and (b) what its terms (e.g., “Jones”) refer to (Adam Jones may be happy while Andruw Jones is not). This is called ambiguity. 7. A valid argument is a deductive argument that has the following (desirable) property (i.e., feature or characteristic): it is logically impossible for its premises to be true while its conclusion is false. (If it is logically possible for a given argument’s premises to be true while its conclusion is false, then the argument is invalid.) Valid arguments are truth-preserving: a. If the premises of a valid argument are true, then its conclusion must be true as well. b. If the conclusion of a valid argument is false, then at least one of its premises must be false as well. Note that there can be a valid argument with false premises as well as an invalid argument with true premises. An example of the former is: Texas is east of the Mississippi River. Therefore, Something is east of the Mississippi River. An example of the latter is: Something is east of the Mississippi River. Therefore, Texas is east of the Mississippi River. Note also that, while all valid arguments are deductive, not all deductive arguments are valid. What makes an argument deductive (as we saw earlier) is the strength of the claim being made by the arguer. What makes a deductive argument valid (we are now seeing) is the correctness of the claim being made by the arguer. This course is concerned exclusively with deduction. If you wish to study induction, you should take 13 Some people refer to it as “synonymity.” 5 Fundamentals of Reasoning (PHIL 1301).14 8. Validity is valuable (i.e., worthy of being valued, not merely capable of being valued) for the sake of what it preserves, namely, truth. It is not valuable for its own sake.15 Truth (i.e., true belief) is valuable because it is essential to knowledge. (One can’t know falsehoods, though one can believe falsehoods.) Knowledge is valuable because it is a component of the good life. As the Greek philosopher Socrates long ago put it (according to his disciple Plato), “The unexamined life is not worth living.”16 9. Any argument that has a valid form is a valid argument. If one’s aim is to produce valid arguments, therefore, it is in one’s interest to know as many valid argument forms as possible. We will examine (i.e., you will learn) 93 valid argument forms in this course: 35 in categorical logic, 40 in propositional logic, and 18 in predicate logic. 10. The form of an argument is its skeleton—the part that remains after the flesh has been removed. For example, the form of the argument “No dogs are cats; therefore, no cats are dogs” is “No Ø are Ψ; therefore, no Ψ are Ø.” Another argument with the same form as this is “No animals are dogs; therefore, no dogs are animals.” This shows that there can be two or more arguments of (with) the same form. (We might say that each of them instantiates the form.) Since validity has to do solely with the form of an argument (and not with its content, matter, or substance), if two arguments have the same specific form, then either both of them are valid or both of them are invalid.17 14 The two courses may be taken in any order; neither, in other words, is a prerequisite for the other. Some people disparage Fundamentals of Reasoning (which at some universities is known as Critical Thinking or Informal Logic) as “baby logic.” That’s like saying that abnormal psychology is “baby psychology” or that microeconomics is “baby economics.” The two types of logic are distinct but equally important. I recommend that both courses be taken by every student. 15 In other words, validity is extrinsically or instrumentally valuable, not intrinsically valuable. Validity is a means to an end, not an end in itself. In this respect, validity is like money and unlike, say, friendship, knowledge, pleasure, or beauty. 16 See Plato’s Apology. 17 This is the basis of what is known as refutation by logical analogy. If one’s aim is to refute a particular argument (call it “A”), one may do so by thinking up a second argument (call it “B”) that (1) has the same specific form as A but (2) has true premises and a false conclusion. The fact that B has true premises and a false conclusion shows that it is invalid, for, by definition, no valid argument has true premises and a false conclusion; the fact that B has the same specific form as A shows that A, like B, is invalid. Do not confuse refutation with rebuttal. To refute is to prove the invalidity of a given argument. “Refutation” is a success term. One can attempt to refute an argument but 6 11. A sound argument is a valid argument all of whose premises are true. It follows from this definition that: a. All sound arguments have true conclusions. (Note the difference between x following from a definition and x being part of a definition.)18 b. Any argument that is invalid is unsound. c. Any argument that has a false premise (even one) is unsound. A given argument may be invalid and have a false premise. Such an argument has two defects: one of them formal (invalidity) and the other material or substantive (a false premise). Here is an example of a doubly defective argument: Keith’s automobile is green. Therefore, Everything is green. As a matter of fact, Keith’s automobile is not green; but even if it were green, it would not follow that everything is green.19 Here, in the form of a taxonomy (of deductive arguments), is a summary of this section: Valid Invalid All Premises True Sound Unsound Not All Premises True Unsound Unsound 12. Validity and soundness are all or nothing, not matters of degree. (Figuratively speaking, they are digital, not analog.) A given deductive fail to do so, just as one can attempt to refute an argument and succeed in doing so. “Rebut,” by contrast, is not a success term. To rebut is to push back against something—with no implication that the pushing succeeds (or fails, for that matter). Refutation may be thought of as successful rebuttal. 