Download First-Order Logic

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts

History of artificial intelligence wikipedia , lookup

Knowledge representation and reasoning wikipedia , lookup

Fuzzy logic wikipedia , lookup

Embodied language processing wikipedia , lookup

Expert system wikipedia , lookup

Unification (computer science) wikipedia , lookup

Logic programming wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
Artificial Intelligence
First-Order Logic
Inference in First-Order Logic
1
First-Order Logic: Better
choice for Wumpus World


Propositional logic represents facts
First-order logic gives us




Objects
Relations: how objects relate to each other
Properties: features of an object
Functions: output an object, given others
2
Syntax and Semantics

Propositional logic has the following:


Constant symbols: book, A, cs327
Predicate symbols: specify that a given
relation holds

Example:




Teacher(CS327sec1, Barb)
Teacher(CS327sec2, Barb)
“Teacher” is a predicate symbol
For a given set of constant symbols,
relation may or may not hold
3
Syntax and Semantics

Function Symbols


Variables



Refer to other symbols
x, y, a, b, etc.
In Prolog, capitalization is reverse:



FatherOf(Luke) = DarthVader
Variables are uppercase
Symbols are lower case
Prolog example ([user], ;)
4
Syntax and Semantics

Atomic Sentences



Father(Luke,DarthVader)
Siblings(SonOf(DarthVader),
DaughterOf(DarthVader))
Complex Sentences

and, or, not, implies, equivalence
Father( Luke, DarthVader )  Father( Leia , DarthVader )

Equality
( DaveAppleyard  DaveMusicant )
5
Universal Quantification
“For all, for every”: 
 Examples:
x Cat ( x)  Mammal( x)

x WeighsSameAs( x, Duck )  Witch( x)


Usually use  with 
Common mistake to use 
x At ( x, Carleton)  Smart ( x)
6
Existential Quantification

x HopeForUniverse( x)  ( x  Luke)



“There exists”:
Typically use  with 
Common mistake to use 
x At ( x, Carleton)  Smart ( x)

True if there is no one at Carleton!
7
Properties of quantifiers
x
x
x
y
x

y same as y x
y same as y x
y not the same as y x :
x FavoriteFood ( y, x)
y FavoriteFood ( y, x)
Can express each quantifier with the
other
x Likes( x, IceCream)
x Likes( x, Broccoli )
x Likes( x, IceCream)
x Likes( x, Broccoli )
8
Some examples
x MadeOfWood ( x)  Burns ( x)
x MadeOfWood ( x)  FloatsInWater( x)

Definition of sibling in terms of parent:
x, y Sibling ( x, y )  [( x  y )  m, f (m  f ) 
Parent (m, x)  Parent ( f , x)  Parent (m, y )  Parent ( f , y )]
9
First-Order Logic in Wumpus
World

Suppose an agent perceives a stench,
breeze, no glitter at time t = 5:



Percept([Stench,Breeze,None],5)
[Stench,Breeze,None] is a list
Then want to query for an appropriate
action. Find an a (ask the KB):
a Action(a,5) ?
10
Simplifying the percept and
deciding actions
b, g , t Percept ([ Stench, b, g ], t )  Stench(t )
s, g , t Percept ([ s, Breeze , g ], t )  Breeze (t )
s, b, t Percept ([ s, b, Glitter ], t )  AtGold (t )

Simple Reflex Agent
t AtGold (t )  Action(Grab, t )

Agent Keeping Track of the World
t AtGold (t )  Holding (Gold , t )  Action(Grab, t )
11
Using logic to deduce
properties

Define properties of locations:
l , t AtAgent(l , t )  Stench(t )  Smelly (l )
l , t AtAgent(l , t )  Breeze (t )  Breezy (l )

Diagnostic rule: infer cause from effect
y Breezy ( y )  x Pit ( x)  Adjacent( x, y )

Causal rule: infer effect from cause
x, y Pit ( x)  Adjacent( x, y )  Breezy ( y )

Neither is sufficient: causal rule doesn’t say if squares
far from pits can be breezy. Leads to definition:
y Breezy ( y )  x Pit ( x)  Adjacent( x, y )
12
Keeping track of the world is
important

Without keeping track of state...





