* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download From Exclusivity to Concurrence
Supreme Court of Pakistan wikipedia , lookup
R (Miller) v Secretary of State for Exiting the European Union wikipedia , lookup
Judicial review in English law wikipedia , lookup
Separation of powers wikipedia , lookup
Judicial review in the United States wikipedia , lookup
Separation of powers under the United States Constitution wikipedia , lookup
Early stage draft of November 20, 2008 (10:51am) Please do not cite or quote without author’s permission. As you’ll see, I’ve not yet completed the article – parts remain to be written. I apologize in advance for not providing a final product. FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE Mark D. Rosen* INTRODUCTION . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2 I. THE ANALYTICS OF CONCURRENCE, AND SOME EXAMPLES . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7 A. B. C. II. THE HISTORICAL TRAJECTORY FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 20 A. B. C. D. E. III. Original Jurisdiction of the Various Federal Courts: The Road from Marbury to Ames . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 20 Fact-Finding in Civil Adjudication: Of Juries, Judges, and Non-Article III Adjudicative Tribunals . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 23 1. Juries and Judges . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 23 2. Juries and non-Article III Adjudicatory Tribunals . . 29 Adjudicatory Jurisdiction of Article III and non-Article III Courts . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 34 Legislative Power: Congress and Agencies . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 40 Some other Contexts . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 44 HOW AND WHY CONCURRENCE IS CREATED . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 44 A. B. * Definitions and Examples . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7 Analytical Tools . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11 1. Same-Effect versus Same-Source Concurrence . . . . 11 2. Non-Identicality. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 16 3. Imperfect Overlap. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 17 The Pacificus-Helvidius Debates . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 17 Mechanisms for Creating Concurrence . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1. Delegation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2. Inherency . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3. Inactivity and Initiative-Taking . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Reasons for Concurrence. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1. What The Courts Have Said . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 45 45 45 46 49 49 Professor and Norman & Edna Freehling Scholar, Chicago-Kent College of Law, Illinois Institute of Technology. I received outstanding comments from a faculty workshop at the Chicago-Kent College of Law and additional helpful words from Allan Erbsen and Nancy Marder. 2. 5. 6. a. Pragmatics and Past Practice . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 49 b. Efficiency . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 52 Systematizing Concurrence’s Benefits . . . . . . . . . . . 55 a. Unforeseen Circumstances . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 55 b. Efficiency . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 55 c. Works-Around . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 55 1. Practical Barriers . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 55 2. Inaction By Primarily Tasked Institution . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 55 3. Constitutional Barriers . . . . . . . . . . . 55 Synergies. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 56 Addressing Emergencies. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 56 IV. NOT ALL OR NOTHING . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 56 V. METHODS FOR ADDRESSING CONFLICTS . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 57 A. B. C. D. VI. Institution-Based Conflict-Resolution Principles . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Time-Based Conflict-Resolution Principles . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Multi-factor Conflict-Resolution Principles . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . No-Sorting Principles . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 57 57 57 58 THE BIG PICTURE: META-NARRATIVES AND CONSTITUTIONAL IMPLICATIONS . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 58 A. B. Meta-Narratives . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 58 Constitutional Implications . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 58 INTRODUCTION 2 The same power cannot belong, in the whole to both departments, or be properly so vested as to operate separately in each. Still more evident is it, that the same specific function or act, cannot possibly belong to the two departments and be separately exercisble by each . . . . A concurrent authority in two independent departments, to perform the same function with respect to the same thing, would be awkward in practice, as it is unnatural in theory. James Madison, Second Helvidius Letter James Madison penned the above words when analyzing what today 2 ALEXANDER HAMILTON & JAMES MADISON, THE PACIFICUS-HEVLIDIUS DEBATES OF 1793-1794: TOWARD THE COMPLETION OF THE AMERICAN FOUNDING 68(MORTON J. FRISCH, ED.) (LIBERTY FUND 2007). [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 3 would be called a “separation of powers” question. As this Article shows, Madison’s basic intuition – that power that is specifically allocated by the Constitution to one institution cannot be exercised by another – also features prominently in discussions concerning the distribution of power as between the federal government and states (vertical federalism) and the distribution of power as between states (horizontal federalism). Indeed, the notion that constitutional allocations of power are “exclusively” held by the specified institution to which the power has been granted, and cannot reside “concurrently” in more than one governmental institution, is found in contexts apart from separation of powers and federalism – for instance, regarding the Seventh Amendment’s distribution of power between jury and judge. Perhaps nowhere else has Madison’s view of the basic architecture of American constitutionalism proven to be so wrong. This Article catalogues and analyzes the many significant respects in which contemporary American government deviates from Madison’s assumption of what I shall call “exclusivity” and instead adopts what Madison believes to be the “unnatural” and “awkward” state of “concurrence.” As regards the distribution of national powers, just consider the following few examples. Although Article II, Section 2 provides that the president “shall have Power to grant Reprieves and Pardons,” the Court long has held that Congress has the power to grant amnesties that, the Court has acknowledged, are functionally equivalent to pardons. Similarly, while the Constitution specifies only one mechanism by which the federal government can create international agreements – treaties – most of this country’s contemporary international obligations have been created outside of the treaty-making process, through so-called “sole executive agreements” and “joint congressional agreements.” Concurrence exists outside the context of separation of powers. As regards “vertical” federalism – the federal government’s relation to the states – though Congress has the power to regulate interstate commerce, states also have power to regulate interstate commerce. In respect of “horizontal” federalism – the relation among states – it quite frequently is the case that 3 4 5 6 7 8 3 The question concerned the constitutionality of President Washington’s Neutrality Proclamation of 1793: did the President have the power to interpret a mutual defense treaty to determine whether the United States was obligated to go to war to assist France, or did Congress alone have the power to do so on account of its constitutionally granted power to declare war? I discuss Madison’s views as well as those of his interlocutor, Alexander Hamilton, infra at Part I.C. For an excellent discussion, see H. JEFFERSON POWELL, THE PRESIDENT’S AUTHORITY OVER FOREIGN AFFAIRS (2002). 4 U.S. CONST. ART. II, §2, cl. 1. 5 See Brown v. Walker, 161 U.S. 591, 601 (1896) (recognizing this and noting that the difference between pardons and amnesties is “one rather of philological interest than of legal importance”). 6 See U.S. CONST. ART. II, §2, cl. 2. 7 See infra Part xx. 8 See Cooley v. Board of Wardens of the Port of Philadelphia, 53 U.S. 299, 318-19 (1851). [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 4 more than one state has the power to regulate a given person, transaction, or occurrence. And there are yet other contexts – beyond separation of powers and federalism – where the Constitution also has been understood as allocating power concurrently. Though the Seventh Amendment allocates adjudicatory fact-finding power to the jury, the jury is not the sole institution with this power: administrative law judges in Article I courts find facts in the very same contests where juries would have the constitutional power to fact-find, and Article III judges engage in fact-finding of the sort performed by juries when they decide motions for summary judgment and motions to grant judgments notwithstanding the verdict. To provide one last example, although the power to sue government contractors belongs to the executive branch, it does not rest exclusively there: qui tam statutes empower private citizens to sue, on behalf of the United States, anyone who has submitted a false claim to the federal government. The power to sue government contractors to recover false claims accordingly rests with both the federal executive and private citizens. Though commentators focusing on discrete doctrines sometimes have recognized that governmental powers sometimes overlap, this is the first Article to comprehensively analyze the phenomenon of concurrence. Because the Constitution spends much of its time allocating power to specific institutions, the question of whether the power allocated is exclusively held by a single institution or instead is concurrently held by two or more institutions is pervasive. This Article’s analysis of the choice between exclusivity and concurrence across multiple doctrinal contexts uncovers multiple recurring patterns that, it is hoped, can lead to a more informed consideration in the future of the choice between exclusivity and concurrence. This is important because many contested contemporary issues implicate, at least in part, the choice between exclusivity and concurrence. Here are some examples: though the Constitution vests the power to declare war with Congress, does the President have a similar power? What is the relation between the Congress’ powers to regulate the land and naval forces and the President’s Commander9 10 11 12 13 9 See Allstate Ins. Co. v. Hague, 449 U.S. 302, 307 (1981); Mark D. Rosen, “Hard” or “Soft” Pluralism?: Positive, Normative, and Institutional Considerations of States’ Extraterritorial Powers, 51 ST. LOUIS L. J. 713, 72930 (2007). 10 See 31 U.S.C. §3730, discussed infra Part xx. 11 Likewise, the posse comitatus doctrines allowed state and federal executive officials to compel private citizens to assist in the making of arrests and in otherwise executing a wide range of state and federal laws, exemplifying yet another instance of coordinacy: executive power that is jointly exercised by the executive branch and private sector. 12 See. e.g., Caleb Nelson, Preemption, 86 VA. L. REV. 225, 225 (2000)(“nearly every federal statute addresses an area in which the states also have authority to legislate”); See, e.g., Lee H. Rosenthal, Back in the Court’s Court, 74 UMKC L.R. 687 (2006) (noting that problems arising from asbestos can be handled either by legislatures or courts). 13 See Michael D. Ramsey, Presidential Declarations of War, 37 U.C. DAVIS L. REV. 321 (2003). [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 5 in-Chief powers? Are there mechanisms outside of Article V by which the Constitution in effect can be amended? The Article is in six parts (some that are quite short!). Part One formally defines concurrence and exclusivity and provides six contemporary instances of concurrence. Part One explains how concurrence differs from the familiar concept of “checks and balance,” and then introduces several analytical tools that facilitate the analysis that follows in the rest of the Article. Part One concludes by closely analyzing the complete argument for exclusivity that James Madison articulated in his famed Second Helvedius Letter, from which this Article’s foreword quotes, as well as Alexander Hamilton’s counterargument in support of concurrence. The next four parts identify and analyze recurring patterns that emerge from a cross-doctrinal analysis. Part Two uncovers a stunning historical pattern: virtually all contemporary contexts where power is understood to be held concurrently amount to renunciations of the Court’s original view, consistent with Madison’s, that the power was held exclusively by only one institution. Part Two documents the doctrinal process by which the Supreme Court has come to accept concurrence in three different doctrinal contexts. It shows that, in so doing, the Supreme Court has rejected categorical application of the principle of expressio unius est exclusio alterius. Part Three examines the how’s and why’s behind the switch from exclusivity to concurrence. Part Three first uncovers three recurring mechanisms by which concurrence is generated. Notably, the initiative for shifting from exclusivity to concurrence mostly has originated outside the judiciary – not terribly surprising in light of Part Two’s finding that courts typically start with exclusivist assumptions. Part Three also explores the reasons for the shift from exclusivity to concurrence, identifying several recurring benefits of concurrence. Part Four points out that the choice between exclusivity and concurrence is not “all or nothing.” There are many contexts where constitutionally allocated power is universally recognized to be exclusively held by a single institution. Further, there are some contexts where there has been a “counter-trajectory” from concurrence back to exclusivism. Moreover, even where there is concurrence, there typically are limits on the degree to which power can be shared among two or more institutions. Taken together, Part Five suggests that the choice between exclusivity and concurrence has not been made on the basis of a trans-substantive or categorical principle, but instead has been made on the basis of context-specific analyses. Part Five also suggests that “slippery slope” concerns that opening the door to concurrence could lead to complete chaos are overblown. Part Five addresses one of the great anxieties that is created by 14 15 14 Ackerman; Reva Segal, ERA, Cal L. Rev. 15 For an example of such an anxiety in a context relevant to concurrence, see See Larry Alexander and Saikrishna Prakash, Delegation Really Running Riot, 93 VA. L. REV. 1035 (2007). [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 6 concurrently held power: the prospect of conflict among the multiple institutions. The specter of conflict sometimes is invoked as a trump card against the conclusion that power is concurrently held. Part Five suggests that this overstates the concern by showing the multiple tools for managing conflict that are found in American constitutional law. Part Five argues that the potential of conflict is a cost of concurrence that appropriately is taken account in weighing the desirability of concurrence in a particular context, but that, at a general matter at least, it should not serve as the sole basis for deciding against concurrence. Part Six, the Article’s final part, considers what are the appropriate lessons to be drawn from what the Article has uncovered. It first identifies four possible meta-narratives to describe the trajectory towards concurrence that it uncovers: (1) a healthy adaptation to changing times and needs, (2) the Court’s “law-on-the-books” catching up with the “law-in-action,” (3) the natural process of entropy, or (4) the systematic extension of one set of institutions at the expense of other institutions. Of these possibilities, the fourth might require elaboration to be comprehensible at this point: virtually all instances of concurrence have made it easier for federal institutions to create law, thereby extending federal power at the expense of states and the private sector. As we’ll see, all these narratives fit the action to a not inconsiderable degree. The Article then considers the constitutional implications of its findings. The mere fact that concurrence is widespread does not on its own mean, of course, that it is constitutionally legitimate. Not surprisingly, what constitutional lessons the reader draws will turn on her prior jurisprudential commitments. To be sure, this Article is not the place to engage in a debate about such foundational questions of whether the Constitution is appropriately construed on the basis of (solely) the Founders’ understanding, what a reasonable member of the Founding generation would have thought, text, pragmatics, history, or something else. Fortunately, though, this Article’s findings should be relevant to adherents of all these approaches to constitutional interpretation. To begin, understanding an underappreciated yet widespread characteristic of contemporary constitutional doctrine should be of value to all constitutionalists. Beyond this, some, but not all, instances of contemporary concurrence will be troublesome to Originalists. Textualists will not necessarily be bothered because, as this Article shows, there are surprisingly strong textual arguments to support most if not all instances of contemporary concurrence. Those who favor any of the multiple schools of dynamic constitutional interpretation will be intrigued to find the types of pragmatic considerations that have driven the large-scale migration from exclusivity to concurrence. The fact that concurrence typically has not been initiated by the judiciary underscores, among other things, the role that governmental actors apart from courts play in determining what practices are deemed consistent with our Constitution. Finally, adherents of almost all [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 7 schools of constitutional interpretation may be encouraged to forthrightly examine the often unstated starting assumption of exclusivity that appears to be shared by many lawyers and that is reflected in such aspects of our legal culture as the maxim of expressio unius est exclusio alterius. I. THE ANALYTICS OF CONCURRENCE, AND SOME EXAMPLES A. Definitions and Examples. “Concurrence” refers to the situation where a given activity “x” can be performed by more than one institution despite the fact that the Constitution (appears to) place the power to do “x” in one specified institution. “Exclusivity” refers to the situation where a given activity “x” can be performed by only a single institution. By “institution,” I mean the different entities that are implicitly adopted by the Constitution: for example, the House of Representatives, the Senate, the Supreme Court, inferior article III courts, the President, states, juries, and citizens (the “People”). My definition of institution also embraces novel institutions not identified in the Constitution, such as administrative agencies and supranational tribunals. It should be apparent from the above definition that “concurrence” is a different concept from “checks and balances.” Concurrence refers to the situation where two (or more) different each have the power to undertake “x.” “Checks and balances,” by contrast, refers to the situation where two (or more) institutions have distinctive roles in completing act “x.” So, for instance, the President’s veto power is an aspect of checks and balances, but is not an example of “concurrence.” The same is true of the Senate’s role in approving appointments of officers. What follows – by way of description, not justification – are some examples of contemporary concurrence. That is to say, the fact that I discuss an example of concurrence here, and elsewhere in the Article, should not be understood as a normative endorsement of the arrangement. Having a clear understanding of current institutional arrangements, it seems to me, is useful if not essential for adherents of all schools of constitutional interpretation. What follows in the bulk of this Article, accordingly, is a description and analysis of wide-ranging phenomenon that has occurred. I discuss the normative constitutional implications of this wide-ranging practice in Part Six. Here, then, are six contemporary examples of concurrence: 16 1. The Constitution states that “[i]n all cases affecting Ambassadors . . . and those in which a State shall be Party, the supreme Court shall have original jurisdiction.” Though the Supreme Court indeed has original jurisdiction in these cases, inferior district courts also 17 16 Madison draws a similar distinction in the Second Hevlidius letter. 17 U.S. CONST. ART. III, §2, CL. 2 (emphasis supplied). [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 8 have original jurisdiction over cases brought by ambassadors and in many cases brought by states. Accordingly, notwithstanding the Constitution’s allocation of original jurisdiction over cases affected Ambassadors and in which States are a party to the Supreme Court, district courts have concurrent authority with the Supreme Court to exercise original jurisdiction over such cases. 18 2. Article III of the Constitution states that “[t]he judicial power of the United States, shall be vested in one supreme Court, and in such inferior Courts as the Congress may from time to time ordain and establish.” Today, however, a significant amount of adjudication occurs in non-Article III federal tribunals. For example, contract and property claims against the United States are heard in a non-Article III federal tribunal known as the Court of Claims, and administrative agencies can hear disputes between private parties as to the compensation owed an injured maritime worker. These non-Article III institutions can oversee these adjudications despite the fact that contract and property claims against the United States also fall within federal district courts’ jurisdiction and notwithstanding the fact that federal district courts have “long handled maritime personal injury claims . . .” Indeed, as Professor Fallon has observed, “virtually all of the kinds of cases that are heard in article III courts, including criminal cases and civil disputes arising under the Constitution, laws, and treaties of the Unites States” today can be heard in non-Article III federal courts. 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 18 See Ames v. State of Kansas, 111 U.S. 449, 467 (1884). 19 U.S. CONST. ART. III, §1. 20 See James E. Pfander, Article I Tribunals, Article III Courts, and the Judicial Power of the United States, 118 HARV. L. REV. 643, 646, 656-60 (2004) (“Congress has often assigned disputes that appear to fall within the scope of the federal judicial power to Article I tribunals whose judges lack salary and tenure protections”); MARTIN H. REDISH, FEDERAL JURISDICTION: TENSIONS IN THE ALLOCATION OF JUDICIAL POWER 36-51 (1980). 