18 Suppose I put the following true-false question on an examination: “By definition, all sound arguments have true conclusions.” The answer to this question is “false.” While it’s true that all sound arguments have true conclusions, it’s not true by definition. The definition of “sound argument” makes no reference to the conclusion of the argument, much less to the conclusion being true. The definition of “sound argument” makes reference to two things: (1) validity; and (2) the truth of the premises. When you put these two components of the definition together, it follows that all sound arguments have true conclusions. 19 If one’s aim is to criticize (i.e., find fault with) another person’s argument, one should point out all its defects, formal as well as material. Conversely, if one is making an argument, one should ensure not only that one’s conclusion follows from one’s premises (i.e., that it has a truth-preserving form), but that one’s premises are (in fact) true. 7 argument is either valid or invalid, sound or unsound. It makes no sense to say, of a deductive argument, that it is “almost valid” or “almost sound,” or that one deductive argument is “valider,” “more valid,” “sounder,” or “more sound” than another. If a given deductive argument has 1,000,000 premises and 999,999 of them are true (the remaining premise being false), then the argument is unsound, just as it would be if all 1,000,000 premises were false. As the old saying goes, “close” doesn’t count except in horseshoes and hand grenades. Here, then, is our final taxonomy of arguments: Arguments Deductive Inductive Valid Sound 1 Invalid Unsound 2 3 4 The taxonomy is jointly exhaustive in that every argument is in at least one of its four categories. Every argument, in other words, is either (1) sound (i.e., a valid deductive argument with true premises), (2) unsound (i.e., a valid deductive argument with at least one false premise), (3) invalid (i.e., a deductive argument that is not truth-preserving), or (4) inductive (i.e., an argument that is not deductive). The taxonomy is mutually exclusive in that no argument is in more than one of its four categories (i.e., every argument is in at most one of its four categories). It follows that every argument is in exactly one of the taxonomy’s four categories. 13. Specialists in logic are known as logicians.20 Logicians, as such, have no expertise in determining which propositions are true and which false—unless, of course, the propositions in question are true or false simply by virtue of their form (such as “God exists or God does not exist,” which is true by virtue of its form, and “God exists and God does not exist,” which is false by virtue of its form).21 Logicians are, however, expert in determining which arguments (argument forms) are valid, for logic, as we saw at the outset, is the science (study) of validity.22 20 Specialists in magic are known as magicians—which is not to say that logic has anything to do with magic! 21 Propositions that are true by virtue of their form are called “tautologies.” Propositions that are false by virtue of their form are called “self-contradictions.” We will have more to say about tautologies and self-contradictions in due course. 22 People who are not expert in a given field should defer to those who are. If you are not a logician, then you should defer to logicians on matters within the scope of their expertise, just as, if you are not a biologist, you should defer to biologists on matters within 8 Appendix: Definitions of “Logic” “The general science of inference.” Simon Blackburn, The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy, 2d ed. revised, Oxford Paperback Reference (New York: Oxford University Press, 2008), 212. Gregory Pence, A Dictionary of Common Philosophical Terms (New York: McGraw-Hill, 2000), 31. “[T]he branch of philosophy that examines the correctness of rational inference, the ways we think, and the limitations of such inferences.” “Loosely speaking, logic is the process of correct reasoning, and something is logical when it makes sense. Philosophers often reserve this word for things having to do with various theories of correct reasoning.” “The scope of the term ‘logic’ has varied widely from writer to writer through the centuries. But these varying scopes seem all to enclose a common part: the logic which is commonly described, vaguely, as the science of necessary inference.” “Logic is the study of principles of reasoning. It is concerned not with how people actually reason, Robert M. Martin, The Philosopher’s Dictionary, 3d ed. (Orchard Park, NY: Broadview Press, 2002), 182. Willard Van Orman Quine, Elementary Logic, rev. ed. (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1980), 1. Warren Goldfarb, Deductive Logic (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 2003), xiii. the scope of their expertise. Expertise does not automatically transfer from one field to another, so the fact that a particular individual is expert in field X does not mean that that individual is expert in field Y. Many people (sadly) are expert in nothing. (A person of this sort is said to be a “jack of all trades, master of none.”) Some people are expert in more than one field. I have a friend (Robert “Bob” Schopp, who teaches at the University of Nebraska) who has three advanced degrees: a Ph.D. in psychology, a Ph.D. in philosophy, and a J.D. (law). He works at the intersection of these three fields—on such topics as the criminal defenses of insanity and automatism. People who are expert in more than one field—especially people who are expert in multiple fields—are known as “polymaths.” Aristotle (384322 BCE), Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646-1716), and Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) were polymaths. 