• Study Resource
  • Explore
    • Arts & Humanities
    • Business
    • Engineering & Technology
    • Foreign Language
    • History
    • Math
    • Science
    • Social Science

    Top subcategories

    • Advanced Math
    • Algebra
    • Basic Math
    • Calculus
    • Geometry
    • Linear Algebra
    • Pre-Algebra
    • Pre-Calculus
    • Statistics And Probability
    • Trigonometry
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Astronomy
    • Astrophysics
    • Biology
    • Chemistry
    • Earth Science
    • Environmental Science
    • Health Science
    • Physics
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Anthropology
    • Law
    • Political Science
    • Psychology
    • Sociology
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Accounting
    • Economics
    • Finance
    • Management
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Aerospace Engineering
    • Bioengineering
    • Chemical Engineering
    • Civil Engineering
    • Computer Science
    • Electrical Engineering
    • Industrial Engineering
    • Mechanical Engineering
    • Web Design
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Architecture
    • Communications
    • English
    • Gender Studies
    • Music
    • Performing Arts
    • Philosophy
    • Religious Studies
    • Writing
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Ancient History
    • European History
    • US History
    • World History
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Croatian
    • Czech
    • Finnish
    • Greek
    • Hindi
    • Japanese
    • Korean
    • Persian
    • Swedish
    • Turkish
    • other →
 
Profile Documents Logout
Upload
On Herbrand`s Theorem for Intuitionistic Logic
On Herbrand`s Theorem for Intuitionistic Logic

Autoepistemic Logic and Introspective Circumscription
Autoepistemic Logic and Introspective Circumscription

2.1 Using Inductive Reasoning to Make Conjectures
2.1 Using Inductive Reasoning to Make Conjectures

CMPSCI 250: Introduction to Computation
CMPSCI 250: Introduction to Computation

Document
Document

Simple multiplicative proof nets with units
Simple multiplicative proof nets with units

1 The Easy Way to Gödel`s Proof and Related Matters Haim Gaifman
1 The Easy Way to Gödel`s Proof and Related Matters Haim Gaifman

... started by enumerating the wffs and by setting ourselves the task to get a wff ϕk for which (5) holds. But having identified ϕn with the wff whose Gödel number is n, we replaced (5) by (7); after that we never used the assumption that ‘n’ and ‘m’ range over natural numbers. They can range over some ...
On Provability Logic
On Provability Logic

... S(S(S(0))) is denoted 3. More generally, the n-th numeral is defined as the term S(S . . (0) . .) with n occurrence of the symbol S. As an exercise we suggest the reader to formulate the fact that there are infinitely many powers of two in the arithmetical language. The solution is not completely tr ...
GENERALIZING ZECKENDORF`S THEOREM TO
GENERALIZING ZECKENDORF`S THEOREM TO

PDF - Project Euclid
PDF - Project Euclid

Applications of Number Theory to Fermat`s Last Theorem
Applications of Number Theory to Fermat`s Last Theorem

When Bi-Interpretability Implies Synonymy
When Bi-Interpretability Implies Synonymy

Sketch-as-proof - Norbert Preining
Sketch-as-proof - Norbert Preining

On the number of real quadratic fields with class number divisible by 3,
On the number of real quadratic fields with class number divisible by 3,

Module 3. The Fundamental Theorem of Arithmetic
Module 3. The Fundamental Theorem of Arithmetic

... Seuss) which means “to discover where something is, discover where it’s not.” His idea is very simple. Write down all the numbers from 1 to 100. Ignore 1 because it is a unit—it’s neither prime nor composite. After 1 the first number we come to is 2, which must be prime because there are no smaller ...
Proof Theory: From Arithmetic to Set Theory
Proof Theory: From Arithmetic to Set Theory

... largely through the copious writings of Chrysippus that the Stoic school became established, though many of these writings have been lost. • The patterns of reasoning described by Stoic logic are the patterns of interconnection between propositions that are completely independent of what those propo ...
Diophantine equations
Diophantine equations

... the usual way, but you can also notice that x(x − 1)(x − 2)(x − 3) = (x2 − 3x + 1)2 − 1. 3. Solve the diophantine equation y 2 = x(x − 1)(x − 2)(x − 3)(x − 4)(x − 5) in x, y ∈ Z. Hint: you can do it the usual way, but you can also use the identity x(x − 1)(x − 2)(x − 3)(x − 4)(x − 5) = (x3 − 15x2 /2 ...
Advanced Topics in Propositional Logic
Advanced Topics in Propositional Logic

Document
Document

Geometry
Geometry

... we clearly have µ ¶ nt cr (G) ≤ 2 · ≤ n2t 2. ...
Chapter 5 - Set Theory
Chapter 5 - Set Theory

A Readable Introduction to Real Mathematics
A Readable Introduction to Real Mathematics

Proof - Dr Frost Maths
Proof - Dr Frost Maths

Notes for week 11.
Notes for week 11.

Section 9.2: Summation Notation
Section 9.2: Summation Notation

... Annuities differ from the kind of investments we studied in Section 6.5 in that payments are deposited into the account on an on-going basis, and this complicates the mathematics a little.6 Suppose you have an account with annual interest rate r which is compounded n times per year. We let i = nr de ...
< 1 ... 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 ... 170 >

Theorem



In mathematics, a theorem is a statement that has been proven on the basis of previously established statements, such as other theorems—and generally accepted statements, such as axioms. The proof of a mathematical theorem is a logical argument for the theorem statement given in accord with the rules of a deductive system. The proof of a theorem is often interpreted as justification of the truth of the theorem statement. In light of the requirement that theorems be proved, the concept of a theorem is fundamentally deductive, in contrast to the notion of a scientific theory, which is empirical.Many mathematical theorems are conditional statements. In this case, the proof deduces the conclusion from conditions called hypotheses or premises. In light of the interpretation of proof as justification of truth, the conclusion is often viewed as a necessary consequence of the hypotheses, namely, that the conclusion is true in case the hypotheses are true, without any further assumptions. However, the conditional could be interpreted differently in certain deductive systems, depending on the meanings assigned to the derivation rules and the conditional symbol.Although they can be written in a completely symbolic form, for example, within the propositional calculus, theorems are often expressed in a natural language such as English. The same is true of proofs, which are often expressed as logically organized and clearly worded informal arguments, intended to convince readers of the truth of the statement of the theorem beyond any doubt, and from which a formal symbolic proof can in principle be constructed. Such arguments are typically easier to check than purely symbolic ones—indeed, many mathematicians would express a preference for a proof that not only demonstrates the validity of a theorem, but also explains in some way why it is obviously true. In some cases, a picture alone may be sufficient to prove a theorem. Because theorems lie at the core of mathematics, they are also central to its aesthetics. Theorems are often described as being ""trivial"", or ""difficult"", or ""deep"", or even ""beautiful"". These subjective judgments vary not only from person to person, but also with time: for example, as a proof is simplified or better understood, a theorem that was once difficult may become trivial. On the other hand, a deep theorem may be simply stated, but its proof may involve surprising and subtle connections between disparate areas of mathematics. Fermat's Last Theorem is a particularly well-known example of such a theorem.
  • studyres.com © 2025
  • DMCA
  • Privacy
  • Terms
  • Report