* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Hegel and Schopenhauer
Survey
Document related concepts
Transcript
Hegel and Schopenhauer: At the Threshold of Artificial Life I. History of the issues at hand The history of philosophy has rarely seen the likes of the animosity Schopenhauer harbored toward his contemporary Hegel. This sentiment was fed by a number of sources: envy of the highly successful elder philosopher, whom Schopenhauer, lacking in this regard, viewed as a usurper; the gnawing disappointment, manifesting itself in high-handed pretensions, at his own lack of success. One is often tempted to overlook that this animosity between Hegel and Schopenhauer was as abstract as it was one-sided, for Hegel was already dead when the poisonous barbs Schopenhauer aimed at him began to circulate. It was in fact the Hegelian school against which Schopenhauer fought, from his isolated, unsociable existence in Frankfurt, and the vehemence of his efforts grew the more the school’s influence waned in the face of the rising Biedermeier era at the time of the Restoration. From today’s perspective, Schopenhauer might strike us as a bold and daring critic of German Idealism, but it did not actually take much courage to kick out at a dead king whose followers over a wide front had begun to beat a hasty retreat. So it would seem that Schopenhauer’s fusillade of abuse served rather to bring his own system, with its “anthropological turn” (Arthur Hübscher), into sharper relief and at the same time to offer his services as a groundbreaking thinker to a new generation. Both arguments have their legitimacy, yet we should be wary of giving Schopenhauer the last word in his dispute with Hegel. In order to arrive at an appropriate philosophical understanding of this relationship, one must be able to appreciate Hegel as Schopenhauer did, but also to think, with Schopenhauer, against him: more than an antipode, Schopenhauer – in a dialectical sense – is a negating consummator of German Idealism, and it is in his philosophy that its furious final act takes place. At the same time, his philosophy heralds the turn to Kierkegaard, Feuerbach and Nietzsche. Originally, Schopenhauer and Hegel were not rivals. When Schopenhauer submitted his application in Latin for qualification as a lecturer at the University of Berlin, he had the full endorsement of Hegel, who at that time stood at the pinnacle of his renown. Hegel had high expectations for the young man with whom Goethe had conversed about his color theory, and showed himself to be quite benevolent during the habilitation colloquium. Later, Schopenhauer liked to recount how Hegel had made a fool of himself on account of his ignorance in the natural sciences, while he himself had known the right answer, but then after all, that was the role of the candidate. At any rate, Hegel showed no ill will whatsoever, and Schopenhauer attained the desired teaching qualification. Perhaps only a psychiatrist will ever be able to figure out what devil had got into him when he decided to hold his lecture, “On My Entire System,” at the very same day and time Hegel gave his own popular lecture. At any rate, it was a poor marketing decision, a folly he could indulge in only because of the modest fortune he inherited from his father, which freed him from having to earn his living from his teaching activity. Having failed in Berlin owing to poor attendance at his lectures, Schopenhauer retreated embittered to Frankfurt, survived Hegel, who died of cholera in 1831, and awaited his hour, which despite Hegel’s demise was long in coming. It was not until just a few years before his death in 1860 that Schopenhauer was able to savor the first fruits of his success, which for all that left a sour taste in his mouth. It was poets like Friedrich Hebel and composers like Richard Wagner who were the first to show Schopenhauer their admiration, while the 1 university philosophers he scorned with such powerful (and prophetic) words gave him a decidedly cooler reception. They left the faithful stewardship of Schopenhauer’s works to professors of Indology like Paul Deussen, who founded the Schopenhauer Society in 1915, and professors of German literature like Arthur Hübscher, president of that society for over 40 years. This situation often led to sectarianism among the members: no philosopher but Schopenhauer was accorded recognition. The Schopenhauer experts among German philosophers could be counted on two hands – to be sure, this group included such world-renowned contrarians as Ludwig Wittgenstein, as well as Rudolf Steiner, the founder of Anthroposophy, the sociologist and philosopher Arnold Gehlen, and the editor of the Philosophisches Wörterbuch (Philosopical Dictionary) and the Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung (Journal for Philosophical Research), Georgi Schischkoff. Karl Raimund Popper was also deeply influenced by Schopenhauer, as were his two philosophical rivals Max Horkheimer and Theodor W. Adorno. The early 1980s ushered in a minor Schopenhauer renaissance, as evidenced by the many complete editions made available in paperback and the surprisingly interesting dissertations that have appeared