21 Pfander, supra note 20, at 657. 22 Crowell v. Benson, 285 U.S. 22, 51 (1932). 23 Boyle. 24 Pfander, supra note 20, at 741. 25 Fallon, supra note ?, at 923. Consider as well the various supranational adjudicatory panels that have been created under federal law. For example, whereas the conclusions of the federal agencies tasked with administering the United States anti-dumping laws typically are subject to judicial review by two Article III courts, the North American Free Trade Implementation Act creates new adjudicatory entities that are staffed by representatives of the two disputing countries. For a discussion, see Monaghan, supra note 167, at 834-39. These adjudicatory entities are not Article III courts, yet they have the power to “directly apply domestic American legal standards” and to then “issue orders directly binding federal administrative officials” that “are not subject to further review in Article III courts.” See id at 837 (discussing Chapter [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 9 Accordingly, notwithstanding the Constitution’s allocation of the “judicial power” to Article III courts, non-Article III tribunals frequently have concurrent authority with Article III courts to adjudicate disputes. 3. The Constitution specifies only one mechanism by which the United States can create international agreements – the treaty – about which it states that the “[President] shall have Power, by and with the Advice and Consent of the Senate, to make Treaties, provided two thirds of the Senators present concur.” Many of the most important twentieth century international agreements into which the United States entered, however, were not created via the treaty process, but instead have been created by CongressionalExecutive agreements, which are negotiated by the President and approved by simple majorities of both Houses of Congress. The Restatement (Third) of Foreign Relations Law takes the position that “any agreement concluded as a Congressional-Executive Agreement could also be concluded by treaty” and notes that “[t]he prevailing view is that the Congressional-Executive agreement can be used as an alternative to the treaty method in every instance.” A prominent example of the Congressional-Executive Agreement is the North American Free Trade Agreement, which received sixty-one supporting votes and thirty-eight “nos” in the Senate – a comfortably majority to be sure, but far short of the two thirds of Senators present that is necessary for a treaty. The agreement bringing the United States into the World Trade Organization likewise was a CongressionalExecutive agreement, not a treaty. Accordingly, notwithstanding the Constitution’s sole specification of the treaty as a mechanism for creating international obligations, Congress has concurrent authority with the Senate to create international obligations by means of Congressional26 27 28 29 30 19 proceedings under NAFTA). 26 U.S. CONST. ART. II, §2, CL 2. 27 See RESTATEMENT (3RD) FOREIGN RELATIONS LAW §303, comment a (1987). International agreements also have been created by the so-called “Sole Executive Agreements,” which are negotiated by the President but subject to no congressional approval whatsoever. See id. For example, President Carter entered into a sole executive agreement known as the “Algiers Accord” to gain release of the U.S. diplomatic personnel who were taken hostage in 1979 in Iran. See Bradford R. Clark, Domesticating Sole Executive Agreements, 93 VA. L. REV. 1573, 1608 (2007). And President Clinton negotiated an agreement with German Chancellor Schroder establishing a mechanism for handling insurance claims held by Holocaust victims. See American Insurance Association v. Garamendi, 539 U.S. 396, 406-08 (2003). 28 Rest. For. Rel. Law, supra note 27, at §303, comment e. 29 Brice Ackerman & David Golove, Is NAFTA Constitutional?, 108 HARV. L. REV. 799, 801 (1995). 30 Id. at 917-19. [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 10 Executive Agreements. 4. The Constitution states that “All legislative Powers herein granted shall be vested in a Congress of the United States.” All legal scholars agree that many administrative agencies have virtually unfettered discretion to generate regulations that are functionally indistinguishable from statutes. For example, the Supreme Court has upheld statutes that instruct agencies to regulate on the basis of “public interest, convenience, or necessity,” to set “fair and equitable prices,” or to set ambient air quality standards that are “requisite to protect the public health.” Accordingly, notwithstanding the Constitution’s allocation of “[a]ll legislative Powers herein granted” to Congress, administrative agencies have concurrent authority with Congress to create the legal obligations that guide citizens’ actions. 31 32 33 34 35 5. The Constitution states that “Congress shall have power to . . . regulate commerce . . . among the Several states.” The United States Supreme Court has held that states also have power to regulate interstate commerce. Accordingly, notwithstanding the Constitution’s allocate of regulatory authority over interstate commerce to Congress, state and Congress have concurrent authority to regulate interstate commerce. 36 6. Congress has the power to enact laws relating to admiralty 37 31 U.S. CONST. ART. I, §1. 32 The Court has invalidated only two statutes on nondelegation grounds, both in the same year. So, in Cass Sunstein’s words, the doctrine has “had one good year, and 211 bad ones (and counting).” Cass R. Sunstein, Nondelegation Canons, 67 U. CHI. L. REV. 315, 322 (2000). Thomas Merrill recently has argued that “legislative power” entails “the power to make rules for the governance of society,” that administrative agencies exercise precisely this power today, and that they properly do so as long as Congress explicitly delegates them this power. Merrill, supra note 54, 198, at 2120. Gary Lawson describes the status quo as one where the Court has found the intelligible principle standard to be satisfied by“any collection of words that Congress chose to string together.” Lawson, supra note 199, at 371. Other scholars who have noted that the non-delegation doctrine fails to curb delegations of de facto lawmaking authority to agencies include David Schoenbrod and Marty Redish. See DAVID SCHOENBROD, POWER WITHOUT RESPONSIBILITY: HOW CONGRESS ABUSES THE PEOPLE THROUGH DELEGATION; REDISH, supra note 20, at 135-61. 33 See NBC v. United States, 319 U.S. 190, 225-26 (1943). 34 Yakus v. United States, 321 U.S. 414, 427 (1944). 35 Whitman, 531 U.S. at 473. 36 See Cooley v. Board of Wardens of the Port of Philadelphia, 53 U.S. 299, 318-19 (1851). 37 Southern Pacific Co. v. Jensen, 244 U.S. 205, 212 (1917) (stating that “in the absence of some controlling statute the general maritime law as accepted by the federal courts constitutes part of our national law applicable to matters within the admiralty and maritime jurisdiction”). [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 11 and laws governing interstate disputes concerning such matters as water pollution. Yet there also is a “tradition of federal common lawmaking in admiralty” as well as a “federal common law of nuisance” regarding interstate waters. Accordingly, Congress and (primarily) federal courts have concurrent authority to create the rules of admiralty as well as the rules that govern many interstate controversies. 38 39 B. Analytical Tools. For purposes of fully understanding concurrence, it will prove useful to introduce some additional concepts and clarifications. 1. Same-Effect versus Same-Source Concurrence. “SameEffect” concurrence refers to the circumstance where two different institutions have the power to undertake “x”, but pursuant to different sources of power. Consider, for instance, example three above: the constitutional source of power that gives rise to Congressional-Executive Agreements is not Article II’s treaty power, but instead is Article I’s grants of legislative power to Congress (as well as any additional grants of legislative power to Congress outside of Article I ). Same-effect concurrence hence describes the situation where two (or more) grants of power overlap such that more than one institution has the power to effectuate act “x.” “Same-source” concurrence refers to the situation where two different institutions exercise the same power. Consider, for instance, example five from above: the Constitution has granted Congress the power to regulate interstate commerce, yet (it has been held) the States have retained power to regulate interstate commerce. Accordingly, two different institutions – Congress and the States – exercise the same power. As will soon be seen, there is controversy as to whether several of the other examples of currency listed above are instances of “same-effect” or “same-source” concurrence. One might think: surely “same-effect concurrence” is not controversial, only “same-source concurrence” would be. That is not so. For example, Madison’s words in the Second Helvidius letter were penned as an argument against “same-effect” concurrence: Madison argued that the Congress had power to interpret a mutual defense treaty under its powers to declare war and that the President could not have the same power to interpret the treaty under any of his constitutional powers because, as Madison stated, 40 41 42 38 American Dredging Co. v. Miller, 510 U.S. 443, 455 (1994). 39 State of Illinois v. City of Milwaukee, 406 U.S. 91, 101 (1972). 40 For instance, Congress’ powers under Article IV’s Effects Clause could support congressional power to enter into a Congressional-Executive Agreement regarding the effect that is to be given foreign (in the sense of non-United States) judgments in state courts. 41 Cooley. 42 Though this constituted a shift from Gibbons v. Ogden, where Chief Justice Marshall embraced only same-effect concurrence. [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 12 “[a] concurrent authority in two independent departments, to perform the same function with respect to the same thing, would be awkward in practice, as it is unnatural in theory.” Consider, as well, the recent battle between Professors Ackerman and Golove, on the one hand, and Professor Tribe, on the other, concerning the constitutionality of Congressional-Executive Agreements. This too concerned the issue of “same-effect” concurrence, for neither the defenders nor the critic suggested that Congressional-Executive Agreements were based on the “treaty” power. Rather, the question was whether the power to create Congressional-Executive Agreements premised (primarily) on Congress’ Article I powers can coexist with, and is interchangeable with, the treaty power. But why should same-effect concurrence ever be controversial? It is not at all unusual, after all, that two institutions having different mandates and different sources of power will have overlapping responsibilities. Two answers suggest themselves. First, the activity in question frequently appears to more readily fit under one of the two powers, opening the door to arguments based on expressio unius est exclusio alterius and fears that some troublesome extension of governmental powers is at work. Second, if two or more institutions have the power to do “x,” then it is possible that the institutions will have decide to act differently and thereby create a conflict. Indeed, the prospect of conflicts frequently is deemed to be a death blow to concurrence. To say that “same-effect” concurrence can be (and frequently is) controversial is not to suggest that the distinction between “same-effect” concurrence and “same-source” concurrence is inconsequential. Indeed, in several areas of the law, courts and scholars have fought mightily to establish that two institutions’ overlapping powers are the result of “same-effect” concurrence but not “same-source” concurrence. For example, as I shall show at greater length in Part Two, a recurring controversy in the context of non-Article III tribunals is whether the powers that such tribunals exercise is Article III “judicial power” or something else. Chief Justice Marshall famously asserted that territorial courts are incapable of receiving Article III “judicial power,” whereas the modern Court has seemingly switched tracks, concluding that Congress may “authorize the adjudication of Article III business in a non-Article III tribunal.” Professor Monaghan likewise seems 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 43 Madison, Second Hevidius Letter. 44 Compare Brice Ackerman & David Golove, Is NAFTA Constitutional?, 108 HARV. L. REV. 799, 801 (1995) with Laurence H. Tribe, Taking Text and Structure Seriously: Reflections on Free-Form Method in Constitutional Interpretation, 108 HARV. L. REV. 1221, 1275 (1995). 45 See, e.g., Tribe, supra note 83.. 46 This concern permeates Madison’s discussion. See Second Helvedius Letter at x. 47 See infra Part II.C. 48 Id. 49 Id. at 851. [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 13 content when he describes today’s “system of shared adjudication between agencies and Article III courts.” But not all agree with this. Two outstanding recent tomes – one by Professor Jim Pfander in the Harvard Law Review, the other by Professor Caleb Nelson in the Columbia Law Review – are both premised on establishing that non-Article III tribunals do not exercise article III “judicial power” but instead exercise some other power. That is to say, both scholars largely accept as legitimate the adjudicatory powers that are exercised by non-Article III courts, but seek to show that they are instances of “same-effect” rather than “same-source” concurrence. Writing in the non-delegation context, Professors Eric Posner and Adrian Vermeule have undertaken the identical strategy as that of Professors Pfander and Nelson. Posner and Vermeule conclude that the powers exercised by agencies are fully constitutional because agencies never exercise Though agency rule-making may be Article I “legislative Powers.” functionally equivalent to law-making so far as the citizen is concerned, Posner and Vermeule assert that rule-making cannot constitute an exercise of “legislative power” because legislative power refers only to the power to enact statutes. Professor Merrill concurs that agencies’ rule-making authority is constitutional, but he criticizes Posner and Vermeule’s idiosyncratically narrow definition of “legislative” power and concludes that the power exercised by agencies indeed constitutes legislative power. In short, Posner and Vermeule embrace “same-effect” concurrence whereas Merrill believes that agencies and Congress are examples of “same-source” concurrence. As a formal matter, contemporary caselaw treats agency powers as an aspect of “same-effect” concurrence as it insists that Article I’s “text permits no delegation of those powers.” One might ask: why should it matter whether power is exercised as a matter of “same-source” or “same-effect” concurrence? Five points bear mentioning. Point One: The difference appears to matter to many, as shown by the fact that serious jurists and scholars have made serious efforts to establish that 50 51 52 53 54 55 50 Monaghan, supra note 167, at 873 (emphasis supplied). 51 See Pfander, supra note 20; Nelson, supra note 164. 52 See Eric A. Posner & Adrian Vermeule, Interring the Non-Delegation Doctrine, 69 U. CHI. L. REV. 1721, 1731 (2002). 53 Merrill, supra note 54, 198, at 2125 (noting that “[t]here is no support in decisional law for” Posner and Vermeule’s formal definition of legislative power as the power to enact statutes and observing that “[t]he possibility seems never to have occurred to anyone in a context in which it would have decisional significance” and that their definition “is at the very least idiosyncratic, and probably would be rejected if presented to the courts”). 54 Thomas W. Merrill, Rethinking Article I, Section 1: From Nondelegation to Exclusive Delegation, 104 COLUM. L. REV. 2097, 2165 (2004) (arguing that “the nondelegation doctrine . . . should be rejected” and that “the Court should repudiate the idea that Article I, Section 1 precludes any congressional sharing of legislative power”). 55 Whitman v. American Trucking Associations, Inc., 531 U.S. 457, 472 (2001). [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 14 contemporary institutional arrangements are examples of same-effect rather than same-source concurrence. Their concern can be fleshed out as follows. If the Constitution goes out of its way to specify special protections for those who exercise the judicial power (life tenure and salary guarantees) and special procedures that must be followed for legislation to be enacted, how can it be concluded that the judicial power can be exercised by those who lacks those protections or that the legislative power can be exercised by means of different procedures? Allowing “judicial power” to be exercised outside of Article III courts or the “legislative power” to be exercised outside of Congress would be to sanction an end-run around the Constitution’s specifications, rendering the Constitutional language “mere surplusage.” This concern, in short, is nicely summarized and addressed by the well-known principle of expressio unius est exclusio alterius Point Two: On the other hand, are the concerns enumerated above in Point One really answered by establishing that an institutional arrangement is an example of same-effect rather than same-source concurrence? Isn’t the only way to really guard against the concerns voiced in Point One to conclude that same-effect concurrence is also problematic, and not to simply assert (for instance) that territorial courts exercise Article I rather than Article III power? Point Three: To the extent there is power to Point Two – and I think there is – what likely drives the impetus to justify a given institutional arrangement as an instance of same-effect rather than same-source concurrence is the sense that the former is a more limited license for concurrence (perhaps because it really is the case that there sometimes are two paths to the same goal). Thus, in situations where the Court (or scholars) do not feel empowered to all-out reject concurrence, insisting that they only are blessing same-effect concurrence appears to be an acceptable fall-back position. In other words, in some contexts at least, advocates of same-effect concurrence really seem to be sympathetic to exclusivity, but just can’t bring themselves to embrace exclusivity’s implications. Point Four: At the end of the day, perhaps the concerns laid out in Point One can be allayed by generalizing Tom Merrill’s non-delegation analysis. Merrill argues that agencies properly exercise actual legislative power, thereby forthrightly defending same-source concurrence. Merrill’s argument demonstrates that the Constitution’s text almost always can be plausibly construed to permit concurrence even when the Constitution allocates power to only one institution. After all, one might think that Article I, section 1 provides a particularly strong textual basis for embracing exclusivity: its language that “[a]ll legislative Powers herein granted shall be vested in a Congress” quite plausibly could be said to require that all legislative power vest only in Congress. Yet Merrill resists this conclusion because the “text of the Constitution is [ ] silent on the question whether or to what extent 56 57 56 Marbury v. Madison, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137, 174 (1803). 57 See, e.g., Tribe. [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 15 legislative power may be shared.” Cass Sunstein has made the same argument: “[t]he Constitution does grant legislative power to Congress, but it does not in terms forbid delegations of that power.” Merrill’s and Sunstein’s arguments have broad implications outside the non-delegation context because, with only a handful of exceptions, the Constitution’s grants of power are not accompanied by prohibitions on the delegation of the allocated power. It would follow that, as a purely textual matter, it is plausible to suggest that virtually all the Constitution’s grants of power to a particular institution could be delegated to another institution, resulting in what Merrill calls “share[d]” power and what this Article dubs “concurrence.” Point Five: On the other hand, Point Four’s textual argument does not really address the anxiety expressed in Point One that concurrence allows the Constitution’s carefully crafted mechanisms for accomplishing “x” to be circumvented by (what typically is) a less demanding procedure: Congressional-Executive Agreements are pursued because there’s not sufficient senatorial support for a treaty, and territorial courts rather than article III courts were created so that their judges did not have to have life tenure. The last Part of this Article – Part Six – will revisit these considerations regarding the distinction between same-effect and same-source concurrence, and the legitimacy of concurrence generally, after we’ve had an opportunity to more fully examine the phenomenon of concurrence across doctrinal contexts and time. Finally, let me summarize two lessons from our discussion before 58 59 60 61 62 63 58 Id. at 2127. 59 Cass R. Sunstein, Nondelegation Canons, 67 U. CHI. L. REV. 315, 322 (2000) (emphasis supplied). 60 The sole exceptions can be found in Article I, Section 10, Clause 1, which specifies a handful of actions (such as entering into treaties and coining money) that federal institutions may undertake but that States may not. That the activities identified in Clause 1 are flatly prohibited to states, and may not be delegated to states, is all but impossible to deny on account of the Constitution’s next two clauses, which specify activities that states shall not do “without the Consent of Congress.” See U.S. CONST. ART. I, §10, CL. 2 & CL. 3. 61 For an extended critique of delegation, see Alexander & Prakash, supra note 63. 62 Id. at 2165. Furthermore, Merrill appears to be of the view that there sometimes can be “shared” powers even without delegation. Merrill believes that institutions apart from Congress have no inherent legislative power (the “anti-inherency principle,” id. at 2101), and that there accordingly can be shared legislative powers only pursuant to congressional delegations, on account of Article I, Section 1's specification that the legislative powers “herein” granted are vested in Congress. See id. (“the reference to legislative powers ‘herein’ granted can be understood to limit the anti-inherency principle to those powers granted in Article I itself.” ). This suggests that legislative powers granted to Congress outside of Article I (perhaps under Section 5 of the Fourteenth Amendment, for instance) may be shared by institutions apart from Congress even without a delegation from Congress. 63 Indeed, the broad implications of Merrill’s argument vis-a-vis delegations of other powers led Larry Alexander and Sai Prakash to pen an extended slippery slope discourse. See Larry Alexander and Saikrishna Prakash, Delegation Really Running Riot, 93 VA. L. REV. 1035 (2007). I respond to their argument later in this Article. [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 16 concluding this preliminary discussion of same-source versus same-effect concurrence. First, as shown by the examples of non-Article III tribunals and agencies’ rule-making powers, there sometimes is controversy as to whether a contemporary institutional arrangement is an instance of “same-source” or “same-effect” concurrence. For example, as regards the adjudicatory powers of Article I and Article III courts, Chief Justice Marshall and Professors Pfander and Nelson are committed to “same-effect” concurrence, whereas the modern Supreme Court and Professor Monaghan seem comfortable with “same-source” concurrence. Second, as shown by the controversy concerning Congressional-Executive Agreements, there sometimes is controversy over whether even same-effect concurrence is legitimate or whether exclusivity is the only permissible power arrangement. 