Cannot head back home
Repeat same actions when end up back in
same place
Unable to avoid infinite loops
Do you leave, or keep searching for gold?
Want to manage time as well

Holding(Gold,Now) as opposed to just
Holding(Gold)
13
Situation Calculus

Adds time aspects to first-order logic
AtAgent([1,1], S0 )  AtAgent([1,2], S1 )
Result function connects actions to results
Result(For ward, S0 )  S1
Result(Tur n( Right ) , S1 )  S 2
14
Describing actions

Pick up the gold!
Stated with an effect axiom
s AtGold ( s)  Holding (Gold , Result (Grab, s))


When you pick up the gold, still have
the arrow!

Nonchanges: Stated with a frame axiom
s HaveArrow( s)  HaveArrow( Result (Grab, s))
15
Cleaner representation:
successor-state axiom

For each predicate (not action):

P is true afterwards means



An action made P true, OR
P true already and no action made P false
Holding the gold:
a, s Holding (Gold , Result(a, s )) 
(( a  Grab)  AtGold ( s )) 
( Holding (Gold , s )  (a  Release ))
(if there was such a thing as a release action – ignore that for our example)
16
Difficulties with first-order
logic

Frame problem



Qualification problem


Need for an elegant way to handle non-change
Solved by successor-state axioms
Under what circumstances is a given action
guaranteed to work? e.g. slippery gold
Ramification problem


What are secondary consequences of your
actions? e.g. also pick up dust on gold, wear and
tear on gloves, etc.
Would be better to infer these consequences, this
is hard
17
Keeping track of location

Direction (0, 90, 180, 270)
Orientation(S0 )  0

Define function for how orientation affects x,y
location
x, y LocationToward ([ x, y ],0)  [ x  1, y ]
x, y LocationToward ([ x, y ],90)  [ x, y  1]
x, y LocationToward ([ x, y ],180)  [ x  1, y ]
x, y LocationToward ([ x, y ], 270)  [ x, y  1]
18
Location cont...

Define location ahead:
l , s AtAgent(l , s ) 
LocationAhead ( s)  LocationToward (l , Orientatio n( s))

Define what actions do (assuming you know
where wall is):
l , d , p, s AtAgent(l , Result(a, s)) 
[ (a  Forward  l  LocationAhead ( s)  Wall (l ))
 ( AgentAt(l , s)  a  Forward )
19
Primitive goal based ideas

Once you have the gold, your goal is to get
back home
s Holding (Gold , s)  GoalLocation([1,1], s)

How to work out actions to achieve the goal?



Inference: Lots more axioms. Explodes.
Search: Best-first (or other) search. Need to
convert KB to operators
Planning: Special purpose reasoning systems
20
Some Prolog



Prolog is a logic programming language
Used for implementing logical
representations and for drawing
inference
We will do:



Some examples of Prolog for motivation
Generalized Modus Ponens, Unification,
Resolution
Wumpus World in Prolog
21
Inference in First-Order Logic

Need to add new logic rules above those in
Propositional Logic

Universal Elimination
x Likes( x, Semisonic )  Likes( Liz , Semisonic )

Existential Elimination
x Likes( x, Semisonic )  Likes( Person1, Semisonic )

(Person1 does not exist elsewhere in KB)
Existential Introduction
Likes(Glenn, Semisonic )  x Likes( x, Semisonic )
22
Example of inference rules





“It is illegal for students to copy music.”
“Joe is a student.”
“Every student copies music.”
Is Joe a criminal?
Knowledge Base:
x, y Student( x)  Music ( y )  Copies ( x, y )
 Criminal(x )
Student(Joe)
(1)
x y Student(x) Music(y)  Copies ( x, y )
(3)
( 2)
23
Example cont...
From : x y Student(x) Music(y)  Copies ( x, y )
y Student(Joe)  Music(y)  Copies ( Joe, y )
Universal Elimination
Existential Elimination
Student(Joe)  Music(Some Song)  Copies ( Joe, SomeSong )
Modus Ponens
Criminal(J oe)
24
How could we build an
inference engine?