since this time. This newly awakened interest also led to the founding of the Internationale SchopenhauerVereinigung (International Schopenhauer Association) in 1985. The Association’s stated objective, not only to study Schopenhauer thoroughly but to bring him into dialogue with other contemporary philosophers as well, has since led to numerous conferences and symposia in Germany and abroad. This activity has ameliorated the hesitancy of Schopenhauer scholars to explore the thought of other philosophers, particularly Nietzsche and Heidegger, and successful efforts have been made to bring Schopenhauer’s thought into the current debates about postmodernity, ethics, and aesthetics. Yet is has been difficult to initiate a Schopenhauer-Hegel debate, even if a number of different approaches have been attempted. In the Hübscher Festschrift "Zeit der Ernte – Studien zum Stand der Schopenhauer-Forschung" (“Harvest Season – Studies on the State of Schopenhauer Research,” ed. W. Schirmacher, Stuttgart 1982), Peter Engelmann, who later became publisher at the Passagen-Verlag publishing company, and I took the bull by the horns and attempted to do justice to the two philosophers. The International Hegel Society chairmen Wilhelm Raimund Beyer and Wolfgang Lefevre invited me to the 1988 conference on “Nature and Mind” in Berlin, and in 1994 an invitation to a plenary lecture at the International Hegel Congress in Budapest was extended to the president of the International Schopenhauer Society, but to this day the two societies have still not met in joint session. It seems that Schopenhauer’s curse still exerts its influence – as in former days, disguised as lack of interest. II. In the Face of Artificial Life In Berlin and in Budapest, my lectures have sought to determine Hegel’s relevance to a philosophy of artificial life. In them, the debate with Schopenhauer took place under cover, for this philosopher too – just as every other one of the tradition – must prove himself in the face of the emerging artificial life. The basis of discussion has changed completely: instead of once again making history versus anthropological constants, dialectics versus the search for truth, intellect versus will and body the fundamental questions of the Hegel-Schopenhauer controversy, these oppositions now become indifferent in view of a new determination of human life. Indifferent does not mean unimportant or without informative value, but only that both sides turn out to be aspects of a new, essentially different phenomenon; that their difference, to freely quote Heidegger, merely bears out the identity of the other. In properly Hegelian 2 manner, these oppositions are subjected to a second negation and find themselves dialectically in another dimension; not pacified, but productively utilized. Nevertheless, it is Schopenhauer who encourages a more radical view: what happens here is not solely another dialectical sublation like so many others before it, but rather that “the will turns” and can in artificial life become identical with itself. Creation’s character of suffering is sublated and will remain revoked regardless of how the dialectic of lived life continues, for Homo generator, the human being that generates itself as nature and culture, has finally brought its ethical knowledge into harmony with the course of the world. To be sure, nothing is yet to be seen of this pacified earth, nor of nature’s having become humane; too violent, unjust, and unpredictable does the condition of human society appear at the beginning of this 21st century. Yet attentive philosophical thought can already discern the sign of another world, the human world, and sees how invisible educators all over the world are at work to bring humans to themselves at last. Those living today will only to a very limited degree take part in this “turning” [Kehre] (Heidegger), that will not lead us to a “human park” (Peter Sloterdijk), but rather allow us to realize the art of life. It is the very media so readily scorned by Sloterdijk and other well-meaning cultivators of humanity that are the most successful educators: they educate indirectly and without intention, and accustom the not-yet-initiated almost unintentionally to the culture of self-networking. It is selfevident that this net culture, in which software and hardware augment one another, cannot become operative without economic and political changes. But such changes are no longer dependent upon the will of contemporaries, whose share of altruism has certainly not increased since Schopenhauer’s time; rather, they result as networking gains. It is easy to say (and often complained) that the internet and whatever succeeds it will fundamentally change life on earth in every respect, but no one has the imagination necessary to imagine this as a whole (the visionaries of internet society are the one-eyed ones among the blind). “Genuine philosophers,” nevertheless (to recall Schopenhauer’s distinction), have an advantage over the studiers of trends and the prophets of science: their specialty has always been the whole, whether true or untrue, which they attempt to grasp intuitively and pin down with bold metaphors. Of course, they