2. Non-Identicality. A second principle relevant to this Article’s analysis is that concurrence does not mean that the two institutions’ acts are wholly identical. This “non-identicality principle” is true of both same-source and same-effect concurrence. In general, the acts of institutions with concurrent power are non-identical as regards both (1) what must happen for the act to come into existence and (2) what must happen for the act to be negated. There sometimes are additional important distinctions between the “concurrent” acts. This principle of non-identicality should be self-evident, but it has surprising illuminating effect. As an example of non-identicality regarding same-source concurrence, though both Congress and the states have power to regulate interstate commerce, congressional regulations and state regulations of interstate commerce differ in several respects. For one, different entities must vote (Congress versus state legislatures) for each act (legislation regulating interstate commerce) to be created. Second, the Supremacy Clause establishes a conflict-resolution principle under which federal regulations trump state regulations. For an example regarding (what contemporary case law considers to be) same-effect concurrence, administrative regulations also are not identical to statutory commands. Though they share much in common – for instance, from the vantage point of most citizens, the legal obligations they impose are indistinguishable – administrative regulations do not appear in U.S. statutes, they also are brought into existence by the actions of two different institutions (Congress versus the agency), and finally regulations typically are easier to amend or rescind than statutes. Congressional-Executive Agreements and Treaties provide a partial exception to the general principle of non-identicality. Although they differ insofar as they are created by different mechanisms (two-thirds of present Senators in the case of treaties versus majorities of both houses in the case of 64 65 64 Relatedly, there exists some areas of concurrence where the source of a particular governmental entity’s powers to act is still a question of controversy – federal common law, for instance. 65 Court of Claims point [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 17 Congressional-Executive Agreements), the Congressional-Executive Agreements and Treaties presently are understood as being equally resilient to alteration. For instance, both are subject to the “last-in-time” rule and can be superseded by later international agreements or treaties. 3. Imperfect Overlap. A third relevant principle is that the existence of concurrence does not necessarily entail perfect overlap between the powers of the two institutions. To the contrary, there frequently is imperfect overlap between the two institutions. For example, the early twentieth century case of Missouri v. Holland established that treaties “may deal with a subject that Congress could not regulate by legislation in the absence of a treaty.” Though the scope of Congress’ powers has significantly expanded since during the twentieth century – and so, for instance, the subject addressed in the Holland that was then viewed as falling outside the scope of Congress’ commerce clause powers today undoubtedly would be deemed as being subject to the commerce clause – there still may be some subjects relating to international relations that do not fall within Congress’ enumerated powers. With respect to these matters, only treaties can be used, and there accordingly is imperfect overlap between the treaty power and CongressionalExecutive Agreements. C. The Pacificus-Helvidius Debates. The earliest exchange concerning the choice between exclusivity and concurrence – and, perhaps surprisingly, to date still the most extended discussion of this issue – is found in the exchange between Alexander Hamilton and James Madison known as the Pacificus-Helvidius Debates. The occasion for the debate was President Washington’s issuance of the Neutrality Proclamation of 1793. In declaring the new nation’s neutrality vis-a-vis France’s war with Great Britain and Holland, the Washington’s Proclamation interpreted America’s Treaty of Alliance with France of 1778. The question dividing Hamilton and Madison was whether the President had the authority to interpret the Treaty. Madison took the exclusivist position, arguing that only Congress had power to do so by virtue of its power to Declare war. Hamilton defended the Proclamation’s legality, adopting what this Article dubs “concurrence” in arguing that both the President and Congress had the power to interpret the Treaty. Let us first look to Hamilton’s position. He acknowledged that Congress had the power to interpret the Treaty pursuant to its power to Declare war, but urged that the President also had the power to interpret the Treaty under the President’s executive powers: 66 67 68 [H]owever true it may be, that the right of the Legislature to declare war includes the right of judging whether the Nation be under 66 See Rest. For. Relat. §303, comment j. There is uncertainty as regards the scope of the President’s power to unilaterally rescind treaties. [elaborate] 67 Id. at comment c, citing to Missouri v. Holland, 252 U.S. 416 (1920). 68 For a good introduction, see DEBATES, supra note 2, at vii. [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 18 obligations to make War or not – it will not follow that the Executive is in any case excluded from a similar right of Judgment, in the execution of its own functions.69 Hamilton here has put forward a defense of what this Article dubs “sameeffect” concurrence. Hamilton believed that the source of the President’s power to issue the Proclamation was the Vesting clause. Though this construction of the Vesting Clause was controversial then and remains disputed today, that issue is not relevant to this Article’s concern of whether power is allocated on an exclusive or concurrent basis. What matters is his understanding that presidential and congressional powers could overlap such that both institutions have the power to undertake the same act (in this case, to interpret a Treaty). That Hamilton’s understanding of concurrence was not tied to his view of the Vesting Clause is proven later in the first Pacificus Letter, where he presents a hypothetical in which the President interprets a Treaty pursuant to his powers under the Recognition Clause and the Congress also has the power under the Declare War Clause to interpret the Treaty. Hamilton fully understood the import of his argument – that, under it, two institutions had the power to undertake the same act – and indeed adopted virtually the same term that this Article utilizes, writing that “there results . . . a concurrent authority” as between the President and Congress. [nothing more than assertion; no real justification, apart from textualist claim, of sorts] Madison violently disagreed with Hamilton’s embrace of concurrence, dedicating the majority of his Second Helvidius Letter to disputing it. His position boils down to two arguments. First, Madison claims to identify a “material error” in Hamilton’s position insofar as, Madison claimed, Hamilton failed to fully apply the principles he adopts: 70 71 72 He [Hamilton] had before admitted that the right to declare war includes the right to judge whether the United States be obliged to declare war or not. Can the inference be avoided, that the executive instead of having a similar right to judge, is as much excluded from the right to judge as from the right to declare?73 It is not at all apparent, however, why Madison’s inference cannot be avoided – unless one assumes exclusivity, which of course is the very principle that Madison hopes to establish. Two paragraphs later Madison tries again to drive home the same point, but with no greater success. Madison asserts that Hamilton “cannot disentangle himself by considering the right of the executive to judge as concurrent with that of the legislature” for the following reason: “[f]or if the executive have a concurrent right to judge, and the right to judge be included in (it is in fact the very essence of) the right to declare, he 69 Pacificus Number 1, reproduced in Debates, supra note 2, at 13 (emphasis supplied). 70 See id. at 16. 71 See id. at 15. 72 Id. at 15. 73 Helvedius Number 2, reproduced in Debates, supra note 2, at 66 (emphasis supplied). [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 19 must go on and say that the executive has a concurrent right also to declare.” But why is this so if, as Hamilton hypothesized, the President’s right to interpret the Treaty derives from an independent presidential power? Why couldn’t the President interpret the Treaty for the purpose of exercising his independent power and the Congress interpret the Treaty for purposes of determining whether it should declare war? Here, once again, Madison circularly assumes his conclusion. So much for his first justification. Madison’s second justification for opposing concurrence is more substantive than his first. The trouble with concurrence, he correctly asserts, is that it opens the door to conflict among the two institutions vested with the same power: 74 If the legislature and executive have both a right to judge of the obligations to make war or not, it must sometimes happen . . . that they will judge differently . . . . In what light does this present the Constitution to the people who established it? In what light would it present to the world, a nation, thus speaking, thro’ two different organs, equally constitutional and authentic, two opposite language, on the same subject and under the same existing circumstances?75 Hamilton had a response to Madison’s argument. I shall discuss it in Part Five, which takes stock of six different mechanisms found in American law for resolving conflicts among institutions with overlapping power. Hamilton’s response tracks one of the six mechanisms. To provide a short preview, though, Point Five’s main response to Madison’s argument is twopronged. First, the mere possibility of conflict is not a categorical argument against concurrence, but instead means that a choice must be made among conflict-resolution principles and an assessment undertaken as to whether the benefits of concurrence are outweighed by its costs (primarily the possibility of conflict). Second -- and what amount to a corollary of the point made immediately above – even if the costs of conflict outweighed the benefits of concurrency in the context of treaty interpretation and foreign relations, it does not follow that concurrence is undesirable as a general matter across all doctrinal contexts. ****************************** Having carefully defined “concurrence” and “exclusivity” and introduced the concepts of same-source concurrence, same-effect concurrence, non-identicality, and imperfect overlap, we are ready to proceed to examine the many intriguing recurring patterns regarding the choice between exclusivity and concurrence. 76 II. THE HISTORICAL TRAJECTORY FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE A study of Supreme Court case law reveals the tenacity of exclusivist 74 Id. 75 Id. at 69. 76 See infra pp. 57. [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 20 assumptions. Virtually always the judiciary has initially adopted exclusivist assumptions and has been resilient to claims that power can be concurrently exercised. Generally, the Court has, over time, been willing to acknowledge concurrence, though the Court’s ultimate blessing of concurrence typically does not initiate the concurrent exercise of power but instead reflects a belated recognition of a widespread practice that has taken root outside the courtroom. In other contexts, the Court has created doctrines that formally cling to exclusivism notwithstanding the fact that virtually all scholars acknowledge that two institutions exercise concurrent powers. The bottom line, though, is that there is a clear trajectory in both practice and doctrine: initial exclusivist assumptions tend to give way to concurrence. A. Original Jurisdiction of the Various Federal Courts: The Road from Marbury to Ames. The substantive constitutional issue raised in Marbury v. Madison is both an early illustration of the choice between exclusivity or concurrence and an exemplar of the Court’s initial approach to answering the query. The Constitution provides that the “supreme court shall have original jurisdiction in all cases affecting ambassadors, other public ministers and consuls, and those in which a state shall be a party. In all other cases, the supreme court shall have appellate jurisdiction.” The (still to be created) inferior federal courts and/or state courts had original jurisdiction of the other matters that fell within scope of Article III’s “judicial power.” The substantive question famously presented in Marbury was whether Congress could expand the Supreme Court’s original jurisdiction beyond the three categories enumerated in the Constitution. The issue raised in the case clearly fell within the “judicial Power of the United States,” and the case also clearly fell within the original jurisdiction of the inferior courts that Congress had established. This is the respect in which Marbury presented the Court with the choice between exclusivity and concurrence: Marbury confronted the question of whether the Supreme Court’s original jurisdiction could be made to overlap with the inferior federal courts’ original jurisdiction. 77 78 79 80 81 77 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137 (1803). 78 U.S. CONST. ART. I, §2, cl. 2. 79 Cf. Question of whether all Art. III judicial power has to be vested in a federal court (Story), see generally Pfander, Cal. L. Rev. 80 The in the case issue concerned a question of federal law: the legal effect of a commission for public justice that had been signed by the President following the Senate’s advice and consent. 81 Other parts of the 1789 Judiciary Act more obviously presented this question. Section 13 of the Act provided that the Supreme Court had “exclusively” original jurisdiction over “suits or proceedings against ambassadors” but only “original, but not exclusive jurisdiction of all suits brought by ambassadors.” Id. (emphasis supplied). In other words, the Act provided that the Supreme Court’s original jurisdiction overlapped with inferior federal courts’ original jurisdiction in cases brought by (but not against) ambassadors. This provision of Section 13 raised the same issue presented in Marbury because the Constitution states that “[i]n all cases affecting Ambassadors . . . the supreme Court shall have original Jurisdiction.” [maybe not: maybe this is Ames redux: not whether S Court jdn can be expanded, but whether inferior court jdn can be expanded. In other words, the Constitution says that Supreme Court shall have original jurisdiction, but does not state the other courts cannot have original jdn as well. [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 21 The Court specifically considered the question of whether Congress could “assign original jurisdiction to [the Supreme Court] in other cases than those specified in” the Constitution. The Court rejected this proposition as follows: Affirmative words are often, in their operation, negative of other objects than those affirmed; and in this case, a negative or exclusive sense must be given to them or they have no operation at all.82 As Professor Tribe has noted, Chief Justice Marshall’s reasoning here is an example of the principle of expressio unius est exclusio alterius: from the fact that the Constitution “apportion[ed] the judicial power between the supreme and inferior courts,” Marshall concluded that only the institution that had been constitutionally allocated original jurisdiction, and no other, could exercise original jurisdiction. Any other interpretation would render the Constitution’s grant “mere surplusage.” Chief Justice Marshall’s chief justification for Marbury’s substantive holding accordingly was an exclusivist argument. My intention here is not to suggest that this portion of Marbury was incorrectly decided, but instead to show that its exclusivist justification has not fared well. Consider in this regard the Court’s decision in Ames v. State of Kansas. The State of Kansas had sued several corporations in Kansas state courts, and defendants had removed to an inferior federal court in reliance on the federal question statute, which grants inferior federal courts jurisdiction over cases raising questions of federal law. At issue in Ames was the constitutionality of the federal question statute’s application to a case in which 83 84 85 86 87 88 89 82 5 U.S. at xx. 83 Laurence H. Tribe, Taking Text and Structure Seriously: Reflections on Free-Form Method in Constitutional Interpretation, 108 HARV. L. REV. 1221, 1275 (1995). 84 See Marbury, 5 U.S. at 174 (“If it had been intended to leave it in the discretion of the legislature to apportion the judicial power between the supreme and inferior courts according to the will of that body, it would certainly have been useless to have proceeded further than to have defined the judicial power, and the tribunals in which it should be vested. The subsequent part of the section is mere surplusage, is entirely without meaning, if such is to be the construction. If congress remains at liberty to give this court appellate jurisdiction, where the constitution has declared their jurisdiction shall be original; and original jurisdiction where the constitution has declared it shall be appellate; the distribution of jurisdiction, made in the constitution, is form without substance.”). 85 Marbury, 5 U.S. at 174. 86 Id. at 174. 87 Indeed, there was strong constitutional language on which the Chief Justice could have relied. After enumerating the cases in which the Supreme Court is to have original jurisdiction, Article III provides that “[i]n all other cases, the supreme court shall have appellate jurisdiction.” U.S. CONST. ART. III, §2, CL. 2. Extending the Supreme Court’s original jurisdiction to include mandamus correspondingly diminishes its appellate jurisdiction and hence could be said to run afoul of this constitutional language. On the other hand, the very last phrase of the above sentence from Article III appears to grant Congress the power to make “exceptions” to the Supreme Court’s appellate jurisdiction. Id. For a collection of sources that examine these competing textual arguments here, see James E. Pfander, Marbury, Original Jurisdiction, and the Supreme Court’s Supervisory Powers, 101 COLUM. L. REV. 1515, 1517 & n. 5 (2001). 88 111 U.S. 449 (1884). 89 Id. at 463. [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 22 a state was a party: Could Congress assign original jurisdiction to an inferior federal court when the Constitution granted the Supreme Court “original jurisdiction” in “all Cases . . . in which a State shall be Party”? The Ames Court acknowledged that Marbury “used language . . . which might, perhaps, imply that such original jurisdiction as had been granted by the constitution was exclusive.” On this approach, the Supreme Court alone (among federal courts) would have had original jurisdiction over cases as this in which a state was a party on account of Article III’s grant of original jurisdiction to the Supreme Court. But Ames rejected this approach and ultimately upheld Congress’ power to grant inferior courts original jurisdiction over the same subjects that fall within the Supreme Court’s Constitution-granted original jurisdiction. Ames instead relied on a rationale that had been provided by Chief Justice Taney in a circuit opinion: 90 91 92 the grant of jurisdiction over a certain subject-matter to one court does not, of itself, imply that the jurisdiction is to be exclusive. In the clause in question [in the Constitution] there is nothing but mere affirmative words of grant, and none that import a design to exclude the subordinate jurisdiction of other courts of the United States on the same subjectmatter.93 The italicized language, it should be noted, is precisely the same argument that Professors Merrill and Sunstein provide in defense of Congress’ powers to delegate legislative authority to agencies. Three important lessons emerge from considering the relationship between the Taney rationale in Ames and Chief Justice Marshall’s reasoning in Marbury. First, the two are at loggerheads. Marbury instructs that the Constitution’s grants of power are conclusively presumed to be exclusive. Otherwise, said Chief Justice Marshall, the Constitution’s language would be “mere surplusage.” Ames, by contrast, strips any presumption of exclusivity from the Constitution’s grant of power to a particular institution. Second, insofar as much of the Constitution’s text consists of affirmative grants of power to particular institutions, the interpretive question that both Marbury and Ames address – whether the Constitution’s affirmative grant of power is to be construed as a constitutional mandate that only that institution have the specified power – is pervasive. 94 95 90 U.S. CONST. ART. III, s. 2, cl. 2. 91 Ames, 111 U.S. at 467. 92 See Ames, 111 U.S. at 447 (“we are unable to say that it is not within the power of congress to grant to the inferior courts of the United States jurisdiction in cases where the supreme court has been vested by the constitution with original jurisdiction.”). 93 Ames, 111 U.S. at 468 (quoting Gittings v. Crawford)(emphasis supplied). 94 See supra at xx. 95 Though additional constitutional language conceivably could answer the question, eg, “all” the power shall vest. Interesting, though, that Ames didn’t rely on this textual warrant in distinguishing Marbury. [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 23 Third, and finally, Ames’ and Marbury’s contrary resolutions to the interpretive question strongly suggest that constitutional text alone does not answer the question of whether constitutional grants are exclusive. How then is the decision to be made as to whether the Constitution’s power-grants are exclusive or potentially concurrent? This important question will be taken up in Part III. B. Fact-Finding in Civil Adjudication: Of Juries, Judges, and Non-Article III Adjudicative Tribunals The Seventh Amendment allocates power to the hybrid public/private institution known as the jury, granting juries the power “[i]n Suits at common law” to “tr[y] . . . fact[s].” The Seventh Amendment simultaneously limits the power of federal judges, providing that “[c]ourt[s]” are not permitted to “re-examine[]” the jury’s findings “otherwise . . . than according to the rules of the common law.” The Court long has held that “common law” for these purposes refers to the procedures for re-examining jury verdicts that were available in English common law in 1791, when the Seventh Amendment was adopted. This section shows that, and explains how, an exclusive regime in which only juries had the power to find facts was transformed into a system of concurrence. Today, the power to fact-find during adjudication is held jointly by juries, ordinary federal judges, and non-Article III adjudicative tribunals. Subsection 1 examines the trajectory from exclusivity to concurrence as between juries and Article III judges. To this day, the Court has been reluctant to formally acknowledge the concurrence that exists. Subsection 2 examines the trajectory from exclusivity to concurrence as between juries and Article I tribunals. A different story appears here: though the Court initially denied and sought to tightly cabin concurrence, it ultimately was forthright in acknowledging concurrence. 