* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download lastjudg
Parametric determinism wikipedia , lookup
Philosophical progress wikipedia , lookup
Marx's theory of alienation wikipedia , lookup
Frankfurt School wikipedia , lookup
Dialectical materialism wikipedia , lookup
Postmodernity wikipedia , lookup
Historicism wikipedia , lookup
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel wikipedia , lookup
After the Last Judgment: Hegel as Philosopher of Artificial Life Wolfgang Schirmacher, New York INTRODUCTION: PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY IN THE SPHERE OF POSTMODERNITY World history is the Last Judgment, and there is “no appealing”1 its decision, as Ernst Bloch determined. But what is the decision of the Last Judgment today? Marxists of all people, Hegel’s aptest pupils, in prayer wheel fashion have laid claim to historical development as the court of last instance, and the collapse of Communism has now proved itself to be all the more definitive. “Real Existing Socialism, considered by many despite all the immanent criticism and at least in principle as a serviceable alternative paradigm, has proven itself as non-viable,” as the writer Peter Schneider has summarized this judgment.2 Does this mean that Capitalism has won? Does Western consumer society represent the attainment of the aim of history, and the culmination of the process of human self-realization? Such false conclusions must be avoided at all costs, for the judgment passed is anything but unambiguous. The Final Judgment seems to resemble more the Oracle of Delphi; its obscure pronouncements are full of ambiguities and ironic surprises. Without its counterpart of Communism, Capitalism has lost all its sparkle, and while Western goods and media may dominate the markets, a North-South conflict is brewing that literally takes no prisoners. If the first postmodern revolution changed world history without shedding blood, through the simulation of popular sovereignty in an interactive media piece, the southern European tourist destination of Yugoslavia transformed itself behind our backs into a premodern paradise for sadists and cutthroats. What judgment will history pass upon powerful industrial states that stood by and watched the genocide in Rwanda, and then contented themselves with digging mass graves? Hegel’s Last Judgment aimed to “resurrect new life”3 from death and not to perpetuate “misery and destruction”.4 For in Hegel’s conception, it is only as uncomprehended history that world history is a “slaughtering block...to which the happiness of nations, the wisdom of the state, and the virtues of individuals have been led.”5 Rather, the “thinker of becoming” (as Bloch calls him) wagered on the conscious unity of theory and practice: “The aim of world history is... that the spirit attain knowledge of that which is true, and make this knowledge concrete, materialize it into an existing world, realize itself as objective.”6 Have the high hopes set by a philosophical world history not long since been dashed, at the latest in the gas chambers of Auschwitz? What knowledge is realized in the smoldering ecological disaster and in the outrageous injustices perpetrated against the third world? What must be the nature of a universal spirit that can hope to prevail in the sphere of postmodernity? Today, a philosophy of history must begin with the admission that Hegel cannot be restored, and that “history” as he understood it is indeed “at its end.” But this implies neither that Hegel’s dialectical philosophy is in every respect obsolete, nor that history has exhausted itself as an object of philosophical inquiry. Quite the contrary! Freed from Hegel’s selfinterpretation and from the determinations of his work’s reception history, Bloch’s prophetic words come true: “Hegel denied the future; no future will deny Hegel.”7 What remains exemplary is Hegel’s attitude as a thinker, his world-saturated circumspection, and his methodical procedure, which discovered history as “the most concrete of objects that encompasses within itself all the different aspects of existence.”8 In functional gesture and in dialectical strategy, Hegel can help us extract meaning from a history that de-constructs itself. This should not be construed as a proposal to separate undialectically the form and content of Hegel’s philosophy, but rather a new reading of Hegel as a philosopher who stands at the height of postmodern criticism and at the same time makes possible something currently sought the world over: a look “beyond postmodernity.” I. The Process of History and the Last Judgment in Hegel 1. After the Last Judgment: the Meaning of the “End of History” In the works of Schopenhauer, Hegel’s powerfully influential antipode, “The Last Judgment” is a key metaphor. For Schopenhauer, the world itself is a Last Judgment,9 and