
Cantor`s Legacy Outline Let`s review this argument Cantor`s Definition
... squared number is one which results from the multiplication of another number by itself. Very well… If I assert that all numbers, including both squares and non-squares, are more than the squares alone, I shall speak the truth, shall I not? ...
... squared number is one which results from the multiplication of another number by itself. Very well… If I assert that all numbers, including both squares and non-squares, are more than the squares alone, I shall speak the truth, shall I not? ...
Precalculus with Calculus Curriculum Map
... Include at least an informal proof of Rolle’s Theorem; Explain MVT as a “rotated” version of Rolle. Emphasize that on the AP exam, students must state their conclusions verbally and/or with mathematically concise language (a number line argument alone is not acceptable); Be sure to include two impor ...
... Include at least an informal proof of Rolle’s Theorem; Explain MVT as a “rotated” version of Rolle. Emphasize that on the AP exam, students must state their conclusions verbally and/or with mathematically concise language (a number line argument alone is not acceptable); Be sure to include two impor ...
Zeros of Polynomial Functions
... If a polynomial equation is of degree, n, then counting multiple roots separately, the equation has n roots. If a + bi is a root of a polynomial equation with real coefficients (b ≠ 0), then the complex imaginary number a – bi is also a root. Complex imaginary roots, if they exist, occur in conjugat ...
... If a polynomial equation is of degree, n, then counting multiple roots separately, the equation has n roots. If a + bi is a root of a polynomial equation with real coefficients (b ≠ 0), then the complex imaginary number a – bi is also a root. Complex imaginary roots, if they exist, occur in conjugat ...
Week 3-4: Permutations and Combinations
... First Method. We may have 11 people (including one of the two unhappy persons but not both) to sit first; there are 10! such seating plans. Next the second unhappy person can sit anywhere except the left side and right side of the first unhappy person; there are 9 choices for the second unhappy per ...
... First Method. We may have 11 people (including one of the two unhappy persons but not both) to sit first; there are 10! such seating plans. Next the second unhappy person can sit anywhere except the left side and right side of the first unhappy person; there are 9 choices for the second unhappy per ...
Chapter 1 Logic
... integer n(n + 1) is even”. We could take a first step towards a symbolic representation of this statement by writing “∀n, n(n+1) is even”, and specifying that the universe of n is the integers. (This statement is true.) The existential quantifier ∃ asserts that there exists at least one allowed repl ...
... integer n(n + 1) is even”. We could take a first step towards a symbolic representation of this statement by writing “∀n, n(n+1) is even”, and specifying that the universe of n is the integers. (This statement is true.) The existential quantifier ∃ asserts that there exists at least one allowed repl ...
pdf - at www.arxiv.org.
... been argued in [6, 18, 22]. In the classical approach [18], the semantic view was taken: if a nonterminating SLD-resolution derivation for Φ and A accumulates computed substitutions σ0 , σ2 , . . . in such a way that . . . (σ2 (σ0 (A))) is an infinite ground formula, then . . . (σ2 (σ0 (A))) is said ...
... been argued in [6, 18, 22]. In the classical approach [18], the semantic view was taken: if a nonterminating SLD-resolution derivation for Φ and A accumulates computed substitutions σ0 , σ2 , . . . in such a way that . . . (σ2 (σ0 (A))) is an infinite ground formula, then . . . (σ2 (σ0 (A))) is said ...
Cichon`s diagram, regularity properties and ∆ sets of reals.
... cardinals and a measurable above them, then there is a forcing extension in which ∆1n+4 (B) holds but ∆1n+4 (C) fails. In this paper, we do not adopt the “large cardinal approach”, for the following reasons: 1. As the consistency of “for all P and n < ω, Σ1n (P) holds” is just an inaccessible (it is ...
... cardinals and a measurable above them, then there is a forcing extension in which ∆1n+4 (B) holds but ∆1n+4 (C) fails. In this paper, we do not adopt the “large cardinal approach”, for the following reasons: 1. As the consistency of “for all P and n < ω, Σ1n (P) holds” is just an inaccessible (it is ...
i(k-1)
... integers (or a subset like integers larger than 3) that have appropriate self-referential structure— including both equalities and inequalities—using either weak or strong induction as needed. – Critique formal inductive proofs to determine whether they are valid and where the error(s) lie if they a ...