1. Juries and Judges. Suja Thomas has shown that English common law as of 1791 adopted what this Article dubs an “exlusivist” allocation of duties in which only the jury, not the judge, had power to find facts. Under three common law procedures, neither the judge nor jury found facts: instead, the parties stipulated to the facts (the “demurrer to the pleadings,” the “demurrer to the evidence,” and the “special case” under the parties’ agreement as to the facts), and the judge thereafter applied the law to 96 97 98 96 U.S. CONST. AMEND. VII. 97 See, e.g., Gasperini v. Center for Humanities, Inc., 518 U.S. 415, 435-36 & n. 20 (1996). While riding circuit, Justice Story was among the first of the American jurists to equate the Seventh Amendment’s language of “common law” with the “common law of England.” United States v. Wonson, 1 Ga.. 5, 20 (1812); see also Slocum v. New York Life Insurance Co., 228 U.S. 364, 377 (1913) (approvingly quoting this language from Justice Story’s Wonson opinion). 98 Suja A. Thomas, Why Summary Judgment is Unconstitutional, 93 VA. L. REV. 139, 143 (2007) (showing that only “the jury or the parties determined the facts,” not the judge, under English common law at the time of 1791). [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 24 the stipulated facts. Under the other common law procedures, the jury’s finding of facts provided the ground for the case’s outcome. In the “special case” following a jury’s general verdict, the court decided a disputed question of law but used the jury’s findings of fact. Common law courts could grant motions for a “new trial” on the ground that the evidence did not support the jury’s verdict, but the result was a new trial during which time a (new) jury would find the facts. Finally, under a compulsory nonsuit, a common law court could enter judgment for a defendant following jury verdict for plaintiff, but only if the jury’s verdict were unsupported as to a particular matter of law. Early American jurisprudence tracked England’s exclusivist approach to dividing power between judge and jury. The 1913 case of Slocum v. New York Life Insurance Co., and the cases on which it relied, are representative. Before adoption of the federal rules of civil procedure in 1938, a federal statute directed federal courts to apply state procedural rules in all common law matters. Pennsylvania law at the time of the Slocum decision permitted what today would be called a judgment notwithstanding the verdict: Pennsylvania procedure authorized judges to disregard jury verdicts on finding the evidence insufficient and instead to enter judgment for the other party. The Slocum Court ruled that this procedure, when applied by federal courts, violated the Seventh Amendment. The problem was not that the federal court had set aside the verdict, for procedures available under the common law (such as the motion for new trial) authorized courts to set aside jury verdicts under specific circumstances. The sole problem, according to Slocum, was that Pennsylvania’s procedural rule permitted the judge to “itself pass on the issues of fact” by issuing a judgment for the other party. The assumption of “exclusivity” – the notion that the jury’s and judge’s constitutional duties vis-a-vis facts were wholly distinct and nonoverlapping – pervaded the Slocum decision. The following statement of the Court is illustrative: 99 100 101 102 103 104 In the trial by jury, the right to which is secured by the Seventh Amendment, both the court and the jury are essential factors. To the former is committed a power of direction and superintendence, 99 See id. at 148-154, 156-57. Under the demurrer to the pleadings and demurrer to the evidence, one party admitted to the facts alleged by the other party (the former after the pleadings had been filed, the latter during the trial itself). Id. at 148-54. Under the special case, the parties could jointly stipulate to specific facts. Id. at 156-57. 100 Id. at 157-58. 101 Id. at 155. Of particular relevance to the discussion above, insufficient evidence was not a basis for a compulsory nonsuit. Id. 102 228 U.S. 364, 382 (1913) 103 See Practice Conformity Act, ch. 225, 17 Stat. 197 (1872). For a discussion, see Ellen E. Sward, The Seventh Amendment and the Alchemy of Fact and Law, 33 SETON HALL L. REV. 573, 583 & n. 63 (2003). 104 Id. at 387-88. [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 25 and to the latter the ultimate determination of the issues of fact. Only through the cooperation of the two, each acting within its appropriate sphere, can the constitutional right be satisfied. And so, to . . .permit one to disregard the province of the other is to impinge on that right.105 Indeed, the Slocum Court quoted considerable precedent that supported its “exclusivist” conception regarding the division of labor between judge and jury. As early as 1812, Justice Story, sitting as a circuit justice, had observed that “the facts once tried by a jury are never re-examined, unless a new trial is granted in the discretion of the court before which the suit is depending . . . or unless the judgment of such court is reversed by a superior tribunal . . .” The logic of exclusivism was even more clearly in an 1885 case in which the Supreme Court reversed a federal court that had awarded judgment for the defendant after the jury had returned a verdict for the plaintiff because “without a waiver of the right of trial by jury, by consent of parties, the court errs if it substitutes itself for the jury, and, passing upon the effect of the evidence, finds the facts involved in the issue and renders judgment thereon.” An 1899 Supreme Court decision likewise stated that “[t]he facts there tried and decided cannot be re-examined in any court of the United Stated States . . . [N]o other mode of re-examination is allowed than upon a new trial, either granted by the court in which the first trial was had or to which the record was returnable, or ordered by an appellate court for error in law.” But exclusivism did not hold for long. Two lines of Supreme Court decisions together had the effect of giving judges significant fact-finding powers. Because this augmentation of the judge’s power occurred without depriving juries of their fact-finding powers, the result was a regime in which judges and juries had concurrent powers to find facts. The first line of decisions addressed the question of when federal courts could keep cases from juries on the ground that insufficient evidence had been put forward. The second line of cases concerned what federal courts were permitted to do after determining that evidence presented was not legally sufficient. As to the first line of cases, the traditional rule was that a “case must go to the jury unless there was ‘no evidence.’” The 1871 case of Improvement Company v. Munson acknowledged (though derogatorily renamed) the traditional rule, and then proceeded to “completely repudiate[]” it: 106 107 108 109 110 111 105 Id. at 382 (emphasis supplied). 106 United States v. Wonson, 1 Gall. 5, 20 (1812). Justice Story reiterated this understanding while writing for the Supreme Court in Parsons v. Bedford, 28 U.S. (3 Pet.) 433, 447-48 (1830). 107 Baylis v. Travellers’ Ins. Co., 113 U.S. 316 (1885) (emphasis supplied), quoted in Slocum, 228 U.S. at 386-87. 108 See Capital Traction Co. v. Hof, 174 U.S. 1, 13 (1899), quoted in Slocum, 228 U.S. at 379. 109 See Galloway v. United States, 319 U.S. 372, 404 (1943) (Black, J., dissenting). For some examples of the traditional rule, see, e.g., Drakely v. Gregg, 8 Wall. 242, 268 (case to jury if evidence “tended to prove the position” of the party); Hickman v. Jones, 9 Wall. 197, 201. 110 81 U.S. 442 (1871). 111 Galloway, 319 U.S. at 404 (Black, J., dissenting). [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 26 Formerly it was held that if there was what is called a scintilla of evidence in support of a case the judge was bound to leave it to the jury, but recent decisions of high authority have established a more reasonable rule, that in every case, before the evidence is left to the jury, there is a preliminary question for the judge, not whether there is literally no evidence, but whether there is any upon which a jury can properly proceed to find a verdict for the party producing it, upon whom the onus of proof is imposed.112 In shifting from one legal test to another, the Court opened the door to judges assuming significant fact-finding powers. Under the traditional rule, the jury’s power to fact-find could not be exercised by the judge because the jury heard the case if there was “‘any evidence’ to support a party’s contention;” the judge could keep a matter from the jury only if there was no evidence to be weighed or analyzed and hence no facts to be found. The replacement test introduced in Munson, by contrast, authorized judges to keep matters from the jury by deciding that the facts that had been put into the record could not “properly” ground a verdict in view of the facts that had been put in by the other side. After the Munson rule took root, there is little question that federal judges in fact took on the role of finding facts. This is well illustrated by the case of Pennsylvania Railroad v. Chamberlain, which concerned the propriety of a trial court’s order that a jury grant verdict for defendant. Writing for the Second Circuit, Judge Learned Hand had reversed the district court’s judgment, ruling that the district court should have allowed the case to proceed to the jury because there was sufficient evidence to support a verdict for the plaintiff. Citing to the Munson rule, the Supreme Court reversed Judge Hand, deciding that the testimony of plaintiff’s sole witness could not have supported a verdict for the plaintiff. It is hard to escape the conclusion that the Supreme Court made credibility determinations and weighed the evidence. Plaintiff’s witness was an experienced train yard worker who testified 113 114 115 116 117 118 112 Munson, 81 U.S. at 448 (emphasis supplied). 113 The “recent decisions of high authority” on which the Supreme Court relied all were decisions from England that post-dated 1791. For a critical discussion of the Supreme Court’s reliance on these cases, see Sward, supra note 103, at 594-99 (concluding that the English cases “in no way can [ ] be construed as allowing judges to take cases away from the jury when there are disputes of pure questions of fact . . .”). 114 Galloway, 319 U.S. at 404 (Black, J., dissenting). 115 Cf. Greenleaf v. Birth, 9 Pet. 292, 299 (1835) (“Where there is no evidence tending to prove a particular fact, the court(s) are bound so to instruct the jury, when requested; but they cannot legally give any instruction which shall take from the jury the right of weighing the evidence and determining what effect it shall have.”). 116 For some time after Munson, the United States Supreme Court continued to recite the pre-Munson “any evidence” test. See, e.g., Hepner v. United States, 213 U.S. 103, 115 (1909) (summarizing the law as “requiring the court to send a case to the jury . . . where the evidence is conflicting on any essential point”). 117 288 U.S. 333 (1933). 118 See 59 F.2d 986. [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 27 that he saw a faster-moving 9-car train closely trailing a slower-moving 2-car train, heard a loud crash, and thereafter discovered the decedent’s body. The Court held that there was no evidence of a collision because the defendant railroad company’s witnesses testified there had been no train crash and plaintiff’s witness had said he heard a “loud crash” but did not use the word “collision.” If this on its own were not enough, the conclusion that the Court engaged in fact-finding seems irresistible in view of its statement that “[t]he fact that [the defendant railroad’s] witnesses were employees of the [railroad] . . . does not impair this conclusion.” This last statement, after all, is an explicit assessment that the railroad’s witnesses were credible, and credibility determinations are widely (and correctly) understood to be a crucial component of fact-finding. The second line of cases responsible for shifting concurrent factfinding authority to federal courts concerned what judges were permitted to do upon determining the evidence to be insufficient to support a judgment. Two common law features assured that juries, not judges, alone made the ultimate findings of fact. First, the common law in 1791 did not have a procedure akin to the directed verdict under which a party could ask the court to rule in his favor after trial but before the jury’s verdict on the ground that the other party’s evidence was insufficient. Second, although the common law permitted the losing party to challenge the verdict after the jury had delivered its verdict on grounds of insufficient evidence, a winning motion netted a new trial before another jury, not a judge-awarded verdict. Twentieth century cases eliminated these two limitations, importantly augmenting judges’ fact-finding authority. As to the first limitation, the decision of Galloway v. United States upheld the directed verdict under the newly adopted federal rules of civil procedure, permitting the judge to enter judgment after trial but before the jury had offered its verdict. Although many previous Supreme Court decisions had approved procedures akin to the directed verdict, Galloway appears to have been the first decision to allow a directed verdict on the ground of insufficient evidence. The significance of the Galloway decision’s approval of the directed verdict is dramatically 119 120 121 122 123 124 119 Id. at 338. 120 Id. at 343. 121 For another example, see the discussion of Galloway v. United States, 319 U.S. 372 (1943), infra note 125. 122 The common law procedure permitting a party to move for judgment after trial but before verdict, the demurrer to the evidence, required that the moving party stipulate to the facts alleged by the non-moving party. Galloway v. United States, 319 U.S. 372, 390 (1943). The judge accordingly did not find facts, but took the facts stipulated by the moving party and applied the stipulated facts to the law. See Thomas, supra note 98, at 150-54. 123 319 U.S. 372 (1943). 124 See Sward, supra note 103, at 599-613 (showing that earlier decisions had upheld directed verdicts where one of the parties had offered no evidence at all or where court was asked to apply undisputed facts to the law). [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 28 amplified by the earlier Munson decision, which rejected the “any evidence” rule and, as discussed above, gave judges the power to fact-find. Indeed, Galloway itself well-illustrates the federal judge’s new powers to fact-find; three dissenting Justices in the Galloway decision carefully reviewed the documentary and testimonial evidence that had been adduced at trial and convincingly demonstrated that the majority in the case, as well as the trial judge, had “weigh[ed] conflicting evidence” and made credibility assessments. As to the second original limitation, the decision in Baltimore & Carolina Line v. Redman held that federal judges could not only disregard a jury’s verdict on grounds of insufficient evidence, but also immediately enter a verdict for the other party – the equivalent of a judgment notwithstanding the verdict. Redman was an abrupt break with the Slocum decision discussed above, which only twenty years before had held precisely the opposite. As with the Galloway decision’s upholding of the directed verdict, Redman’s full significance vis-a-vis judges’ fact-finding powers can be understood only upon taking account of Munson’s rule. Indeed, by the time the Redman case came before the Supreme Court, “four judges had considered the sufficiency of the evidence, with two believing that the evidence was sufficient, and two believing that it was not.” This alone strongly suggests that the judges’ 125 126 127 128 129 125 See Galloway, 319 U.S. at 397 (Black, J., dissenting). the Supreme Court in Galloway v. United States, 319 U.S. 372 (1943), upheld a directed verdict against a veteran who had sued for benefits due under a war risk insurance policy. The veteran had the burden of proving “total and permanent” disability no later than May 31, 1919. The veteran’s guardian introduced testimony from a doctor who had diagnosed the veteran as suffering from a form of dementia that had been triggered by the shock of conflict on the battle field before 1919. The veteran also had offered the testimony of 2 fellow soldiers, a friend who had known him both before and after the war, and his Commanding Officer, all of whom testified to behaviors that were consistent with the symptoms of insanity that the testifying doctor had identified. Id. at 408-12. Reviewing this testimony in detail, three Justices reasonably concluded in dissent that the majority of the Court “re-examine[d] testimony offered in a common law suit [and] weigh[ed] conflicting evidence.” Id. at 397 (Black, J., dissenting); see also Sward, supra note 103, at 603 (noting that “[t]he issue in Galloway could not be classified as anything other than a question of fact: was Galloway permanently and totally disabled by reason of mental illness as of May 31, 191, or not?”). Simply put, the majority’s assertion that they “gave full credence to all of the testimony” is not credible. Galloway, 319 U.S. at 396. 126 See 295 U.S. 654 (1935). 127 Redman predated the federal rules of civil procedure and, pursuant to a federal statute then in force, applied the procedures of the state in which the federal court sat. See Redman, 295 U.S. at 661. 128 To be sure, the Redman Court distinguished Slocum on the ground that the trial court had not yet decided the defendant’s motion to dismiss and motion for directed verdict, both of which had been submitted to the court before the jury began its deliberations. Redman, 295 U.S. at 658-59. The Second Circuit had not deemed this technical difference to be material, and even the Redman Court acknowledged that “some parts of the [Slocum] opinion give color to the interpretation put on it by the Court of Appeals.” Id. at 661. A fair reading of Slocum shows Redman’s acknowledgment to be a decided understatement. Commentators justifiably have understood Redman as having effectively reversed Slocum. See, e.g., Thomas, supra note 98, at 168-73 (concluding that Redman was a “drastic change” from Slocum); Sward, supra note 103, at 613-24 (“contrast[ing]” Redman and Slocum and showing that Redman was not supported by other cases the opinion had relied upon). 129 Sward, supra note 103, at 616. Because the Supreme Court did not grant certiorari on the sufficiency of the evidence, its opinion in Redman provides only a cursory review of the facts. Professor Sward nicely reviews the factual record as it was discussed in the court of appeals decision, definitively showing that the judges who had determined the evidence to be inadequate had weighed evidence and assessed [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 29 determination that the evidence was insufficient was itself based on judicial fact-finding, a conclusion that a review of the record bears out. To be clear, Munson, Galloway, and Redman did not displace the jury’s fact-finding powers and thereby replace one exclusivist regime with another. Rather, these (and other) decisions created a regime in which judges also had fact-finding powers. The contemporary result is a regime of concurrence in which judges and juries both have fact-finding powers: juries still find facts and return verdicts, but judges also exercise fact-finding powers when they issue directed verdicts, motions-notwithstanding-the-judgment, and summary judgments. As to the latter, a federal court deciding a motion for summary judgment must determine if there is a “genuine issue as to any material fact” by asking whether “a reasonable jury could return a verdict for the nonmoving party.” Under these standards, federal judges now “decide[] whether factual inferences from the evidence are reasonable,” with the result that “[c]ases that would have been decided by a jury under the common law are now dismissed by a judge under summary judgment.” To date, however, the Court has not been willing to acknowledge the degree to which federal courts have been awarded fact-finding powers that used to belong solely to juries. 2. Juries and non-Article III Adjudicatory Tribunals. Juries today share adjudicatory fact-finding power not only with article III judges, but with yet another governmental institution: judges on non-Article III tribunals. Administrative agencies are the most important of these non-Article III tribunals. The rule today, as stated in the 1977 case of Atlas Roofing Co. v. Occupational Safety and Health Review Commission, is that “when Congress creates new statutory ‘public rights,’ it may assign their adjudication to an administrative agency” and the non-Article III administrative judge then has the power to find facts. Further, “[t]his is the case even if the Seventh Amendment would have required a jury [were] the adjudication of those rights [to be] assigned instead to a federal court . . .” In other words, at least as 130 131 132 133 134 135 credibility. See id. at 614-16. 130 See supra note 129. 131 Fed. R. Civ. P. 56. 132 Anderson v. Liberty Lobby, Inc., 477 U.S. 242, 248 (1986). 133 Thomas, supra note 98, at 143. 134 Atlas Roofing Co., Inc. v. Occupational Safety and Health Review Commission, 430 U.S. 442, 455 (1977). 