the hour of our death is the hour the judgment is pronounced.10 In this view, becoming and history are mere illusions, a capricious masquerade that acts out the ever-constant will to life. If one remembers that almost every age has considered itself an age of upheaval, and if one does not repress the images of presentday barbarity, then Schopenhauer’s pessimistic view of the Last Judgment seems much closer to the mark than does Hegel’s optimistic one. History has reached its end because there has never been a history, but only ever the “eternal return” of the same, as Nietzsche maintained.11 Without a doubt, Hegel did much to ensure that his philosophy of history can be read as an ideology of progress, but such an interpretation is by no means conclusive. Becoming , Hegel’s “password” (Bloch), is not synonymous with natural evolution or social progress; rather, becoming describes first and foremost that fundamental “movement before all interpretation” (Aristotle) that neither Schopenhauer nor Nietzsche would deny. How one interprets this movement, what meaning one gleans from the universal dynamic, serves to clarify the real and differentiate the philosophers one from the other. Hegel as “teacher of living movement”12 did nothing other than understand this becoming — and this is his great achievement — not from without, but as a “going into oneself” in the manner of the “knowing and self-imparting becoming”13 itself. To be sure, the “individual”14 of world history is the “spirit” whose “progress in the consciousness of freedom”15 retraces Hegel’s philosophy of history, — not the human species, and certainly not the individual person. But an anthropomorphic interpretation is by all means possible, seeing how Hegel’s analogy of the development from child to adult, as a “sequence of steps” in the “progression” of the becoming-consciousness [des Bewußtwerdens] in the spirit, can be readily applied to man as well. How much more anthropological is Feuerbach in the christological Hegel! The student carried to its end what in the work of the teacher was still lacking a concept.16 “World history equals last judgment” is a reversible equation17, for what was condemned or acquitted is our history. Justice is dispensed there and judgment passed. As fact, however, history remains mute; only when it is narrative are we able to glean meaning from it. The historical process “must be clarified and won” (Bloch) and this happens not through determinations of content nor ideological codification. Today, such a “grand narrative” (in Lyotard’s sense18) can only tell of the “end of history” and of the Last Judgment that has befallen Western metaphysics. To the extent that Hegel remained rooted in eternal time ["Überzeit in der Zeit"]19 that satisfied our “metaphysical need” (Schopenhauer) and allayed the creaturely fear of death, his history is completed. But the end of one history is the beginning of other histories; the Last Judgment has not adjourned. The verdict of Schopenhauer’s Last Judgment was decided at the outset, according to the motto “give him a fair trial and then hang him!”, but Hegel’s dialectical court is open to changes and thus always capable of surprising us with its verdicts. 2. After Humanism: Rehabilitation of the Anthropomorphic In the sphere of postmodernity, all isms are just so much presumptuous claptrap, including (and above all) humanism. Thus, we should not let Feuerbach persuade us to countermand Hegel’s disassociation from the delusion that man is the center of all things. There is no center anywhere! Neither God, nor nature, nor society are capable of establishing the unity that allows all differences to become relative. A humanism on a natural or on a historical basis must needs degenerate into an ideology of power and will want to decree what can only fulfill itself when left to its own devices. For Hegel, Nature is oriented “relatively to the spirit,” and the work of this “spirit” is, according to Hegel’s determination, “this: that it brings itself forth, makes itself into that which it is.”20 Today, this self-production is known as autopoiesis, which refers particularly to human activity. As the self-generating being (Homo generator)21, man avoids being master or slave of the other nature, and assumes responsibility for the world he generates. The aim of the Hegelian spirit, to become transparent to itself and at the same time to be world, without having to dominate something foreign to it, corresponds in gesture and strategy to a post-humanistic existence. Bound up with this is a rehabilitation of the anthropomorphic after the “death of God” (Nietzsche). This must be clearly differentiated from an anthropomorphism that is nothing but a naive anthropocentrism, that transfers human behavior to nature or the gods.22 Like Hegel’s spirit, man is “this: that it brings itself