9 but rather with how people ought to reason if they wish to ensure the truth of their results.” “Logic is the study of the methods and principles used to distinguish good (correct) from bad (incorrect) reasoning.” “Logic deals with arguments and inferences. One of its main purposes is to provide methods for distinguishing those that are logically correct from those that are not.” “Logical inference leads from premises—statements assumed or believed for whatever reason— to conclusions which can be shown on purely logical grounds to be true if the premises are true. Techniques to this end are a primary business of logic. . . .” “Logic as a distinctive science is concerned . . . with the relation of implication between propositions. Thus the specific task of logic is the study of the conditions under which one proposition necessarily follows and may therefore be deduced from one or more others, regardless of whether the latter are in fact true.” “Logic may be defined as the organized body of knowledge, or science, that evaluates arguments.” “[T]he subject matter of symbolic logic is merely logic—the principles which govern the validity of inference.” “It is quite common for people to concentrate on the individual statements in an argument and Irving M. Copi, Introduction to Logic, 7th ed. (New York: Macmillan Publishing Company, 1986), 3. Wesley C. Salmon, Logic, 3d ed. (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: PrenticeHall, 1984), 1. W. V. Quine, Methods of Logic, 4th ed. (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1982), 53 (italics in original). Morris R. Cohen and Ernest Nagel, An Introduction to Logic (New York: Harcourt, Brace & World, 1962), 8 (italics in original). Patrick J. Hurley, A Concise Introduction to Logic, 11th ed. (Boston: Wadsworth, 2012), 1. Clarence Irving Lewis and Cooper Harold Langford, Symbolic Logic, 2d ed. (New York: Dover Publications, 1959), 3 (italics in original). Stan Baronett, Logic, 3d ed. (New York: Oxford University Press, 2016), 3. 10 investigate whether they are true or false. Since people want to know things, the actual truth or falsity of statements is important; but it is not the only important question. Equally important is the question ‘Assuming the premises are true, do they support the conclusion?’ This question offers a glimpse of the role of logic, which is the study of reasoning, and the evaluation of arguments.” “Logic is the study of reasoning.” “Logic may be broadly defined as the study of methods for determining whether or not a conclusion has been correctly drawn from a set of assumptions.” “Logic in general is the science and art of right thinking.” “The study of the validity of different kinds of inference.” “[T]he science of reasoning, proof, thinking, or inference.” “Logic is concerned with the principles of valid inference. . . .” “Logic is concerned with what makes reasoning good and what makes arguments valid.” Daniel Bonevac, Simple Logic (New York: Oxford University Press, 1999), 2. Joseph Bessie and Stuart Glennan, Elements of Deductive Inference: An Introduction to Symbolic Logic (Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Publishing Company, 2000), 1. Raymond J. McCall, Basic Logic: The Fundamental Principles of Formal Deductive Reasoning, 2d ed., College Outline Series (New York: Barnes & Noble, 1952), xvii. Boruch A. Brody, “Logical Terms, Glossary of,” in The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Paul Edwards (New York: Macmillan Publishing Company, 1967), 5:57-77, at 67. The Oxford American Dictionary and Language Guide (New York: Oxford University Press, 1999), 583. William Kneale and Martha Kneale, The Development of Logic (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1962), 1. Tom Tymoczko and Jim Henle, Sweet Reason: A Field Guide to 11 “The province of logic must be restricted to that portion of our knowledge which consists of inferences from truths previously known; whether those antecedent data be general propositions, or particular observations and perceptions. Logic is not the science of Belief, but the science of Proof, or Evidence. In so far as belief professes to be founded on proof, the office of logic is to supply a test for ascertaining whether or not the belief is well grounded. With the claims which any proposition has to belief on the evidence of consciousness, that is, without evidence in the proper sense of the word, logic has nothing to do.” Modern Logic (New York: W. H. Freeman and Company, 1995), 1. John Stuart Mill, A System of Logic Ratiocinative and Inductive: Being a Connected View of the Principles of Evidence and the Methods of Scientific Investigation, Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, vol. VII (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1974 [first published in 1843]), 9. 12