135 Id. Independent of the Seventh Amendment question of whether administrative judges rather than juries can find facts is the question of whether adjudicatory facts can be found by non-article III courts – what is variously conceptualized as either a due process or an Article III question. Most federal legislative schemes provide that agency facts are reviewable by federal courts (sometimes district courts, sometimes only courts of appeals) under a substantial-evidence test, id. at 456 & n. 13, and this has repeatedly been held to be constitutional. Id. The Supreme Court has not yet decided whether Congress could “commit the adjudication of public rights and the imposition of fines for their violation to an administrative agency without any sort of intervention by a court at any stage of the proceedings.” Id. [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 30 regards public rights, the Supreme Court has forthrightly acknowledged that administrative agencies and juries have concurrent authority to fact-find as a constitutional matter. This amounts to significant concurrence because, as Professor Monaghan recently has reminded us, “[t]he ‘public rights’ exception is a wide and significant one” that “has been significantly enlarged so as to absorb much of what hitherto had fallen into the private rights domain.” Consistent with the general trajectory from exclusivity to concurrence documented above in other doctrinal contexts, the Supreme Court has not always acknowledged this concurrent regime. To the contrary, during most of our country’s history, the Court has understood the Constitution’s allocation of adjudicatory fact-finding authority in exclusivist terms. Cases from the nineteenth and early twentieth century regularly asserted that lawsuits brought by the federal government in federal court for civil penalties in violation of federal statutes – in other words, lawsuits premised on what today would be called “public rights” – qualified as “suits at common law” that accordingly entitled the defendant to a jury under the Seventh Amendment. The first case that upheld the constitutionality of a federal statute that transferred adjudication from trial courts to an administrative agency without affording a jury– a laconic decision by Justice Holmes in the 1921 case of Block v. Hirsh– did so on the grounds that there existed an “exigency” on account of the First World War that justified the “suspension of [the] ordinary remedies” of trial by jury. The “publicly notorious . . . emergency” that Congress sought to cure was inadequate rental properties in the District of Columbia to accommodate employees of the federal government, and the act addressed the problem by permitting tenants to remain in possession at the same rent they had been paying so long as the rent paid was “reasonable” in the determination of a housing commission established by the act. The bulk of Justice Holmes’ opinion addressed not the Seventh Amendment, but whether the rent control statute violated due process, constituted a taking without just compensation, and violated the contracts clause. Only after concluding that “a public exigency will justify the legislature in restricting property rights in land to a certain extent without compensation” did the Court, in its final paragraph, address the Seventh Amendment. It cursorily concluded that “[i]f the power of the Commission established by the statute to regulate the relation is established, as we think it 136 137 138 139 140 141 142 136 Congress has a choice as to which institution to entrust with fact-finding authority. 137 Monaghan, supra note 167, at 868. 138 Id. at 873. 139 See, e.g., Hepner v. United States, 213 U.S. 103, 115 (1909) (defendant “entitled to have a jury summoned” in action of debt brought by the United States to recover penalty under federal statute regulating immigration of aliens); United States v. Regan, 232 U.S. 37, 47 (1914) (same). 140 Block v. Hirsh, 256 U.S. 135, 158 (1921). 141 Id. at 154-57. 142 Id. at 156. [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 31 is, by what we have said, this objection [based on the Seventh Amendment] amounts to little. To regulate the relation and to decide the facts affecting it are hardly separable.” In other words, so long as constitutional limitations apart from the Seventh Amendment did not render the statute’s substantive provisions unconstitutional, the Seventh Amendment was not violated either. To this not-very self-evident proposition Holmes added two more brief justifications. The very emergency justifying the act’s substantive provisions equally excuse its summary procedures: because “[a] part of the exigency is to secure a speedy and summary administration of the law” the housing emergency also justified dispensing with jury trials. Finally, in any event, Holmes wrote that there wasn’t much in the way of jury fact-finding was being displaced, for “[w]hile the act is in force there is little to decide except whether the rent allowed is reasonable . . .” In short, the Block decision upheld what it deemed to be only a limited incursion by an administrative agency into the jury’s fact-finding domain, and did so on the narrow ground that the statute at issue aimed to remedy a national emergency. Conversely, Block understood that a jury right to hear the type of issues that were being decided by an administrative agency was among a citizen’s “ordinary remedies.” The next two Supreme Court decisions upholding administrative agencies’ fact-finding powers did so by means of rationales wholly consistent with exclusivism. The 1937 case decision of NRLB v. Jones & Laughlin Steel Corp., best known for its commerce clause holding, also decided that the National Labor Relations Board’s power to decide whether an unfair labor practice had been committed and to order backpay did not violate the Seventh Amendment. The Court reasoned that the NLRB’s power did not trench at all on the jury’s role guarded by the Seventh Amendment. Said the Jones & Laughlin Steel Court, 143 144 145 146 147 148 [t]he instant case is not a suit at common law or in the nature of such a suit. The proceeding is one unknown to the common law. 143 Id. at 158. 144 Holmes’ proposition here is not self-evident because the Seventh Amendment is a constitutional limitation that is independent of due process, the takings clause, and the contracts clause. Accordingly, the mere fact that a statute does not violate these other clauses does not really tell us anything about whether the Seventh Amendment is violated. For a similar argument, see Ellen E. Sward, Legislative Courts, Article III, and the Seventh Amendment, 77 N.C, L. REV. 1037, 1041-42, 1099-1105 (1999). 145 Block, 256 U.S. at 158. 146 Id. (emphasis supplied). In fact, however, questions apart whether the rent was “reasonable” also could arise under the act. Because the act provided that the owner shall have possession following 30 days notice “for actual and bona fide occupancy by himself, or his wife, children or dependent,” id. at 154, the question could arise as to whether an owner seeking to displace a tenant on this ground indeed was going to occupy the residence. Indeed, the owner in the Block case had alleged that he wanted the premises for his own use and the tenant had denied this. Id. at 156. 147 Id. at 158. 148 301 U.S. 1 (1937). [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 32 It is a statutory proceeding.149 Because the Seventh Amendment by its terms applies only to “Suits at common law,” the Jones & Laughlin Steel Court’s analysis meant that the NLRB was performing functions that did not fall under the Seventh Amendment. The 1966 decision in Katchen v. Landy, which upheld the power of a bankruptcy court, sitting without a jury, to adjudicate issues that would have been entitled to a jury trial if the trustee had pressed the issues in a separate lawsuit in federal court, similarly came to its conclusion with a rationale thoroughly consistent with exclusivism. The Court reasoned that what would have been a legal claim if pursued on its own is “convert[ed]” into an equitable claim when it arises “as part of the process of allowance and disallowance of claims” in bankruptcy. Because the Seventh Amendment does not attach to equitable proceedings – its reference to “Suits at common law” long has been understood to mean that the Seventh Amendment applies to suits in “law” but not in “equity” – the Katchen Court readily concluded that the Seventh Amendment did not allocate power to the jury to hear voidable preference claims raised in the context of a bankruptcy proceeding. This reasoning is wholly consistent with exclusivism insofar as the power exercised by the bankruptcy judge did not overlap at all with the jury’s Seventh Amendment granted powers. Two cases in 1974 radically shifted the rationale for agencies’ powers to engage in adjudicatory fact-finding and, in the process, created – or, perhaps more accurately, acknowledged – a regime of concurrence. The question in Curtis v. Loether was whether the Seventh Amendment entitled litigants to a jury trial in actions for damages under the Civil Rights Act’s fair housing provisions. According to the logic of Jones & Laughlin Steel the answer should have been no because the housing right at issue in Curtis was “unknown to the common law” and instead was “a statutory proceeding.” In finding that litigants were entitled to a jury, Curtis radically retooled Jones & 150 151 152 153 154 155 156 157 149 Id. at 48-9. 150 The NLRB Court provided a second rationale that also was consistent with exclusivism. The Seventh Amendment’s application to cases at “common law” long had been understood to mean that Seventh Amendment rights did not attach to cases in equity, and the NLRB Court ruled that the case brought by the NLRB was analogous to a case in equity rather than law. Id. at 48-9. The Court further held that any monetary relief via orders of backpay were merely “incident[al] to (nonlegal relief) even though damages might have been recovered in an action at law.” Id. 151 382 U.S. 323 (1966) (bankruptcy judges can decide voidable preferences without a jury). 152 Id. at 336. 153 Id. 154 See Parsons v. Bedford, 3 Pet. 433, 446-47 (1830). 155 Id. at 336-38. 156 415 U.S. 189 (1974). 157 301 U.S. at 48-9. [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 33 Laughlin Steel, asserting that the case “merely stands for the proposition that the Seventh Amendment is generally inapplicable in administrative proceedings, where jury trials would be incompatible with the whole concept of administrative adjudication and would substantially interfere with the NLRB’s role in the statutory scheme.” Three interrelated aspects of Curtis merit notice. First, whereas Jones & Laughlin justified its conclusion on the nature of the legal right at issue (that the legal right was statutory rather than common law based), Curtis’s holding instead turned on where the litigation occurred: no jury in administrative proceedings, jury in federal courts. Second, this shift created a regime of concurrence: under Curtis’ approach, the identical legal right could be decided by either a jury-free administrative agency or a court with jury. Third, Curtis justified administrative agencies’ adjudicatory powers on the basis of naked pragmatism: the Seventh Amendment is “generally inapplicable to administrative proceedings” because “jury trials would be incompatible with the whole concept of administrative adjudication.” The same three elements are on display in the 1974 case of Pernell v. Southall Realty. Like the Curtis decision, Pernell re-rationalized an earlier decision – this time Block v. Hirsh – that had served to cabin agencies’ adjudicatory powers vis-a-vis juries. Whereas Block had upheld the agency’s jury-free adjudicatory powers on the ground that exigent circumstances justified an exception to a litigant’s “ordinary remedies,” Pernell recharacterized Block as standing for a business-as-usual principle, stating that the case “merely stands for the principle that the Seventh Amendment is generally inapplicable in administrative proceedings . . .” As in Curtis, the Seventh Amendment’s inapplicability was justified purely on practical grounds. Finally, Pernell explicitly acknowledged the regime of concurrence it had created. Pernell ruled that the Seventh Amendment required a jury to adjudicate the right to possession of real property at issue in the case because the adjudication took place in an ordinary federal court. The Court went on to observe that “[w]e may assume that the Seventh Amendment would not be a bar to a congressional effort to entrust landlord-tenant disputes, including those over the right to possession, to an administrative agency.” The Pernell decision thus expressly acknowledges that the identical dispute could be resolved either by a jury (before a court) or a jury-free administrative agency. Concurrence was fully acknowledged. As this section’s 158 159 160 161 162 163 158 415 U.S. at 194-95. 159 Id. 160 416 U.S. 363 (1974). 161 Id. at 383. 162 Id. (stating that “jury trials would be incompatible with the whole concept of administrative adjudication”). 163 Id. at 383. See also Atlas Roofing Co. Inc. v. Occupational Safety and Health Review Commission, 430 U.S. 442, 455 (1977) (affirming this rule). [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 34 tour through the case law shows, though, such a forthright acknowledgment was a long time in the making. C. Adjudicatory Jurisdiction of Article III and non-Article III Courts. Article III’s language that the “judicial Power of the United States, shall be vested in one supreme Court, and in such inferior Courts as the Congress may from time to time ordain and establish” is readily prone to being understood to mean that the federal judicial power only can be vested in Article III courts, i.e., in an exclusivist manner. But, as Professor Monaghan writes, 164 [t]he expanding national government and the rapidly expanding national domain quickly rendered any such conception untenable. From the very beginning, the Court recognized ‘exceptions,’ i.e., that significant federal adjudication could occur in non-Article III tribunals.165 As the following discussion shows, Professor Mongahan’s perspicacious observation is correct save for one thing: the Supreme Court long denied that federal adjudication was occurring outside of article III courts, acknowledging only in the 1960s that non-article III tribunals could exercise federal jurisdiction. In other words, the historical trajectory noted in the movement from Marbury to Ames recurs here: initial efforts to square the non-Article III tribunals with an exclusivist interpretation of Article III ultimately gave way to the recognition that non-Article III institutions share concurrent adjudicatory power with Article III courts. In short, Professor Monaghan appears to have anachronistically read today’s acceptance of concurrence back into the earlier caselaw, obscuring the Supreme Court’s initial and longstanding reluctance to abandon exclusivism. Just as Ames rejected an exclusivist construction of the Constitution’s grants of original jurisdiction to the Supreme Court, contemporary doctrine has rejected an exclusivist interpretation under which only Article III courts can exercise “judicial Power,” opting instead for a system in which “article I courts and the article III courts frequently exercise a concurrent jurisdiction or otherwise share portions of the judicial business.” A circuit court case decided early in our country’s history – the 1803 166 167 164 See Caleb Nelson, Adjudication in the Political Branches, 107 COLUM. L. REV. 559, 565 (2007). Nelson; Bator; CFTC v. Schor, 478 U.S. 833 (1986) (acknowledging that “[o]n its face, Article III, §1, seems to prohibit the vesting of any judicial functions in either the Legislative or the Executive Branch.”) (Brennan, J., dissenting) (emphasis in original); Cf. Monaghan, supra note 167, at 868 (“Article III might (at least as an original matter) have been understood to require that if any adjudication by federal tribunals occurs, it must occur in Article III courts”). 165 Id. at 868. 166 As will be discussed, however, two notable scholarly tomes recently have argued that non-article III institutions do not in fact exercise constitutional “judicial power.” 167 See Paul M. Bator, The Constitution as Architecture: Legislative and Administrative Courts Under Article III, 65 IND. L. J. 233, 242 (1990); see also Henry P. Monaghan, Article III and Supranational Judicial Review, 107 COLUM. L. REV.833, 868 (2007) (noting that “significant federal adjudication [can] occur in non-Article III tribunals.”). [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 35 decision in United States v. More – nicely illustrates the exclusivist approach first taken by American courts. An 1801 federal statute allowed justices of the peace for the District of Columbia to collect fees from litigants for the judicial services they performed. Though this provision was repealed a year later, justice of the peace Benjamin More continued to collect fees. When More was indicted, he contended that the 1802 repeal was unconstitutional because it sought to diminish the compensation of a federal judge. The Circuit Court of the District of Columbia agreed. Dismissing the indictment, the court said as follows: 168 169 [i]t is difficult to conceive how a magistrate can lawfully sit in judgment, exercising judicial powers, and enforcing his judgments by process of law, without holding a court. I consider such a court, thus exercising a part of the judicial power of the United States, as an inferior court, and the justice of the peace as the judge of that court.170 The circuit court’s holding was predicated on an unspoken assumption of exclusivity. Having decided that the justice of the peace served on a federally created court that acted judicially, the circuit court reflexively concluded that the court therefore was an Article III tribunal (that accordingly enjoyed protection against diminishment of compensation, thereby rendering the 1802 repeal unconstitutional). Without the assumption of exclusivity, the fact that the justice of the peace served on a federal court exercising judicial power would not automatically have meant it was an Article III court. Exclusivist assumptions carried though to Supreme Court decisions until well into the twentieth century. One of the Court’s most influential discussions concerning non-Article III federal courts is found in the 1828 decision of American Insurance Co. v. Canter. The case concerned a ship carrying a large quantity of cotton that had been stranded and lost on the coast of the territory of Florida. A portion of the cotton had been saved by rescue ships, and the question considered in the decision was whether a federally 171 172 173 168 7 U.S. (3 Cranch) 159 (1805) (circuit court opinions, 1803). The More case was brought to my attention by an intriguing article by Professor Gary Lawson. See Lawson, supra note ?, at 879-86. 169 See U.S. CONST. ART. III, §1. 170 More, 7 U.S. at 161 n.*. 171 Id.; see also O’Donoghue v. United States, 289 U.S. 516 (1933) (holding that judges of the District of Columbia’s Supreme Court and Court of Appeals are constitutionally protected from having their compensation reduced). 172 Incontrovertible evidence of the proposition above in text is that the United States Supreme Court reasoned in just this fashion 170 years after More was decided, ruling that Congress had the power to create a non-article III court known as the Superior Court of the District of Columbia that could try criminal cases for violation of federal law but that the court’s judges enjoyed neither life tenure nor salary protection since they did not sit on an article III court. See Palmore v. United States, 411 U.S. 389 (1973), discussed infra. Gary Lawson also has pointed out this relationship between the More and Palmore decisions. See Lawson, supra note ?, at 893. 173 26 U.S. (1 Pet.) 511 (1828). [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 36 created territorial court was competent to adjudicate salvage cases. As Canter acknowledged, salvage falls within the admiralty jurisdiction that itself is part of what Article III calls the “judicial Power of the United States.” Yet the judges on the territorial courts held “their offices for four years,” not the life tenure guaranteed by Article III. Canter held that the territorial courts were “not constitutional courts” but that they nonetheless had jurisdiction to hear the claims. Is it fair to characterize Canter as an example of the Court’s resistance to concurrence? After all, Canter could be said to be an instance of sameeffect concurrence insofar as it concurrent adjudicatory powers as between Article III courts and territorial courts. This is true, but it seems to me that Canter is most persuasively characterized as an instance where the Court signaled its preference for exclusivism but was simply unable to embrace the implications that all territorial courts be declared unconstitutional. In my view, Canter’s same-effect rationale reflects an effort to reclaim exclusivism rather than an embrace of concurrence. I come to this conclusion on the basis of the utterly unconvincing nature of its argument that the territorial courts were exercising something other than Article III judicial power. Chief Justice Marshall upheld the territorial courts in Canter on the rationale that they were 174 175 176 not constitutional Courts, in which the judicial power conferred by the Constitution on the general government can be deposited. They are incapable of receiving it . . . . The jurisdiction with which they are invested, is not a part of that judicial power which is defined in the Third Article of the Constitution, but is conferred by Congress, in the execution of those general powers which that body possesses over the territories of the United States.177 Exclusivism thus was the conceptual bedrock of the Canter decision: the Florida salvage courts could do what they did, despite their being manned by judges without life tenure, only because their judicial powers did not qualify as part of the “judicial Power of the United States.” Only Article III courts 174 The court that had heard the salvage claim had been created by the Florida territorial legislature pursuant to a federal statute that had empowered the legislature to do so. See Canter, 26 U.S. at 20-21. Though the petitioner argued that “Congress cannot vest admiralty jurisdiction in Courts crated by the territorial legislature,” id. at 25, the Court quite reasonably collapsed the distinction between delegator and delegee and instead analyzed as if Congress itself had directly created the salvage court in question. See id. at 24 and discussion above in text. Professor Lawson treats Canter’s discussion as mere dictum because the salvage court had been created by the territorial legislature rather than by Congress, see Lawson, supra note ?, at 888, 892, but he offers no reason for believing that the delegee (the territorial legislature) should have more power to create a non-article III court than the delegator (Congress). In any event, as Lawson himself notes, subsequent Supreme Court decisions treated Canter’s discussion as a holding, not dicta. See id. at 892. 175 Canter, 26 U.S. at 24(emphasis supplied). 176 See supra page 14. 177 Id. [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 37 could exercise that power. Though the conclusion that territorial courts were not Article III courts readily explained why territorial judges could have limited tenure, the Chief Justice’s major premise consists of little more than ipse dixit: unexplained was why and in what respect adjudications of controversies falling within the jurisdiction of Article III courts by federally created territorial courts were not part of the federal judicial power. An unstated assumption of exclusivity, of the sort that animated Marbury, quite clearly was doing the work. The other great opinions of the nineteenth century upholding nonArticle III federal tribunals similarly justified their holdings on grounds formally consistent with exclusivism, for they too premised their holdings on the proposition that the non-Article III tribunals were not exercising federal judicial power. Consider the important and influential decision of Murray’s Lessee v. Hoboken Land & Improvement Co. Samuel Swartwout was a federal collector of customs for the port of New York. Pursuant to an 1820 statute, the treasury department conducted an internal audit and determined that Swartwout had collected almost $1.4 million more than he had remitted to the government. Under authority of the statute, the solicitor of the treasury issued a “distress warrant” that directed a federal marshal to levy against and thereafter sell certain of Swartwout’s real property to satisfy his debt. It was argued in Murray’s Lessee that the marshal’s sale of Swartwout’s property was unconstitutional because the treasury officials’ acts (auditing of Swartwout’s account, ascertaining its balance, and issuing the distress warrant) constituted the exercise of United States “judicial power” that only could have been undertaken by an Article III court. In upholding the treasury official’s act, Murray’s Lessee famously announced what has become known as the public rights doctrine. At its core, the public rights doctrine is an example of concurrence. In the Court’s own words, 178 179 180 181 182 183 [t]here are matters, involving public rights, which may be presented in such form that the judicial power is capable of acting on them, 178 To be clear, I mean simply to characterize Canter’s reasoning from the internal perspective of its authors, not to praise it. For a particularly trenchant critique of this aspect of Canter’s reasoning, see Bator, supra note ?, at 241-42; see also Lawson, supra note ?, at 887-93; REDISH, supra note 20, at 36-9. Below I discuss Justice Harlan’s radical reinterpretation of this part of Carter’s rationale. See infra page 38. 