forth, makes itself into that which it is,” and for this work he indeed requires, as does the spirit, the entire cosmos. The result, which is in essence “something brought forth”23 constitutes our Lebenswelt [life-world] and influences the stories we tell ourselves about it. Philosophical apprehending, Hegel’s “idea of reason,” is one of these stories of the man responsible for himself (Homo generator), and by all means a very beautiful fable: that the real world is as it should be, that the rational will as the concrete good is the most powerful thing indeed; absolute power that unfolds itself24 Such a fable is by no means merely an idealistic fairy tale or a postmodern bedtime story for children. Hegel’s concept of world history avoids anthropocentrism just as it does biocentrism. That reason should prevail in the world, admittedly not in a straightline manner nor under all circumstances, throws down no challenge to the other nature, but is simply an anthropomorphic prerequisite to a life of fulfillment. What can remain open are the questions of what this rationality looks like and whether its instrument is one of identity or difference — just as long as it is human. In all cultures, our fables and stories tell of justice, the locus of mediation between the “concrete good” and the “rational will.” The human has the right to be solely human, and no one should misconstrue this as “human, all-toohuman.” This anthropomorphic justice is not simply given, but rather, as Hegel’s dialectical philosophy of history reminds each and every present-day, is generated by us, in struggle and in renunciation. 3. After Postmodernity: Dialectics of Artificial Life As Last Judgment, the murderous 20th century has in an immediate way acquainted us with the true, even if this world-historical process largely has yet to be apprehended. Technical civilization as efficient machine of destruction and universal system of exploitation targets man and nature without distinction. Metaphysics, this millennia-old occidental mode of life, has by means of modern technology become planetary, and through the synthesis of technology and anthropocentrism it has attained its final perfection as well as brought about its own demise. Postmodernity means the cultural diagnosis that sees traditional orientations as devalued, without itself being able to offer a new world view. The joyful-serious play of differences, however, cannot be expected to engender another epoch; attempts to codify a transitional phase and proclaim the philosophy of difference tend to make a somewhat desperate impression. Postmodern thinking is cleanup work; with deep erudition it sweeps up the shards of metaphysics or uses them to make ironic works of art — more or less to pass the time — anything goes. We are waiting “without expectation” (Heidegger) for something “beyond postmodernity,” for the true concept of a Lebenswelt (life-world) that strikes us every day as increasingly uncanny. “What comes after postmodernity?” was a question put to the leading postmodern philosopher Lyotard. His astounding reply, at the same time a challenge to the postmodern variations of spurious rationality, has to this day not been take seriously philosophically. “After postmodernity comes modernity” was Lyotard’s explanation.25 So, after postmodernity comes Hegel’s “Novum,” Nietzsche’s “Übermensch,” Adorno’s “completely other” [ganz Anderes], Heidegger’s enownment [Ereignis]! At issue here is not a return to metaphysics and its hypostasizations: neither history nor nature are being restored here. The modernity after postmodernity is the Other modernity, whereby “Other” is capitalized, in Levinas’s sense.26 This other modernity beyond postmodernity reveals itself as “artificial life,” and leaves behind a once-raging debate about who will determine and control this artificial life. In information technology and media as well as in biotechnology and the biological sciences, one can observe how long-since obsolete paradigms abuse their power to define when faced with new phenomena. Whether ethics and public acceptance attain a key position in this regard and mobilize criticism or whether a linear optimism of progress prevails, remains of secondary importance, for both positions bear the stamp of anthropocentrism and are deeply undialectical. Those blinded by humanism and fixated on the eradication of contradictions utterly fail to see that “artificial life” entails a fertile Hegelian contradiction. To acknowledge this contradiction in its immanent necessity and to urge it along as an open-ended theoretical-practical process, is the challenge faced by a philosophy of history in the Other modernity. Artificial life is anthropomorphic, but we do not produce it from nothing, nor is it a matter of some powerful other that stands opposed to us as a higher phase of evolution. The