could never work without the help of the philosophical tradition, whose courageous work in the formulation of concepts has preceded them into the unknown. This past now comes back at us from the future, and both Hegel and Schopenhauer number among those conceptual artists without whose work our insight into that which is (as Heidegger said) would never have been possible. We must not let it discourage us that day-to-day reality will require decades (if not centuries) before the notion of Homo generator in artificial life becomes as self-evident as those of objective reality or Kantian ethics have become today. No philosopher would be able to discern anything that has not long since become reality. The fundamental error of metaphysics did not consist in posing questions to which there are no answers (for humans will always do this), but in granting prescriptive power to the theory born in human heads. Then, the best theoretical knowledge and the most violent of means (this applies particularly in politics) were used to attempt to bring this figment of the imagination, this purely cerebral creation to life. Yet only Homo creator could do this, the anthropocentric chimera that previously obscured our authentic form as Homo generator. We are not God, who represents metaphysics carried to an extreme, but we generate world with materials given in all their mutability. Thus, the world springs not from our heads; our spirit springs from the world, whose exhortation to determine it is fundamentally limited. Something is 3 always already there, and this There teaches our theory to be modest. To be sure, our spirit is autopoietic, but neither as individual self nor as a reflex reaction to impressions from the world. It would be going too far to follow the course of the human monad’s “unfolding, folding, re-unfolding,” as Deleuze recently determined**. For our context, all that matters is the post-metaphysical aspect: theories, concepts, conceptions of the world are factors in a world process that is already in motion – they inspire, refine, and change what transpires through us, but – apart from theory itself – they have no causative, originary force. At first glance, it is correct that we live in “interpretation worlds,” but these secondary worlds, as heeded as they are, owe their existence to a life that is unheeded in ethical worlds and thus effectively lived. III. Questions to Hegel and Schopenhauer What is the role of dialectics in artificial life? Will contradictions and injustices continue to act as driving forces for historical development or will Schopenhauer’s eristic dialectics with their warning against a contemptible dialogue partner carry the day? To put the question thus is perhaps to put it too succinctly. To be sure, transparency of argumentation strategies will have to become part of the general pedagogical curriculum so that the netizens of tomorrow will not be so easily duped, but it is just as certain that error and folly can never be completely eradicated: the total amount of necessary suffering, and one must concede this point to Schopenhauer, will most likely remain the same for all eternity. Yet Hegel’s faith in the power of historical dialectics to promote freedom through self-consciousness is equally justified: the total amount of self-inflicted suffering in our life will sink dramatically. Our self-generation fulfills itself autopoietically in the art of a well-lived life: valuation, the infinite finiteness of the world (Weltfülle), the giving of meaning come about as though by themselves (auto) (Guattari, Chaosmosis, 20-21). Envy, hate, and jealousy reveal themselves to be historically dependent factors, not anthropological constants; schadenfreude spices up the play of media and no longer threatens anyone’s existence, since people no longer exercise control over each other. Whatever mischief the nasty neighbor threatens to carry out, the effects of his misdeeds remain dependent on my consent: if I refuse to play along, he will have to make do with my virtual clone. Schopenhauer had a neighbor, a gossipmonger, whose presence poisoned the atmosphere of the stairway their apartments shared until the day he pushed her down the stairs (for which he subsequently paid dearly). He could have prevented the situation entirely had he refused to play along. We are no longer compelled to coexist, for each monad, if it wanted to, could lead the life of a hermit at the highest technical standard of living – including the occasional orgy. For the survival of the individual (and of the species) is no longer in question, even if it will still continue to be an issue for some time. In the artificial life of the posttechnological age, the most advanced technologies ensure imperceptibly and without calling attention to themselves that the human right to the absence of want, compulsion, and untimely death will be globally fulfilled. What, then, remains of the question of truth, what impels the knowledge of beings and Be-ing, when death, this wellspring of metaphysical inquiry, has become a welcome guest, the pain-free end of a life lived to the fullest? Ontology and epistemology are dialectically “sublated” [“aufgehoben”], for