179 Consider also the well-known case of Martin v. Hunter’s Lessee, where the Court observed that “Congress cannot vest any portion of the judicial power of the United States” in institutions aside from courts that it had “ordained and established” under article III. Similar reasoning is present in Ex parte Milligan, 71 U.S. (4 Wall.) 2, 121 (1866), where the Court concluded that “ no part of judicial power of the country was conferred on” military commissions “because the Constitution expressly vests it ‘in one supreme court and such inferior courts as the Congress may from time to time ordain and establish,’ and it is not pretended that the commission was a court ordained and established by Congress.” 180 59 U.S. (18 How.) 272 (1856). 181 Id. at 274-75. 182 Id. at 275. 183 See Monaghan, supra note 167, at 871 (noting that Murray’s Lessee “still remains the fountainhead for the modern public rights doctrine”); Nelson, supra note 164, at 586-90. [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 38 and which are susceptible of judicial determination, but which congress may or may not bring within the cognizance of the courts of the United States, as it may deem proper.184 The doctrine is an exemplar of concurrence because, under it, public rights may be adjudicated in Article III tribunals or Article I tribunals. Like the Canter decision, however, Murray’s Lessee upheld this concurrence while formally holding fast to exclusivist justifications. After all, Murray’s Lessee “admitted” that “if the auditing of [Swartout’s] account, and the ascertainment of its balance, and the issuing of this process, was an exercise of the judicial power of the United States, the proceeding was void; for the officers who performed these acts could exercise no part of that judicial power.” The Court upheld de facto concurrence (finding that two different institutions could undertake the identical act) only by averring that the subject-matter was not “necessarily . . . a judicial controversy” though it was something over “which the judicial power c[ould] be exerted.” In short, an Article III court’s actions would have constituted the exercise of judicial power, but the treasury official’s identical actions did not. By thus squaring the circle, the Court aimed to make concurrent powers formally consistent with exclusivism. Exclusivist assumptions began to give way in the twentieth century. The most important initial move was Justice Harlan’s opinion for the Court in Glidden Co. v. Zdanok, in the course of which Harlan radically restated Chief Justice Marshall’s reasoning in the Canter decision. Glidden acknowledged Chief Justice Marshall’s averment that territorial courts were not courts “in which the judicial power conferred by the Constitution . . . can be deposited” and were “incapable of receiving” the judicial power of which the Constitution spoke, but Justice Harlan went on to state that 185 186 187 188 [f]ar from being ‘incapable of receiving’ federal-question jurisdiction, the territorial courts have long exercised a jurisdiction commensurate in this regard with that of the regular federal courts . . .189 Though surely sounding like a significant break with the past, Justice Harlan labored to show that his and Marshall’s words in Canter were wholly consistent: [a]ll the Chief Justice meant . . . is that in the territories[,] cases and controversies falling within the enumeration of Article III may be heard and decided in courts constituted without regard to the limitations of that article . . .190 But try as he may, Justice Harlan could not obscure the milestone his words 184 59 U.S. at 284. 185 Id. at 275. 186 Id. at 281. 187 Id. 188 370 U.S. 530, reh’g denied, 371 U.S. 854 (1962). 189 190 Id. at 545 & n. 13. Id. at 544-45. [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 39 constituted. For the first time, the Supreme Court had explicitly acknowledged that non-Article III courts could “hear” and “decide” the same sort of “cases and controversies” that fall under the federal judicial power and that accordingly could be heard in Article III courts. The jurisdiction of nonArticle III courts could be “commensurate . . . with that of the regular federal court,” wrote Justice Harlan. Perhaps the use of “commensurate” was intended to leave room for concluding that the non-Article court’s jurisdiction was not precisely identical to an Article III court’s powers, but Harlan did not even try to explain in what respects the two institutions’ adjudicatory powers differed. For all practical intents and purposes, Justice Harlan had formally embraced concurrence. By the end of the twentieth century, the Supreme Court had come to fully accept non-exclusivity in relation to the federal judicial power. This is most clearly seen in the decision of CFTC v. Schor. Going the final step beyond Glidden’s acknowledgment that non-Article III courts may have jurisdiction “commensurate” with the jurisdiction of Article III courts, Schor observed that Congress could “authorize the adjudication of Article III business in a non-Article III tribunal.” Its holding was consistent with this observation: though the counterclaim at issue in the case was a “‘private’ right for which state law provide[d] the rule of decision,” and which accordingly was “a claim of the kind assumed to be at the ‘core’ of matters normally reserved to Article III courts,” Schor rejected the view that a “bright line rule” confined such claims to Article III courts and upheld the non-Article III court’s exercise of jurisdiction. Surely Professor Monaghan is correct when he speaks of today’s “system of shared adjudication between agencies and Article III courts.” D. Legislative Power: Congress and Agencies. Early Supreme Court decisions and early treatises understood Article I, Section I’s declaration that “[a]ll legislative Powers herein granted shall be vested in a Congress” in exclusivist terms: that only Congress may legislate. The threat to congressional exclusivity in the early days came in the form of apparent congressional 191 192 193 194 195 196 197 198 191 Id. at 545. 192 Id. (emphasis supplied). 193 478 U.S. 833 (1986). The very different approach to understanding non-Article III courts that was advanced by Justice Brennan in Northern Pipeline Construction Co. v. Marathon Pipe Line Co.,, 458 U.S. 50 (1982), also acknowledged non-exclusivity. As Justice Brennan later described his approach in the Marathon case, although “Article III, §1, seems to prohibit the vesting of any judicial functions in either the Legislative or the Executive Branch . . .[t]he Court has, however, recognized three narrow exceptions to the otherwise absolute mandate of Article III . . .” Schor, 478 U.S. at 859 (Brennan, J., dissenting) (emphasis in original). 194 Id. at 851. 195 Id.at 853. 196 Id. at 857. 197 Monaghan, supra note 167, at 873 (emphasis supplied). 198 Merrill, Rethinking, supra note 54, 198, at 2098 (quoting U.S. Const. Art. I, § 1) (emphasis supplied). [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 40 delegations of legislative power to other governmental institutions. The response to such actions (rhetorically, at least ) – which, if allowed, would have created a concurrent system in which institutions apart from Congress also would have had legislative power – was unequivocal. Speaking of delegations to the executive branch, the 1892 decision of Marshall Field & Co. v. Clark asserted as follows: “[t]hat congress cannot delegate legislative power to the president is a principle universally recognized as vital to the integrity and maintenance of the system of government ordained by the constitution.” Addressing legislative delegations to courts, Chief Justice Marshall stated in the 1825 decision of Wayman v. Southard that “[i]t will not be contended that Congress can delegate to the Courts, or to any other tribunals, powers which are strictly and exclusively legislative.” Speaking more generally, Thomas Cooley’s nineteenth century treatise declares that “[o]ne of the settled maxims in constitutional law is, that the power conferred upon the legislature to make laws cannot be delegated by that department to any other body or authority.” Virtually everyone today acknowledges, however, that, as a practical matter, these nineteenth century statements of congressional exclusivism do not describe contemporary American government. An extraordinary proportion of contemporary lawmaking occurs in the extra-congressional governmental entities known as administrative agencies. As a formal doctrinal matter, though, contemporary constitutional doctrine has not been willing to part with the myth of exclusivity. The nondelegation doctrine still purports to absolutely prohibit the delegation of legislative power. The Court’s most recent non-delegation decision, Whitman v. American Trucking Associations, Inc., is representative of contemporary 199 200 201 202 203 204 205 206 207 199 In none of the early cases did the Court strike down a federal statute on non-delegation grounds. For a detailed discussion of the early cases, see Gary Lawson, Delegation and Original Meaning, 88 VA. L. REV. 327, 353-72 (2002). 200 143 U.S. 649 (1892). 201 Id. at 692. 202 23 U.S. (10 Wheat) 1, 46 (1825). 203 Id. at 42. Chief Justice Marshall’s formulation here concededly is ambiguous as regards the question of whether legislative power can be delegated: it might be thought that he means to say that powers that are “strictly and exclusively legislative” cannot be delegated, but that matters that are legislative in character that are but not “exclusively legislative” may be delegated. When read context, however, it is clear that the Chief Justice meant to contrast “strictly and exclusively legislative” with matters that are nonlegislative yet still may be undertaken by the Congress, not with matters that are legislative and yet delegatable. See id. at 43 (immediate sentence after sentence quoted above in text reads as follows: “But Congress may certainly delegate to others, powers which the legislature may rightfully exercise itself.”); see Lawson, supra note 199, at 358-59 (similarly concluding). 204 Thomas Cooley, Constitutional Limitations 224 (8th ed. 1927), quoted in Merrill, supra note 54, 198, at 2112 & n. 60. 205 See Thomas W. Merrill, The Common Law Powers of Federal Courts, 52 U. CHI. L. REV. 1, 45-7 (1985). 206 See Merrill, supra note 54, 198, at 2119. 207 531 U.S. 457 (2001). [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 41 doctrine when it asserts that 208 [i]n a delegation challenge, the constitutional question is whether the statute has delegated legislative power to the agency. Article I, §1, of the Constitution vests ‘[a]ll legislative Powers herein granted . . . in a Congress of the United States.’ This text permits no delegation of those powers.209 How can this exclusivist rationale be harmonized with the contemporary reality of widespread rule-making by agencies? The Court has equated legislative power with discretion and has concluded that no legislative power is delegated so long as Congress provides an “intelligible principle” that cabins the administrative agency’s decisionmaking. But, as all legal scholars agree, the Court has applied this standard in an extraordinarily loose fashion that in fact has allowed administrative agencies to act with virtually unfettered discretion. As explained above in Part One, statutes that instruct agencies to regulate on the basis of “public interest, convenience, or necessity,” to set “fair and equitable prices,” or to set ambient air quality standards that are “requisite to protect the public health” all have passed muster. Indeed, only two times in our nation’s history has the Court struck down statutes on non-delegation grounds – and both occurred in 1935 before 210 211 212 213 214 208 Earlier caselaw formulated the constraint on Congress’ ability to delegate differently. Chief Justice Marshall stated that “[t]he line has not been exactly drawn which separates those important subject, which must be etnirely regulated by the legislature itself, from those of less interest, in which a general provision may be made, and power given to those who are to act under such general provisions to fill up the details.” Wayman, 23 U.S. (10 Wheat.) at 43. Today’s “intelligible principle” formulation originated in the 1935 decision of J.W. Hampton, Jr. & Co. V. United States, 276 U.S. 394, 409 (1935). Scholars debate to what degree Hampton’s formulation represented a change in the doctrine. Compare Lawson, supra note 199, at 368-72 (arguing against the view that Hampton altered the doctrine announced by Chief Justice Marshall) with Posner & Vermeule, supra note 227, at 1738-40 (concluding that “[t]he critical passage from Wayman v. Southard, then, adopts a different theory than the one modern nondelegation proponents have read into it”). 209 Id. at 472 (emphasis supplied). For other cases to similar effect, see, e.g., Touby v. United States, 500 U.S. 160, 165 (1991); United States v. Shreveport Grain & Elevator Co., 287 U.S. 77, 85 (1932); J.W. Hampton, Jr., & Co. v. United States, 276 U.S. 394, 407 (1928). 210 See, e.g., id. at 472; Merrill, supra note 54, 198, at 2119. 211 The Court has invalidated only two statutes on nondelegation grounds, both in the same year. So, in Cass Sunstein’s words, the doctrine has “had one good year, and 211 bad ones (and counting).” Cass R. Sunstein, Nondelegation Canons, 67 U. CHI. L. REV. 315, 322 (2000). Thomas Merrill recently has argued that “legislative power” entails “the power to make rules for the governance of society,” that administrative agencies exercise precisely this power today, and that they properly do so as long as Congress explicitly delegates them this power. Merrill, supra note 54, 198, at 2120. Gary Lawson describes the status quo as one where the Court has found the intelligible principle standard to be satisfied by“any collection of words that Congress chose to string together.” Lawson, supra note 199, at 371. Other scholars who have noted that the non-delegation doctrine fails to curb delegations of de facto lawmaking authority to agencies include David Schoenbrod and Marty Redish. See DAVID SCHOENBROD, POWER WITHOUT RESPONSIBILITY: HOW CONGRESS ABUSES THE PEOPLE THROUGH DELEGATION; REDISH, supra note 20, at 135-61. 212 See NBC v. United States, 319 U.S. 190, 225-26 (1943). 213 Yakus v. United States, 321 U.S. 414, 427 (1944). 214 Whitman, 531 U.S. at 473. [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 42 the Justices’ famous “switch in time.” Cass Sunstein puts it nicely when he says that “it is more accurate, speaking purely descriptively, to see 1935 as the real anomaly. We might say that the conventional [non-delegation] doctrine has had one good year, and 211 bad ones (and counting).” As a formal matter, defining legislative power as it has permits the Court to continue to assert that no legislative power has been delegated. As a pragmatic matter, however, by construing the non-delegation doctrine’s “intelligible principle” so broadly, the Court has sanctioned a regime of concurrence under which more than one governmental entity – Congress and agencies – exercise de facto legislative power. This is what has led Justices Stevens and Souter to criticize the Court for “pretend[ing] . . . that the authority delegated” to administrative agencies “is somehow not ‘legislative power’,” advocating instead that “it would be both wiser and more faithful to what we have actually done in delegation cases to admit that agency rulemaking authority is ‘legislative power.’” To use this Article’s terminology, Justices Stevens and Souter argue that the federal legislative power today is concurrently exercised by Congress and administrative agencies. It is fair to say that virtually the entire scholarly community is of the view that, as a purely descriptive matter, Justices Stevens and Souter have the better of the argument: it is widely agreed that the Court’s expansive interpretation of “intelligible principle” means that agencies exercise de facto legislative power. This raises an interesting question: why does the current majority continue to cling to the exclusivist rationale that no legislative power has been, nor can be, delegated? Precedent provides a large part of the answer: as Justices Stevens and Souter acknowledge, the Court’s past opinions have uniformly relied on exclusivism. But that only pushes back the question, for then it must be asked why earlier Courts adopted the exclusivist assumption that only Congress could exercise legislative power. Answering this question is complicated by the fact that, as others have pointed out, early Congresses enacted statutes that appear to have delegated lawmaking power to the executive and judicial branches: one statute provided for military pensions “under such regulations as the President of the United States may direct,” another authorized members of the executive branch to license “any proper persons” to trade with Indian 215 216 217 218 219 220 221 215 Cass Sunstein, Nondelegation Canons, 67 U. CHI. L. REV. 315, 322 (2000). 216 Id. 217 Whitman, 531 U.S. at 488 (Stevens, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part, joined by J. Souter). 218 Consensus breaks down as regards what if anything should be done about this: more on this soon. True even of Posner/Vermeule? 219 See id. (acknowledging that “there is language in our opinions that supports the Court’s articulation of our holding . . .” and citing to a raft of such cases). 220 See Posner & Vermeule, supra note 227, at 1735-36. 221 Act of September 29, 1789, 1 Stat. 95, cited in Posner & Vermeule, supra note 227, at 1735. [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 43 tribes “under such rules and regulations as the President may prescribe,” and yet another authorized courts to “make and establish all necessary rules for the orderly conducting of business in the said courts . . .” In other words, the early Supreme Court cases quoted above that flatly asserted that Congress’ legislative power could not be delegated did so in the face of contrary practice. This means that the “story” regarding the movement from exclusivity to concurrence is a bit different here than elsewhere: the Supreme Court’s insistence on exclusivity was not a description of what existed at the time, but instead reflected the Court’s aspiration. And indeed, to this day, doctrine formally denies that legislative power can be delegated, asserting that only Congress can legislate. This is powerful evidence of the ongoing power of exclusivist assumptions. Finally, fully understanding the degree to which institutions apart from Congress exercise de facto if not actual legislative power requires that we not confine our inquiry to administrative agencies. Although frequently overlooked, there is yet another governmental institution outside of Congress where significant law-making occurs: courts, particularly when they interpret vague statutes that do not fall under the rule-making aegis of an administrative agency. Our corpus of federal antitrust law is an excellent example, for almost the entirety of antitrust law is the creation of courts. The non-delegation doctrine does not apply at all to the de facto delegations to courts that occur when Congress enacts vague statutory language without delegating rule-making authority to an executive agency. In such circumstances, courts in effect generate the law when they decide questions on a case-by-case basis – what is variously called statutory interpretation or federal common law. Constitutional doctrine imposes virtually no limits on this sort of congressional delegation. Though the voidfor-vagueness doctrine at one point was conceptualized inter alia as an antidelegation separation of powers principle, today it almost exclusively is treated 222 223 224 225 226 227 228 222 Act of July 22, 1790, 1 Stat. 137, 137, cited in Posner & Vermeule, supra note 227, at 1735. 223 Act of September 24, 1789, 1 Stat. 73, 83, cited in Posner & Vermeule, supra note 227, at 1735. 224 not unique: similar wrt Story and jury’s role vis-a-vis the law. 225 This is frequently, but not wholly, overlooked. Professor Marty Redish and Gary Lawson, for example, both have discussed these sorts of delegations. See Redish, supra note 227, at 140-41; Lawson, supra note 199, at 375-78. 226 See, e.g., National Society of Professional Engineers v. United States, 435 U.S. 679, 688 (1978) . 227 See Eric A. Posner & Adrian Vermeule, Interring the Non-Delegation Doctrine, 69 U. CHI. L. REV. 1721, 1731 (2002) (noting this); see also Margaret H. Lemos, The Other Delegate, 81 S. Cal. L. Rev. Xx (forthcoming 2008). It should not noted, though, that the Court has applied the non-delegation doctrine in the rare instances where Congress has delegated rule-making authority to courts, as with the Rules Enabling Act and the Sentencing Reform Act, which created the United States Sentencing Commission as an independent body within the Judicial Branch. See Mistretta v. United States, 488 U.S. 361, 386-90 (1989) (analyzing Sentencing Commission); Sibbach v. Wilson & Co., 312 U.S. 1, 9-10 (1941) (upholding Rules Enabling Act). For a defense of the position that there should be constraints on legislative delegations to the executive branch but not to the judiciary that would keep Congress from enacting vague statutes, see MARTIN H. REDISH, THE CONSTITUTION AS POLITICAL STRUCTURE 140-41 (1995). 228 Rosen, NW U L. REv. [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 44 as a due process principle designed to provide notice and to ensure nonarbitrary enforcement. Further, as a practical matter, the void-for-vagueness doctrine primarily has been applied to state laws, and is limited almost exclusively to the criminal and first amendment contexts. E. Some other Contexts. The trajectory of exclusivity to concurrence appears in other doctrinal contexts. Professors Ackerman and Golove have shown that Congress and the President understood originally believed that a certain class of international agreements only could be created by the treaty, and that it was only in the mid-twentieth century that Congress and the President came to believe that treaties and Congressional-Executive Agreements were wholly “interchangeable,” i.e., that they were wholly (or virtually wholly) concurrent. [To complete: Gibbons v. Ogden to Cooley; horizontal federalism/Story’s exclusivism to Hague overlap] 229 230 231 232 III. HOW AND WHY CONCURRENCE IS CREATED Part II explained that exclusivism typically is the starting assumption. This Part III examines the mechanisms by which concurrence has been created as well as the reasons for the shift from exclusivity to concurrence. A. Mechanisms for Creating Concurrence. As shown in Part II, the judiciary tends to start with exclusivist assumptions. Consequently, the move toward concurrence typically has been initiated by non-judicial institutions. Analysis of the contexts in which concurrence is found reveals three mechanisms by which concurrence has been created. 