robot Dante II has much more in common with the poet Dante than conventional wisdom would have us believe! Virtual worlds, aesthetic spaces, and random, everyday discourses are all equally accessible to an ethics of fulfillment, in the performance of which human beings generate themselves (Homo generator). Adorno’s hope of being different without fear expresses the mood of this new life-world [Lebenswelt]. The dialectics of artificial life overcomes the one-sidedness of art and of life, and attains post-technological ethics worlds in which humanity enowns as though of its own accord. I will briefly outline this radical turn using the example of a culture of death in the Other modernity. II. The Culture of Death in the Other Modernity 1. Negativity and the Ethics of Fulfillment In opposition to Hegel’s history of success, Heidegger put forward a history of decline. The sharpness of negativity, this Hegelian development principle akin to death, turns dull when the result of history is a world ever more fulfilled. At the basis of every negativity, according to Heidegger’s critique of Hegel, lies a “daringness of thought” [Wagnis des Denkens] whose shadow is destruction.27 In this dialectical conflict, the concept of fulfillment mediates, a concept which encompasses construction and destruction, and as de-construction never redeems what was planned or intended. Fulfillment shows itself only after the fact, and brings about an order whose characteristics are unpredictability, lightness, and releasement [Gelassenheit]. An ethics of fulfillment needs no recognition, neither from society nor from individuals. Rather, it sets itself up — “before our eyes” (Maurice Merleau-Ponty) — as a world in which human rights are realized without humanism. The meaning of history as fulfilled life, life of fulfillment includes our very right to productive negativity and a culture of death.28 Death as nature, notes Hegel,29 is overcome in history, for death as fact is “the greatest banality among people,”30 as Nietzsche remarked. Such great teachers of practical wisdom as Epicurus and Spinoza have emphasized that we don’t need to worry about death, and Rorty, an American, summed up today’s pragmatic relation to death as follows: “I will die. There is nothing more to say.”31 [get original quote] While Schopenhauer characterized “the fear of death as the greatest fear,” a fear “native to every living thing,” he also qualified immediately this inappropriate ontologization of death: “Upon reflection it seems ridiculous to worry so about the brief span of time allotted to us in life”32 Our traditional understanding of death no longer fulfills itself and in the post-technological world it has become obsolete. The experiential background of the prevailing metaphysics of death has fallen away, as far as concerns the First World, and thus culturally as concerns the entire world. Death today is a simulation: a “media theatre of cruelty” (Jean Beaudrillard) about the death of the barbarians, or the superpower’s virtual war game, in which only the Third-World opponents die — and only offscreen at that. It is beyond all doubt: dying begins at birth! But the First World retorts: Life lasts until the last dying breath! Death no longer dwells “in the midst of life,” and a “headlong rush to death” (Heidegger) reveals no meaning: our statistical life expectancy has conquered the threatening power of death: for whom is death not welcome after the age of 90? (To be sure, what we still have to fear is a death without self-determination and dignity.) In a culture of death,such as it needs an artificial life, even one’s own death is selfengendered, a deed for which I am responsible. In Schopenhauer’s grim interpretation, nature asks the will to life in the hour of death: “Have you finally had enough?”33 On the other hand, the question posed in a culture of death would be “Have you lived?” She who has lived fulfills herself in death as well and is allowed to die; all the others merely croak. It is seldom and never as a rule — as it was in the metaphysical epoch — that one dies before one’s time in the First World, and it is this experience of a fully-lived life span (something still hardly ever taken into consideration by philosophy) forms the basis of a culture of death that owes its existence not to fear, but to generosity. 