what I can know about manifold Be-ing is ethically and aesthetically decided [/determined; entschieden] from the start. The psychiatrist and philosopher Felix Guattari – a compatriot of Gilles Deleuze, after Heidegger perhaps the most important thinker of the 20th century – in 4 his last book attempted to define as “chaosmosis”* the way that ethics and aesthetics, the individual and his or her socio-cultural environment fulfill Homo generator’s selfgiven mission: the osmotic “production of subjectivity,” in which all materials take part in equal measure. It is as a productive factor of this bringing-forth, which follows no linear logic, that dialectics remains operative, and truth is its most beautiful moment. “Who are we?” “What does it mean to be human?” Such questions answer themselves: we are the askers of questions, whatever the answers turn out to be. In the transition to artificial life, this controversial choice between intellect-essence and will-nature, between Hegel and Schopenhauer, has become only more controversial. In the century of the brain and in light of the “egotism of the gene,” Schopenhauer’s biological perspective seems to have been fully justified. Yet one should not overlook that Schopenhauer was only expressing bluntly what Hegel knew enough to repress, but in their appraisal of the situation, their positions were close indeed: biology is not humane, the law of “eat or be eaten” is a moral abomination. Albert Camus declared a century later, in the gesture of the “human in revolt,” that he rejected creation in its entirety if even one child had to suffer. One can only wonder at the inhumanity with which modern-day neuro-philosophers advocate a biological computer in our head, a computer that requires the ego only as a projection. It is as though they could not bear the thought that there is no longer an authority to determine who the human being is and to dictate how he should construct his life. Thus does an organ that without me is a mere object (and a potential food) become the profane idol that we must serve. Even more absurd is the paean sung to the gene, to whose pipe we must dance. This genetically specified reincarnation of the Schopenhauerian Will in Nature, according to which our sexual organs constitute the center of the universe, can only remind us why the human being, against all appearances and despite his close genetic kinship with the animals, is not an animal. From the very beginning, being a human has meant acting differently from animals, having to become human, and this becoming can be thought of as open-ended, as never coming to a conclusion. To this end, we take merely the materials as given, but none of their determinacies, and generate whatever occurs to us – not what occurs to natural evolution. Feedback too, the falsification of the human project remains is left solely to our judgment, which, to be sure, in its own interest heeds the materiality of the phenomena. Neither nature worship nor contempt for nature characterizes the work of Homo generator, for whom mind and body, will and insight develop the self itself, each in different ways yet in their intention identical ways, which show themselves as life-techniques. In no way are these intentions necessarily anthropocentric, but they are indeed anthropomorphic; they do not place the “eccentric human” (Hellmuth Plessner) in the center, but they do defend his right to a home. Homo generator will allow no objective determination to deny its own self-experience. Whether it is symbolization or language itself that determines the limits of our experience, can remain an open question, since the self itself is not an empirical self, but rather an activity that generates something like the ego, the self, the individual. Nothing shows more clearly than the spirit-will controversy between Schopenhauer and Hegel that such dichotomies are fruitless. As much as the presumptuous and antithetical claim to primacy has afforded us a sharper view of the respective phenomenon, it obscures the necessity of the work of both in the task of establishing 5 a truly human life. Hegel had much greater confidence in our ability to humanize the world (in his interpretation, to spiritualize [vergeistigen] it) than the more melancholy Schopenhauer. From an early age, the latter had a clear picture of human baseness and the wrath of nature, and as much as he hated the inhumanity of it all, he was unable to believe humanity capable of extricating itself from the workings of nature. Thus, all that remained as an ethical stance was the solidarity of the sufferers, as Max Horkheimer pointed out. This solidarity is rooted in humanitarianism and it demands of us, even and above all in happy circumstances, that we not see ourselves as rescued ones and that we behave optimistically. But the Schopenhauer of the black moods had his white days too, and always at those times when he was overwhelmed by the intuition that the will could turn around and nothingness could become the starting point of a world without selfinflicted suffering. Yet the early-embittered philosopher withheld for the most part this intellectual-mystical experience from his fellow humans, for without