1. Delegation. The first, and probably most important, mechanism for creating concurrence is delegation. Congress explicitly 229 See Colorado v. Hill, 530 U.S. 703, 732 (2000) (“A statute can be impermissibly vague for either of two independent reasons. First, if it fails to provide people of ordinary intelligence a reasonable opportunity to understand what conduct it prohibits. Second, if it authorizes or even encourages arbitrary and discriminatory enforcement.”). While some earlier void-for-vagueness cases conceptualized the doctrine as ameliorating legislative delegations of authority to courts and juries, see, e.g., United States v. Ragen, 314 U.S. 513, 523-24 (1942) (holding that the statute was “not vague nor does it delegate policy making power to either court or jury”); Cline v. Frink Dairy, Co., 274 U.S. 445, 457 (1927), this anti-delegation rationale has “largely been abandoned in favor of . . . preventing arbitrary and discriminatory law enforcement.” Andrew E. Goldsmith, The Void-for-Vagueness Doctrine in the Supreme Court, Revisited, 30 AM. J. CRIM. L. 279, 282 (2003). One modern Supreme Court decision has revived the non-delegation concept, but assimilated it under the concern of arbitrary enforcement. See Grayned v. City of Rockford, 408 U.S. 104, 108-9 (1972) (noting that a “vague law impermissibly delegates basic policy matters to policemen, judges, and juries for resolution on an ad hoc and subjective basis, with the attendant dangers of arbitrary and discriminatory application”). No recent case has relied on the delegation concept as a basis for finding a law to be void for vagueness. 230 An influential and excellent student note written by Professor Amsterdam both noted this and proffered an explanation as to why the void-for-vagueness doctrine primarily limited states rather than the federal government. See Note, The Void-for-Vagueness Doctrine in the Supreme Court, 109 U. PA. L. REV. 67, 82-86 (1960). A recent article confirms that this trend has continued. See Goldsmith, Revisited, supra note 229, at 290. 231 See Village of Hoffman Estates v. Flipside, Hoffman Estates, Inc., 455 U.S. 489, 499 (1982)(“perhaps the most important factor affecting the clarity that the Constitution demands of a law is whether it threatens to inhibit the exercise of constitutionally protected rights”). 232 See Ackerman & Golove, supra note 29, at xx. [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 45 delegates rule-making authority to agencies and implicitly delegates similar authority to courts when it enacts open-ended statutory language and decides against tasking agencies with rule-making authority to flesh out the statutory language. Call this “Type 1 delegations.” Type 2 delegations are exemplified by congressional delegations of adjudicatory authority to article I courts when it creates them and vests them with adjudicatory jurisdiction that mirrors the powers enjoyed by Article III courts. The difference between Type 1 and Type 2 delegations is as follows: in the former, the delegator delegates its own authority, whereas in Type 2 delegations the delegator delegates another institution’s authority (e.g., a congressional delegation of Article III “judicial Power” to an article I tribunal). The reason for distinguishing between these two types of delegations should be obvious: institutional self-interest operates as a check against overly extensive Type 1 delegations, but not for Type 2 delegations. A few more observations regarding delegation are in order. First, Type 1 delegations typically create concurrence insofar as the delegator retains power of the sort that it has delegated. Delegation accordingly results in a situation where the delegator and delegatee both have power. The same is true, mutatis mutandi, for Type 2 delegations. Second, institutions apart from Congress can delegate. For instance, it is conceivable that the President could delegate some of his powers. Third, delegation is a mechanism that readily gives rise to (though need not necessarily give rise to) same-source concurrence. Fourth, and finally, analyzing the propriety of delegations demands consideration not only of the nature of the powers delegated but the identity of the delegatee. In this regard, it may matter whether the delegatee is a preexisting institution or a newly created institution. It is likely that a pre-existing institution may be unable to receive certain powers that a new institution could, if, for example, the delegated powers would be incompatible with the pre-existing institution. 2. Inherency. The second mechanism for creating concurrence is what might be called “inherency..” Under inherency, a second institution claims that its constitutionally-granted powers extend to authorizing it to undertake the identical act “x” that another institution can undertake. For instance, the Court has held that Congress’ powers to “constitute Tribunals inferior to the supreme Court” subsumes the power to enact immunity statutes that are functionally equivalent to the President’s pardon power. Accordingly, inherency is the mechanism most closely associated with same-effect concurrence. 3. Inactivity and Initiative-Taking. A third mechanism for 233 234 235 233 See, e.g., 48 U.S.C. §1424b(b) (1988) (vesting the District Court of Guam with “the jurisdiction of a district court of the United States . . . and that of a bankruptcy court of the United States”). 234 U.S. CONST. ART. I, §8, CL. 9. 235 See Brown v. Walker, 161 U.S. 591, 601 (1896). [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 46 creating concurrence is what I call “inactivity and initiative-taking.” This occurs when the one institution with clear authority to undertake act “x” does not, and another institution steps in to do so. A good illustration is provided by the facts in United States v. Midwest Oil Company. An act of Congress provided that public lands containing petroleum or other mineral oils were to be “free and open to occupation, exploration, and purchase by citizens of the United States . . .” After deciding that oil was being extracted too rapidly, with the result that the government soon would be “obliged to repurchase the very oil that it has practically given away” on account of the American Navy’s increasing use of fuel, the President issued a proclamation withdrawing the rights to extract petroleum from select locations on U.S. public lands. Midwest Oil Company continued to extract oil following the President’s decree, and was sued for doing so. Midwest argued in court that the executive order was null insofar as it was not authorized by statute but, to the contrary, contradicted an act of Congress that permitted petroleum extraction. The Supreme Court upheld the President’s proclamation. The Court provided two primary justifications. One was that although “no [] express authority has been granted” to the President to withdraw rights to drill for oil, “there is nothing in the nature of the power exercised which prevents Congress from granting it by implication . . .” This rationale reduces to an (implied) delegation justification for the President’s exercise of essentially legislative powers, but it is unpersuasive: why should the statute opening public lands be understood as impliedly authorizing the President to withdraw those lands? Far more persuasive is the Court’s second justification. “[G]overnment is a practical affair, intended for practical men,” said the Court, and Congress’s “rules or laws for the disposal of public land are necessarily general in their nature” such that “[e]mergencies may occur, or conditions may so change as to require that the agent in charge should, in the public interest, withhold the land from sale . . .” In other words, (perhaps understandable) congressional inaction provided the justification for presidential initiative. 236 237 238 239 240 241 242 243 236 Justice Jackson alluded to this sort of mechanism in his Steel Seizure concurrence when he observed that “[w]e may say that power to legislate for emergencies belongs in the hands of Congress, but only Congress itself can prevent power from slipping through its fingers.” Youngstown Sheet & Tube Co. v. Sawyer, 343 U.S. 579, 654 (1952)(Jackson, J., concurring). 237 236 U.S. 459 (1915). 238 Id. at 465 (quoting the statute). 239 Id. at 466-67. 240 Id. at 468. 241 Id. at 474. 242 The Court also pointed to a past practice of executive withdrawal of public lands. See id. at 469-72. 243 Id. at 474. It is worth adding that the Court refused to endorse the President’s effort to ground his powers to issue the proclamation on his Commander-in-Chief powers, id. at 468, and that much of the Court’s reasoning arguably turned on the fact that the case concerned public lands, id. at 474-75. For an illuminating analysis of the case, see Henry P. Monaghan, The Protective Power of the Presidency, 93 COLUM. L. REV. 1, 44-45 (1993). [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 47 The mechanism of “inactivity and initiative-taking” has given rise to the concurrent rule-making authority as between Congress and federal courts that characterizes the dormant commerce clause and most areas of federal common law. Congress has unquestioned authority to disallow (or approve) all the state regulations that federal courts have deemed presumptively unlawful under the dormant commerce clause. The Supreme Court has not yet pointed to a persuasive doctrinal basis to ground its dormant commerce clause doctrine, so, given the fact that Congress clearly has the power to regulate everything that the Court is addressing, why has the Court proceeded? The answer quite clearly is that the Court deems federal inaction in the face of discriminatory state laws to be unacceptable, and so it has stepped into the breach of congressional inaction and taken the initiative. Although most instances of federal common law-making plausibly can be justified on the basis of inherency basis – on the ground that Article III’s “judicial Power” encompasses common lawmaking powers – what actually has driven the Court to act and create federal common law is better described by the “inactivity and initiative-taking” paradigm than judicial belief in its inherent powers to do so. After all, even after Erie’s embrace of legal positivism, which made it important to identify the source of judge’s power to generate common law, the Supreme Court failed to specify the source of the federal common law rules it announced, appearing to instead justify its actions on the grounds of necessity. Consider in this regard the Court’s decision in Clearfield Trust Co. v. United States, which was among the first post-Erie federal common law cases. The Court explained that “[t]he rights and duties of the United States on commercial paper which it issues are governed by federal rather than local law” and then asserted that “[i]n the absence of an applicable Act of Congress it is for the federal courts to fashion the governing rule of law according to their own standards.” The Court wholly neglected, however, to explain the source of federal courts’ powers to fashion law absent congressional action. Consider as well a decision handed down the same day as Erie, Justice 244 245 246 247 244 I would add the caveat that federal courts’ common-lawmaking powers exist only to the extent that they were not statutorily preempted, as it were, by the Rules of Decision Act. See Martin H. Redish, Federal Common Law, Political Legitimacy, and the Interpretive Process: An “Institutionalism” Perspective, 83 NW. U. L. REV. 761, 795 (1989). This suggests that the Court’s dormant commerce clause may be particularly problematic insofar as it applies federal law where state law is applicable and hence ought to be applied under the terms of the Rules of Decision Act. 245 Prior to Erie, common law was widely understood as being judicial articulation of pre-existing natural law rather than create judicial law-making. See Erie R.R. Co. v. Tompkins, 304 U.S. 64, 79 (1938) (asserting that Swift v. Tyson’s sanctioning of federal courts’ common law powers rested on the “fallac[ious]” natural law belief that there is a “transcendental body of law outside of any particular State but obligatory within it unless and until changed by statute”); but see Jack Goldsmith & Steven Walt, Erie and the Irrelevance of Legal Positivism, 84 VA. L. REV. 673, 683 (1998)(challenging this account). If, following Erie, there was no “transcendental body” of law that courts merely declared when they announced common law, the following question naturally arose: what then was the source of the common law rule that a court declared? 246 318 U.S. 363 (1943). 247 Clearfield Trust, 318 U.S. at 366-67. [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 48 Brandeis (Erie’s author) wrote that the apportionment of an interstate stream’s water presents a “question of ‘federal common law.’” Brandeis cited to earlier cases for the principle, but neither he nor the cited cases explained the source of federal courts’ powers to create such federal common law – a question that, it is worth repeating, becomes essential in the wake of Erie’s embrace of positivism. To be sure, in some contexts the Court has attempted to explain the source of its powers to generate federal common law. Yet even here it is hard to escape the conclusion that a perceived need to act, rather than firm belief in its inherent powers, drove the Court’s decision to articulate federal common law, for the inherency justifications the Court has offered are extraordinarily weak. First consider the federal common law of admiralty and interstate conflicts. The Court has said that the source of federal courts’ authority to generate admiralty law is the Constitution’s “grant of general admiralty jurisdiction to the federal courts.” As many have argued, however, this justification seems inconsistent with Erie’s holding that the Constitution’s grant of diversity jurisdiction does not empower federal courts to create general common law in diversity cases. After all, “there is no obviously relevant difference in the texts of the diversity and admiralty jurisdictional grants.” If the diversity grant gives courts adjudicatory jurisdiction but not the power to fashion substantive common law rules, why should the admiralty grant operate differently? Consider, as well, the Court’s holding in Textile Workers Union v. Lincoln Mills that federal courts’ powers to create a body of federal law to enforce collective bargaining agreements came from the Labor Management Relations Act’s provision that federal courts have jurisdiction over “[s]uits for violation of contracts between an employer and a labor organization . . . in an industry affecting commerce.” Fairly read, this statutory provision is a jurisdictional grant – which the Court in fact acknowledged. Reliance on a jurisdictional grant as the source of a court’s power to generate federal common law thus is subject to the same sort of post-Erie critique leveled above in respect of the Court’s admiralty jurisprudence: Erie made clear the distinction between 248 249 250 251 252 253 254 248 Hinderlider v. La Plata River & Cherry Creek Ditch Co., 304 U.S. 92, 110 (1938). 249 Though some lower courts and modern commentators similarly have sought to ground federal common lawmaking power to the Constitution’s jurisdictional grant over interstate controversies, see PAUL BATOR ET AL, HART & WECHSLER’S THE FEDERAL COURTS AND THE FEDERAL SYSTEM 884 (3rd ed. 1988) (gathering sources), the same Erie-based critique leveled at the Court’s reliance on the admiralty jurisdiction clause applies here: if the diversity grant gives courts adjudicatory jurisdiction but not the power to fashion substantive common law rules, why should the interstate controversy grant operate differently? 250 Northwest Airlines v. Transport Workers Union, 451 U.S. 77, 95-96 (1981). 251 See, e.g., Ernest A. Young, Preemption at Sea, 67 GEO. WASH. L. REV. 273, 312 (1999). 252 353 U.S. 448, 451 (1957). 253 Lincoln Mills, 353 U.S. at 451-52 (relying on 29 U.S.C. §185(a)). 254 Id. at 452 (stating the question before the Court as being whether the statutory provision at issue is “more than jurisdictional”). [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 49 jurisdictional and substantive law-making grants, and why should the LMRA’s jurisdictional grant be the source of common law powers if the diversity grant is not? Lincoln Mills also relied on what Justice Douglas’ opinion for the Court termed “a few shafts of light” in the legislative history to buttress its conclusion, but “[t]he Court’s handling of the legislative history was severely criticized by the dissent and, subsequently, by commentators.” B. Reasons for Concurrence. The analysis of the case law provided above in subsection one demonstrates that the judicial decisions upholding concurrence all have stressed, and likely have been primarily driven by, situation-specific pragmatic considerations. Frequently, though not always, the Court also was able to point either to historical precedents or to the fact that the practice of concurrence had become widely accepted or wellentrenched. The courts’ explanations, however, typically do not venture beyond relatively undeveloped assertions that concurrence is practical or efficient. In response to this, this subsection cashes out the types of benefits that concurrence brings. Consulting the case law’s explanations, but not confining analysis to the justifications provided in the case law, seems particularly appropriate to the task of ascertaining what drives concurrence insofar as concurrence typically originates extra-judicially. 1. What The Courts Have Said a. Pragmatics and Past Practice. The Ames Court – which, it should be recalled, reversed course from Marbury and upheld Congress’ allocation of original jurisdiction of cases involving States and ambassadors to inferior federal courts – premised its holding on two bases: longstanding practice and considerations of practicality. Ames reasoned on the basis of an analogous practice that had arisen in relation to federal courts’ adjudicatory jurisdiction in respect of ambassadors. The same section of the Constitution that specified that the Supreme Court shall have original jurisdiction over suits involving States provides that “the supreme Court shall have original Jurisdiction . . . [i]n all Cases affecting Ambassadors . . .” Since the early days of our Republic, however, this language had not been understood to mean that only the Supreme Court could have original jurisdiction in cases affecting Ambassadors. The 1789 Judiciary Act provided that the Supreme Court “shall have exclusively all such jurisdiction of suits or 255 256 257 258 259 255 See also supra note 249 (noting similar critique that can be leveled at various efforts that have been made to explain federal courts’ powers to create federal common law to resolve interstate controversies). 256 Id. 257 Merrill, supra note 205, at 40 & nn. 180-81. 258 Tellingly, the Ames Court did not distinguish Marbury on the basis of the Constitution’s specification that “[i]n all other cases, the supreme court shall have appellate jurisdiction.” It quite plausibly could have been argued on the basis of this language that the Supreme Court could not have original jurisdiction over matters that the Constitution granted it appellate jurisdiction. Rather, the Ames Court distinguished Marbury on the basis of longstanding practice and practical considerations, as discussed above. 259 U.S. CONST. ART. III, §2, CL. 2 (emphasis provided). [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 50 proceedings against ambassadors” but “original, but not exclusive, jurisdiction of all suits brought by ambassadors . . .” The Court specifically noted that this legislation reflected a “construction” of the Constitution by Congress, and provided a highly practical (though hypothesized) rationale for Congress’ “understand[ing] that the original jurisdiction vested in the supreme court was [not] necessarily exclusive” : 260 261 262 keep[ing] open the highest court of the nation for the determination, in the first instance, of suits involving . . . a diplomat or commercial representative of a foreign government . . . was due to the rank and dignity of those for whom the [constitutional] provision was made; but to . . . deprive an ambassador, public minister of consul of the privilege of suing in any court he chose having jurisdiction of the parties and the subject matter of his action, would be, in many cases, to convert what was intended as a favor into a burden.263 The Ames Court also was impressed by the fact that this longstanding practice was popularly accepted. The Supreme Court itself, and commentators as well, likewise have acknowledged that considerations of practicality drove the Supreme Court’s jurisprudence upholding concurrent power as between Article I tribunals and Article III courts. Justice Harlan’s decision for the Court in the Glidden Co. v. Zdanok decision is exemplary. Justice Harlan traced non-Article III federal courts back to Chief Justice Marshall’s opinion in the above-discussed Canter case, which upheld a territorial court’s power to hear a case that would have been justiciable under a federal district court admiralty jurisdiction. I explained above how Justice Harlan’s opinion transformed the Chief Justice’s 264 265 266 267 260 Ames, 111 U.S. at 463-64 (quoting the 1789 Judiciary Act, with emphasis provided by the author). 261 Id. at 464. The Ames Court also observed that this construction was provided by “the first congress, in which were many who had been leading and influential members of the convention, and who were familiar with the discussions that preceded the adoption of the constitution by the states, and with the objections urged against it . . .” Id. at 464. This raises an obvious question: shouldn’t these same considerations have led the Court to decide Marbury differently? 262 Id. 263 Id. at 464. 264 The Ames Court also reviewed several circuit court opinions that upheld against constitutional challenges the exercise by inferior federal courts of original jurisdiction in lawsuits involving foreign consuls. Interestingly, the Ames Court also noted that one of the opinions was contemporaneous with the decision of Chisholm v. Georgia, which famously caused immediate controversy and led to the quick adoption of the Eleventh Amendment. The Ames Court said that “[i]t is a fact of some significance, in this connection, that although the decision in Chisholm’s Case attracted immediate attention, and caused great irritation in some of the states,” that the decision in the contemporaneous decision, “which in effect held that the original jurisdiction of the supreme court was not necessarily exclusive, seems to have provoked no special comment.” See id. at 465-69. 265 See Monaghan, supra note 167, at 868 (arguing that “[t]he expanding national government and the rapidly expanding national domain quickly rendered [exclusivity] untenable”); Bator, supra note ?, at 254 (“The justification for the existence of territorial courts has always been essentially pragmatic”). 266 370 U.S. 530, 547 (1962). 