2. Sacrifice, Extravagance, Generosity Sacrificing oneself for others, for the community, for an idea, must not be idealized as a culture of heroic death, since it often merely confirms in secret a negative judgment of life. Death is conquered, as Schopenhauer would have it, when one discovers the worthlessness of life.34 Hegel, on the other hand, points out that every sacrifice is accompanied by pleasure and as “cult” it establishes a “ongoing poetry of life.”35 Immortality and eternal life would be unbearably boring, so that the aim of an ethics of fulfillment can never be to overcome death. Bataille outlined an “aesthetics of death”36 and coupled it with an economy of extravagance, thus conforming to key traits of a culture of death. Just as reckless lovers risk the leap into an enownment [Ereignis] beyond being and time, so does a “freeing-from-oneself-tothe-Other” become an ethical habit in the Other modernity which is artificial life. Levinas celebrated this extravagance that merges into asymmetric generosity and laughs at its own fear of death, as a praxis “beyond being.” The attitude he introduced paradigmatically as a “trembling and wavering for justice’s sake” makes possible the beginnings of a culture of death imbued with generosity. 3. Beyond Fear: Artificial Death “To live in such a way that one has one’s will to death at the right time!” recommended Nietzsche.37 Beyond the creaturely fear of death the artificial death awaits us, which the post-nihilistic Nietzsche announced as “voluntary (rational) death,” but only after he entrusted it to “a completely incomprehensible- and immoral-sounding morality of the future.” Yet the Other Modernity, artificial life, has already drawn near and with it, the culture of death anticipated by Nietzsche, the main characteristic of which is “a wise arrangement and a genuine ability to die.”38 Nietzsche’s teacher Schopenhauer must be read against the grain of his animosity toward life, so that his profound conception of death can come to fruition. In Schopenhauer’s words, death contains “the great reservoir of life”39 from which it feeds “an eternal noon,”40 Hegel’s “ongoing poetry of life,” for which life and death represent aesthetically luxuriant reflections in the mirror of the world. America’s most courageous philosopher, Avital Ronell, calls for “the embracing of being-unto-death” and “ecstatic temporality” [get the original words]41, for it is thus that being-unto-death changes into the enownment-of-death. In this enownment [Ereignis], the self learns how it can live confidently and free of anxiety, by means of such practices as caution, circumspection, empathy, and listening. In this culture of ethics, a timely death is part of a mastered existence, one characterized by persistence, deliberation, releasement [Gelassenheit], and generosity as life-attitudes. With the Second Negation, the dialectician Hegel opened the way to artificial death, a “course and process,” which “sublates” [aufhebt] nature and history in the consciously anthropomorphic person. The christological Hegel outlined precisely the culture of death whose influence is evolving even today; which, when regarded systematically, is a culture of the Second Negation: “The death of Christ is the death of this death itself, the negation of the negation.”42 Conclusion: Hegel as the Philosopher of Artificial Life To read Hegel as a philosopher of artificial life is not an attempt to do justice to his work from an historical standpoint, but rather to allow it to speak with regard to a future history. Hegel encourages us to dissolve the rigid opposition of anthropocentrism and biocentrism in a dialectic that leads to a new conception of the anthropomorphic. Man generates his world himself — as individual, as group, and as species — but only within the realm of his subjective and objective possibilities. As Homo generator, the “non-fixed animal” (Nietzsche) transcends all ontologies and transforms them into an ethics of fulfilled life. Hegel had attributed to Spirit what is actually an anthropomorphic existential: the self-production of a world through comprehending and realization. This Hegelian Spirit as the individual of world history is in itself a fulfilled mediation and from a strategic standpoint an antidote to the relapse into unreconciled contradictions, such as are represented by an optimistic faith in progress on the one side and a pessimistic criticism of history on the other. Without an unrelenting dialecticism, Artificial Life, the Other Modernity beyond postmodernity, would run the constant risk of succumbing to the monotony of the technological “framework” [Gestell] (Heidegger). In that case, the human world would indeed function like a well-designed cybernetic machine, but it could never fulfill itself anthropomorphically. That man can assert the right to resolve the contradictions of his existence offensively, and is thus able to realize a humanity without humanism, is Hegel’s lesson for the critics of contemporary society. A future history encompasses all phenomena, transgresses with the Second Negation every ontological fixation, and cultivates above all death. Today, we can say: this future has already begun, and Hegel with his dialectic was one of its most surprising envisioners. Translated by Daniel Theisen 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42