a foregoing reprimand and penitent mending of ways, he saw no opportunity to bring about this turnabout of will – doubtless, the teachings of Christianity had a lasting effect here. Nevertheless, the ethical white shimmered through Schopenhauer’s metaphysical black clearly enough to become time and again the aesthetic (in the sense of aisthesis) jumping-off place for philosophers after him – Nietzsche is the first of the “white” Schopenhauerians. *** The artificial life co-generated by Nietzsche seems to have begun without an inner conversion preceding it, but this appearance may deceive. While one indeed cannot speak here of a change of attitude as general as it is individual, Hegel’s offensive thesis of world history as last judgment just may have borne itself out, at least indirectly. The bloody 20th century, which revealed its inhuman character in the gas warfare of the First World War and the atomic bombs of the Second, outdid nature’s inhumanity with the manufacture of death at Auschwitz. With Auschwitz, humanity has lost its innocence, but since that time it is irrevocably challenged as Homo generator: human nature does not exist, it must be generated in a global exertion without end. The ongoing ecological crisis makes it clear that this nature is not limited to the human person and the world it shares, but includes that which is known as the natural environment. Thus, while the forces of nature may want to remind us time and again through unforeseeable and uncontrollable events that they are not the work of human hands, Homo generator has never claimed that they were. It is merely our responsibility to bring them, in their materiality (tamable or not), into an anthropomorphic world, and no hurricane or earthquake can then serve as an explanatory excuse for the inhuman suffering caused by them. How does the human being live, what determines human development, what can humans hope for, and how will human existence fulfill itself? The ethics of the saint is Schopenhauer’s resigned answer, justified as much by the media obsession with serial killers as by the young mercenaries from the realm of investment banking. An international ethics guaranteed by the constitutional state, on the other hand, is Hegel’s well-founded hope, which has been at least partially realized in the universality of human rights championed these days by Western courts. Human beings need not resign themselves to being born in wretched circumstances and robbed of their human rights by an unjust state. Schopenhauer thought so as well, but he was skeptical about whether this situation could ever change. Yet it is in the Hegelian world spirit that Schopenhauer’s saint morality achieves concreteness, and 6 to the astonishment of all proves itself eminently useable. No tradition, as venerable as it may be, and no international law that harasses its own citizens from behind the protective shield of sovereignty, can offer any lasting protection these days from punishment threatened by an enraged world community. To be sure, the courage and the will of governments to intervene for moral-ethical reasons (and not merely out of self-interest) in the internal affairs of other states is still a rare phenomenon, and it is all too common that they look the other way in cowardice. Yet history, which in Marx’s words cannot take form without us, has revealed itself as an opportunity for becoming human: one must merely take heart and seize the seam of its cloak, just as the Monday demonstrators did in Leipzig in 1989 – among them members of my family as well. What is ethically decisive here is not merely the sum of our inner qualities, as Schopenhauer thought, but just as much, if not even more so, the conditions of posttechnological society. The social human being is not the individual pressed into the service of society, but rather the ensemble of all shared and developed life technologies, from the global economy, to education and culture, to the Internet. The fundamental changes in the hardware and software of our global existence, changes which neither individual states nor isolated societies can resist, take place for the most part behind our backs, if not without our active participation. This development need not cause alarm; what one ought to fear is missing out on this transformation itself. Hegel’s ruse of reason is at work here, just as is Schopenhauer’s artist of genius, who can silence the will within for moments at a time and bring into circulation a “graspable idea,” the truth framed in a work. We would be doing justice to Schopenhauer and Hegel if we could finally succeed in deeming highly desirable these indirect transformation processes and the ethical happenings behind our backs. Such acknowledgment, however, must remain no more than a momentary flash! The intuitions of a fulfilled life must be released immediately into oblivion for them to remain effective. Translated by Daniel Theisen · Guattari, Felix, Chaosmosis – An Ethico-Aesthetic Paradigm. Transl. P.Bains / J.Pefanis. Indiana University Press, Bloomington 1995. ** Deleuze, Gilles, [get English title and info] Die Falte: Leibniz und der Barock. Übers.U.J.Schneider. Frankfurt/ Main 1995. 7