Software system to try all inferences to
test for Criminal(Joe)

A very common behavior is to do:



And-Introduction
Universal Elimination
Modus Ponens
25
Example of this set of
inferences
4&5

Generalized Modus Ponens does this in one
shot
26
Substitution


A substitution s in a sentence binds variables
to particular values
Examples:
p  Student ( x)
s  {x / Cheryl}
ps  Student (Cheryl )
q  Student( x)  Lives( y )
s  {x / Christopher , y / Goodhue}
qs  Student (Christopher )  Lives(Goodhue)
27
Unification

A substitution s unifies sentences p and
q if ps = qs.
p
q
Knows(John,x)
Knows(John,Jane)
Knows(John,x)
Knows(y,Phil)
Knows(John,x)
Knows(y,Mother(y))
s
28
Unification
p
q
s
Knows(John,x)
Knows(John,Jane)
{x/Jane}
Knows(John,x)
Knows(y,Phil)
{x/Phil,y/John}
Knows(John,x)
Knows(y,Mother(y))
{y/John,
x/Mother(John)}

Use unification in drawing inferences: unify premises
of rule with known facts, then apply to conclusion


If we know q, and Knows(John,x)  Likes(John,x)
Conclude



Likes(John, Jane)
Likes(John, Phil)
Likes(John, Mother(John))
29
Generalized Modus Ponens

Two mechanisms for applying binding to
Generalized Modus Ponens


Forward chaining
Backward chaining
30
Forward chaining


Start with the data (facts) and draw
conclusions
When a new fact p is added to the KB:

For each rule such that p unifies with a
premise
 if the other premises are known
 add the conclusion to the KB and
continue chaining
31
Forward Chaining Example
32
Backward Chaining


Start with the query, and try to find facts to
support it
When a query q is asked:



If a matching fact q’ is known, return unifier
For each rule whose consequent q’ matches q
 attempt to prove each premise of the rule
by backward chaining
Prolog does backward chaining
33
Backward Chaining Example
34
Completeness in first-order
logic


A procedure is complete if and only if
every sentence a entailed by KB can be
derived using that procedure
Forward and backward chaining are
complete for Horn clause KBs, but not
in general
P1  P2    Pn  Q
Pi and Q are nonnegated atoms
35
Example
36
Resolution



Resolution is a complete inference procedure
for first order logic
Any sentence a entailed by KB can be derived
with resolution
Catch: proof procedure can run for an
unspecified amount of time



At any given moment, if proof is not done, don’t
know if infinitely looping or about to give an
answer
Cannot always prove that a sentence a is not
entailed by KB
First-order logic is semidecidable
37
Resolution
38
Resolution Inference Rule
39
Resolution Inference Rule

In order to use resolution, all sentences must
be in conjunctive normal form

bunch of sub-sentences connected by “and”
40
Converting to Conjunctive
Normal Form (briefly)
41
Example: Using Resolution to
solve problem
42
Sample Resolution Proof
43
What about Prolog?

Only Horn clause sentences





Negation as failure: not P is considered
proved if system fails to prove P
Backward chaining with depth-first search
Order of search is first to last, left to right
Built in predicates for arithmetic


semicolon (“or”) ok if equivalent to Horn clause
X is Y*Z+3
Depth-first search could result in infinite
looping
44
Theorem Provers

Theorem provers are different from
logic programming languages


Handle all first-order logic, not just Horn
clauses
Can write logic in any order, no control
issue
45
Sample theorem prover: Otter




Define facts (set of support)
Define usable axioms (basic background)
Define rules (rewrites or demodulators)
Heuristic function to control search



Sample heuristic: small and simple statements are
better
OTTER works by doing best first search
http://www-unix.mcs.anl.gov/AR/sobb/

Boolean algebras
46