267 Id. at 544. [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 51 rationale. But why did Justice Harlan think that Canter’s holding was correct? Harlan tells us: “The reasons for [Canter’s holding] are not difficult to appreciate so long as the character of the early territories and some of the practical problems arising from their administration are kept in mind.” There was “no state government to assume the burden of local regulation,” with the result that “courts had to be established and staffed with sufficient judges to handle the general jurisdiction that elsewhere would have been exercised in large part by the courts of a State.” It was imperative that these territorial courts not be staffed by life-tenured Article III judges because there would have been no need for them when the territories entered statehood. This consideration, as well as other “problems not foreseen by the Framers of Article III,” Justice Harlan says, explained Canter: “Against this historical background, it is hardly surprising that Chief Justice Marshall decided as he did. It would have been doctrinaire in the extreme” to rule otherwise. Instead, continued Harlan, Chief Justice Marshall was “conscious as ever of his responsibility to see the Constitution work” and accordingly “recognized a greater flexibility in Congress to deal with problems arising outside the normal context of a federal system.” Harlan then generalized, explaining that “[t]he same confluence of practical considerations that dictated the result in Canter has governed the decision in later cases sanctioning the creation of other courts with judges of limited tenure” and that otherwise do not conform to the requirements of Article III. The Court relied on considerations of historical practice and practicality in its other decisions upholding non-Article III tribunals as well. In the landmark case of Murray’s Lessee v. Hoboken Land & Improvement Co., for instance, the Court upheld the non-Article III procedure for collecting federal taxes on the historical grounds that it did “not differ in principle from those employed in England from remote antiquity – and in many of the States, so far as we know without objection . . .” The Court then explained the pragmatic basis for this practice: 268 269 270 271 [P]robably there are few governments which do or can permit their claims for public taxes, either on the citizen or the officer employed for their collection or disbursement, to become subjects of judicial controversy, according to the course of the law of the land. Imperative necessity has forced a distinction between such claims and all others . . .272 The nation’s courts-martial similarly were justified on the basis of historical practice and practicality. Emphasizing the former, the early decision 268 See supra text and notes at note 188. 269 Glidden, 370 U.S. at 545 (emphasis supplied). 270 Id. at 546-47. 271 59 U.S. (18 How.) 272 (1856). The facts of this case are laid out in considerable detail supra at p. 37. 272 Murray’s Lessee, 59 U.S. at 282. [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 52 of Dynes v. Hoover concluded that “Congress has the power to provide for the trial and punishment of military and naval offences in the manner then and now practiced by civilized nations . . .” Emphasizing considerations of practicality, Ex Parte Quirin rejected the view that offenses against the laws of war are subject to the requirements of the Fifth and Sixth Amendments, holding instead that such offenses can be tried in military tribunals, “which are not courts in the sense of the Judiciary Article, and which in the natural course of events are usually called upon to function under conditions precluding resort to such procedures.” Consistent with Ex Parte Quirin, the recent landmark decision of Hamdan v. Rumsfeld candidly acknowledged that “[t]he military commission, a tribunal neither mentioned in the Constitution nor created by statute, was born of military necessity.” Sometimes pragmatic considerations alone, absent historical pedigree, have proven to be sufficient justification for the Court. Consider in this regard its forgiving non-delegation doctrine. As the Court has said in its more candid moments, “[o]ur jurisprudence has been driven by a practical understanding that in our increasingly complex society . . . Congress simply cannot do its job absent an ability to delegate power.” This justification has been elaborated and defended by multiple scholars. Pragmatics without pedigree also have sufficed in the Court’s Seventh Amendment jurisprudence, which is explored immediately below. b. Efficiency. The judicial decisions sanctioning concurrent judicial and jury fact-finding power were driven primarily by another pragmatic consideration: efficiency and resource-preservation. The Munson decision, which rejected the rule under which questions were submitted to the jury as long as there was “any evidence” rule, justified its new approach by citing to “recent decisions of high authority” that “have established a more reasonable rule . . .” The “high authority” that the Supreme Court cited all were English cases that post-dated 1791, the year that the Seventh Amendment was adopted, and hence were not legally binding authority. Moreover, a careful review of the cases suggests that none of them went so far as to support the Court’s rule that judges can “take cases away from the jury when there are disputes of pure questions of fact . . .” The conclusion is inescapable that what ultimately led the Supreme Court to 273 274 275 276 277 278 279 280 273 61 U.S. 65, 79 (1857). 274 317 U.S. 1 (1942). 275 126 S.Ct. 2749 (2006). 276 Mistretta, 488 U.S. at 372; see also American Power & Light Co. v. SEC, 329 U.S. 90, 105 (1946) (observing that “[t]he judicial approval accorded these ‘broad’ standards for administrative action is a reflection of the necessities of modern legislation dealing with complex economic and social problems.”). 277 Merrill, supra note 54, 198, at 2151-59, 2164-65; Posner & Vermeule, supra note 227, at 1743-45. 278 Munson, 81 U.S. at 448 (emphasis supplied). 279 See Sward, supra note 103, at 593. The earliest of these cases had been decided in 1853. See id. 280 Id. at 598. [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 53 adopt its new rule in Munson was its belief that the new rule was – as the Court itself said – “more reasonable” than the old one: Why let a case go to the jury, even if there were some evidence in support of the plaintiff’s position, if a jury could not “properly proceed to find a verdict” for the non-moving party? Doing so would only waste the valuable time of the court, jury, and parties. The Galloway decision, which determined that directed verdicts on grounds of insufficiency of evidence did not violate the Seventh Amendment, likewise grounded its holding on considerations of practice and practicality. The “short answer” as to why “the Amendment [does not] deprive[] the federal courts of power to direct a verdict for insufficiency of evidence,” explained the Court, is that any contention to the contrary “has been foreclosed by repeated decisions made here consistently for nearly a century” with the result that any “objection therefore comes too late.” But the Galloway Court did not end its analysis there, as it also aimed to establish that “the consequences flowing from” the proposition that a judge’s only response to insufficient evidence was to order a new trial “are sufficient to refute it.” The conclusion that the Seventh Amendment demanded a new trial after the plaintiff had failed to provide sufficient evidence in the first, said the Court, would lead to “endless repetition of litigation and unlimited chance, by education gained at the opposing party’s expense, for perfecting a case at other trials.” Unlike Monson and Galloway, the Redman Court was unable to justify its new rule on grounds of past practice. This is becauseonly twenty years before, in Slocum, the Court had rejected the proposition that a court could disregard a jury’s determination and instead pass on the facts and substitute its own judgment. Indeed, the Second Circuit decision that was appealed to the Supreme Court in Redman had relied on Slocum for the proposition that a new trial was the only remedy for a judge’s determination that a jury’s verdict had been based on insufficient evidence, and the Supreme Court in the Redman decision itself acknowledged that “some parts of the [Slocum] opinion give color to the interpretation put on it by the Court of Appeals.” This is an understatement: as reproduced above, Slocum had cited to many earlier decided Supreme Court cases that had flatly asserted that only juries could find facts. As a formal matter, Redman’s holding turned on a highly technical distinction. Unlike Slocum, the defendant in Redman had moved for a directed verdict on the grounds of insufficient evidence after evidence had been 281 282 283 284 285 286 287 288 281 Munson, 81 U.S. at 448 (emphasis supplied). 282 See also Chamberlain, 288 U.S. at 343. 283 Galloway, 319 U.S. at 389. 284 Id. at 392. 285 Id. at 393. 286 See supra note 129. 287 Redman, 295 U.S. at 656. 288 Id. at 661. [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 54 adduced at trial but before verdict, and the trial court had reserved its decision on the defendant’s motion. The Redman Court then pointed to the common law procedure known as the “special case,” under which courts could submit the case to the jury subject to reserved questions of law and, following verdict, award verdict to a different party than the jury depending upon how their resolved the reserved question of law. So far Redman had done nothing out of the ordinary. What made Redman revolutionary was its conclusion that sufficiency of the evidence was among the legal questions that could be reserved pending the jury verdict notwithstanding its acknowledgment that “issues of law are to be resolved by the court and issue of fact are to be determined by the jury . . .” As of 1791, the “special case” did not permit reservations concerning sufficiency of the evidence. The one British case Redman cited that did support the conclusion that reservations could be made as regards sufficiency of evidence was not decided until 1853 – i.e., until after 1791 – and hence was not formally relevant. Accordingly, the legal materials that were before the Redman Court alone cannot explain its decision. In light of this, the efficiency-minded practical reasons the Court adduced for its ruling most likely are what fueled its decision: reserving questions “gave better opportunity for considered rulings, made new trials less frequent, and commanded such general approval that parties assented to its application as a matter of course” and, the Redman Court suggested, these considerations carried over to questions as to whether the evidence was sufficient. 2. Systematizing Concurrence’s Benefits. As shown above, most of the Supreme Court’s justifications for concurrence amount to context-specific observations that concurrence carried pragmatic benefits. This section aims to formalize and systematize these benefits. In so doing it builds upon, but does not limit itself to, the justifications that the Court has 289 290 291 292 293 294 289 Id. at 659-60. 290 See id. at 659 (“Whether the evidence was sufficient or otherwise was a question of law to be resolved by the court.”). 291 Id. at 657. 292 See Thomas, supra note 98, at 156-57 (“[t]he court decided only a legal issue, which, under the common law special case, did not involve a question of the sufficiency of the evidence.”). The pre-1791 British cases cited by Redman were not to the contrary, as they concerned reservations of legal questions that did not turn on disputed facts such as the interpretation of statutes, the interpretation of a written will, and the determination of whether damages could be recovered against a person who induces another to breach her contract. See Sward, supra note 103, at 616-24. 293 That case was Jewell v. Parr, 13 C.B. 909, 138 Eng. Rep. 1460 (1853). Professor Sward argues that Jewell does not provide an adequate foundation for Redman because “the decision was necessary in order to preserve a rule of law concerning who had primary responsibility for paying a bill,” id. at 595, and accordingly was “more legal than factual.” Sward, supra note 103, at 595, 621. This distinction is unconvincing, for the same reasoning readily could carry over to Redman: the judge’s determination that the evidence propounded by insured was insufficient was “more legal than factual” insofar as it preserved a “rule of law” that insurance companies will not be deemed contractually liable unless insureds come forward with more than the evidence than was propounded in Redman. 294 Redman, 295 U.S. at 660. [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 55 provided. a. Unforeseen Circumstances. Non-Article III courts. Administrative agencies. New institution delegations. b. Efficiency. As shown above, the Court explicitly pointed to efficiency considerations in its Seventh Amendment jurisprudence. c. Works-Around. Concurrence has been turned to as a mechanism for working-around various obstacles. 1. Practical Barriers. Pragmatic barriers (agencies, treaty-substitutes, article V amendment) 2. Inaction By Primarily Tasked Institution. (DCC, FCL) 3. Constitutional Barriers. Probably most controversial of all, concurrence occasionally has been turned to avoid constitutional limitations that hindered the most obvious institution from undertaking a particular task. Consider in this regard Professor Pfander’s discussion of the Article I tribunal known as the Court of Claims. Under early American practice, a private party who had a “public claim” against government (such as contractors and other public creditors) would submit petitions for payment directly to the legislature. “Shortly after the Revolution, states began to experiment with the judicial determination of public claims.” Congress wished to meld these two practices together by having courts take the first crack at public claims but retaining ultimate control in deciding what public claims to ultimately authorize. The Invalid Pensions Act of 1792 required article III federal courts to “hear the pension claims of veterans, to estimate the degree of their disability, and to propose the proper amount of compensation due them,” and then provided that such judicial determinations would be reviewed by the Secretary of War and then Congress. The validity of this mechanism for initial judicial review followed by review by the executive and legislative branches, however, was determined to be unconstitutional in Hayburn’s Case, which held that Article III requires that the judiciary’s final decisions be final and accordingly could not be subject to executive or legislative review. Hayburn’s Case’s finality requirement led Congress to create the non-article III Court of Claims in 1855. “In creating the Court of Claims, Congress was said to have created an Article I tribunal subject to legislative oversight and free from the constraints of Article III.” In short, as Pfander nicely puts it, Hayburn’s Case “purchased judicial independence at the price of forcing Congress to turn to other institutions to perform the function of preliminary adjudication.” In fact, Congress created several other non-article III 295 296 297 298 299 295 Id. at 701. 296 Pfander, supra note 20, at 699. 297 2 U.S. (2 Dall.) 409 (1792). 298 Id. at 702-3. 299 Id. at 702 (emphasis supplied). [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 56 adjudicatory tribunals on the view that the Constitution flatly forbade it from assigning particular adjudicatory tasks to Article III courts. Such a use of concurrence presents difficult legitimacy challenges: Is the Court of Claims a brilliant work-around, or a troublesome (even unconstitutional) end-run around, article III’s finality requirement? Whereas Pfander appears to throw his lot in with the first approach in characterizing Hayburn’s Case as having “forc[ed] Congress to turn to other institutions to perform the function of preliminary adjudication,” an alternative conclusion would be that the Court of Claims is illegitimate: Congress cannot circumvent Article III’s finality requirement by creating adjudicative bodies that look and smell like federal courts but are simply called something else. 5. Synergies. Whole greater than sum of its parts. Complementing differing institution’ characteristics (Prospective versus presentist, i.e. in Midwest Oil; access to experts (agencies); superiority of caseby-case decisionmaking, at least to generate initial rules (admiralty) 6. Addressing Emergencies. (Block v. Hirsh and non-jury agencies). Danger of generalizing from the exception. 300 301 302 IV. NOT ALL OR NOTHING [to be written] Many powers that everybody accepts are exclusively held by single institution: (1) only Congress has appropriation power, (2) impeachment powers; (3) only Pres has recognition power Even where concurrence exists, often there are limits. Eg, Schor and limits on article I courts’ powers. Youngstown limits presidential “legislative” powers to independent powers + delegation. Matters currently up for grabs: declare war; V. METHODS FOR ADDRESSING CONFLICTS Though the possibility of conflict is a constant anxiety caused by concurrence, and sometimes is viewed as a definitive reason to embrace exclusivity, American law not infrequently confronts, and deals with, conflicts among two or more institutions with overlapping powers. A review shows that American law has developed six different methods for addressing inter-institutional conflicts. Relatedly, a study of the various methods for 303 304 300 See, e.g., Pfander, supra note 20, at 706-12 (arguing that Congress originally created non-article III territorial courts because it believed that inhabitants of territories “lacked federal rights to enforce”) and that territorial courts were local rather than national courts). 301 Id. at 702. 302 Indeed, Congress didn’t even attempt to avoid the locution of “court” when creating the Court of Claims. 303 See, e.g., Madison’s Second Helvidium letter. 304 Much of what follows in this Part is drawn from Mark D. Rosen, Revisiting Youngstown: Against the View that Justice Jackson’s Concurrence Resolves the Relation Between Congress and the Commander-in-Chief, 54 UCLA L. REV. 1703, 1717-31 (2007). [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 57 addressing conflict shows that context-specific institutional considerations, rather than trans-substantive principles, typically explain the selection of the method. That we already have at our disposal multiple mechanisms for dealing with conflict suggests that the prospect of conflict is not on its own a sufficient reason to rule out concurrence. At most, the prospect of conflict constitutes a cost of concurrence that appropriately is weighed against the benefits that concurrence promise in a particular context. A. Institution-Based Conflict-Resolution Principles. Two types: (a) Categorical Institution-Based Conflict Rule: one institution’s acts categorically trumps the other (e.g., supremacy clause; Congress trumps dormant commerce clause and federal common law rules; judiciary’s constitutional interpretations trump constitutional interpretations of other institutions under Marbury). Call this a Type 1A conflict-resolution rule (b) Presumptive Institution-Based Conflict Rule: one institution presumptively, but non-categorically, trumps (e.g., juries find facts, subject to narrow judicial overrides). Call this a Type 1B conflict-resolution rule. B. Time-Based Conflict-Resolution Principles. Once again, two types: (a) first-in-time (res judicata and collateral estoppel to resolve conflicts among courts with concurrent authority – the first court to reach final judgment trumps). Call this a Type 2A conflict-resolution rule. (b) last-in-time (treaties, Congressional Agreements, and Sole Executive Agreements, where conflicts among these are resolved on basis of a last-in-time rule; Rest (2d) of Judgments §15 rule according last-in-time trump to narrow category of res judicata issues: “When in two actions inconsistent final judgments are rendered, it is the later, not the earlier, judgment that is accorded conclusive effect in a third action under the rules of res judicata”). Call this a Type 2B conflict-resolution rule. Frequently used in relation to institutions of equivalent hierarchical rank where there is no a priori reason to give trumping advantage to one institution over another. C. Multi-factor Conflict-Resolution Principles. Eg, the multi-factor approach used in state conflict of laws doctrine. Used in circumstance of where institutions have equivalent hierarchical rank and a timing rule either wouldn’t work or would exclude too many considerations that are adjudged to be normatively relevant. Down-side: as number of considerations grows, can become ad-hoc and unpredictable. Call this a Type 3 conflict-resolution rule. D. No-Sorting Principles. A final possibility is that the law could refuse to adopt a conflict-sorting rule, with the result that two (or more) institutions are permitted to simultaneously act, even if they act inconsistently. There are several possible outcomes. First, the regulated entities may be subject to multiple rules simultaneously, some of which may conflict, and are [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 58 expected to conform their behavior nonetheless. Other times, the different institutions with overlapping authority may formally or informally negotiate among themselves to coordinate their actions. Such coordination typically is undertaken by the political branches of government, not the courts. Call this a Type 4 conflict-resolution rule. Alexander Hamilton proposed a Type 4 conflict-resolution rule in the course of the Pacificus-Helvidius Debates. Madison, it should be recalled, argued that if the President had the power to interpret treaties for one purpose, then it necessarily followed that the President also had to have the power to interpret treaties for purposes of determining whether war should be declared. Since the Constitution grants Congress the power to declare war, Madison concluded the President could neither declare war nor, as a consequence, interpret treaties. Hamilton disagreed, concluding that the President could interpret treaties pursuant to the exercise of his general executive powers while the Congress could interpret treaties in the exercise of its power to declare wars. I showed earlier, Madison recoiled at this, largely because it opened the door to conflicting treaty interpretations by the President and Congress. Hamilton’s response concerning possible conflicts appears when he discusses a hypothetical that pitted the President’s recognition power against Congress’ declare war powers. [to finish] Possible justifications: Competition, spur to action, belief that coordination likely to yield best outcome because pools institutional resources of both institutions, no viable alternative conflict-resolution rule. 305 306 307 VI. THE BIG PICTURE: META-NARRATIVES IMPLICATIONS A. Meta-Narratives. AND CONSTITUTIONAL B. Constitutional Implications. Eg, the multi-factor Originalism: treaty wrong (Tribe, Ackerman & Golove), but plausible sameeffect at least some places (Pacificus) Textualists: a la Merrill, plausible delegations; same-effect perfectly plausible change typically occurs at initiative of extra-judicial institutions. Broad array of pragmatic considerations has given rise to concurrence in past. [to write] 305 As I have explained elsewhere, this is true of state criminal law generally, and also is reflected in the Double Jeopardy Clause’s “dual sovereignty” doctrine. See Rosen, Youngstown Revisited, supra note ?, at xx. 306 (eg, UCCJA, cf. From checks and balances context of reconciling Senate and House bills). 307 Second Helvidius Letter, reprinted in Debates, supra note ?, at 66. [2008] FROM EXCLUSIVITY TO CONCURRENCE 59