... integers (or a subset like integers larger than 3) that have appropriate self-referential structure— including both equalities and inequalities—using either weak or strong induction as needed. – Critique formal inductive proofs to determine whether they are valid and where the error(s) lie if they a ...
Document
... How many ways are there to pick 2 successive cards from a standard deck of 52 such that: a. The first card is an Ace and the second is not a Queen? b. The first is a spade and the second is not a Queen? a) We are creating a list of two things. There are 4 choices for the first item and (51 – 4) = 47 ...
... How many ways are there to pick 2 successive cards from a standard deck of 52 such that: a. The first card is an Ace and the second is not a Queen? b. The first is a spade and the second is not a Queen? a) We are creating a list of two things. There are 4 choices for the first item and (51 – 4) = 47 ...
Generating Prime Numbers
... possible to always return a prime number. In [1] it is stated that a nonconstant polynomial f (x) with integer coefficients produces at least one composite image. In [1] they improve the result by proving the following theorem. Theorem 2. Given a positive integer n, f (x) takes an infinite number of ...
... possible to always return a prime number. In [1] it is stated that a nonconstant polynomial f (x) with integer coefficients produces at least one composite image. In [1] they improve the result by proving the following theorem. Theorem 2. Given a positive integer n, f (x) takes an infinite number of ...
RECURSIVE REAL NUMBERS 784
... 6 See, e.g., MacDuffee, Introduction to abstract algebra, New York, 1940, Chap. VI. License or copyright restrictions may apply to redistribution; see http://www.ams.org/journal-terms-of-use ...
... 6 See, e.g., MacDuffee, Introduction to abstract algebra, New York, 1940, Chap. VI. License or copyright restrictions may apply to redistribution; see http://www.ams.org/journal-terms-of-use ...
Logic and Proof Jeremy Avigad Robert Y. Lewis Floris van Doorn
... Aristotle observed that the correctness of this inference has nothing to do with the truth or falsity of the individual statements, but, rather, the general pattern: Every A is B. Every B is C. Therefore every A is C. We can substitute various properties for A, B, and C; try substituting the propert ...
... Aristotle observed that the correctness of this inference has nothing to do with the truth or falsity of the individual statements, but, rather, the general pattern: Every A is B. Every B is C. Therefore every A is C. We can substitute various properties for A, B, and C; try substituting the propert ...
Theorem
In mathematics, a theorem is a statement that has been proven on the basis of previously established statements, such as other theorems—and generally accepted statements, such as axioms. The proof of a mathematical theorem is a logical argument for the theorem statement given in accord with the rules of a deductive system. The proof of a theorem is often interpreted as justification of the truth of the theorem statement. In light of the requirement that theorems be proved, the concept of a theorem is fundamentally deductive, in contrast to the notion of a scientific theory, which is empirical.Many mathematical theorems are conditional statements. In this case, the proof deduces the conclusion from conditions called hypotheses or premises. In light of the interpretation of proof as justification of truth, the conclusion is often viewed as a necessary consequence of the hypotheses, namely, that the conclusion is true in case the hypotheses are true, without any further assumptions. However, the conditional could be interpreted differently in certain deductive systems, depending on the meanings assigned to the derivation rules and the conditional symbol.Although they can be written in a completely symbolic form, for example, within the propositional calculus, theorems are often expressed in a natural language such as English. The same is true of proofs, which are often expressed as logically organized and clearly worded informal arguments, intended to convince readers of the truth of the statement of the theorem beyond any doubt, and from which a formal symbolic proof can in principle be constructed. Such arguments are typically easier to check than purely symbolic ones—indeed, many mathematicians would express a preference for a proof that not only demonstrates the validity of a theorem, but also explains in some way why it is obviously true. In some cases, a picture alone may be sufficient to prove a theorem. Because theorems lie at the core of mathematics, they are also central to its aesthetics. Theorems are often described as being ""trivial"", or ""difficult"", or ""deep"", or even ""beautiful"". These subjective judgments vary not only from person to person, but also with time: for example, as a proof is simplified or better understood, a theorem that was once difficult may become trivial. On the other hand, a deep theorem may be simply stated, but its proof may involve surprising and subtle connections between disparate areas of mathematics. Fermat's Last Theorem is a particularly well-known example of such a theorem.