Survey
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Guilt by Acquisition, Should today's stockholders pay the price of a corporation's past sins? By Steven E. Landsburg, Posted Friday, Jan. 8, 1999, at 12:30 AM PT When the German car maker Daimler-Benz announced plans to acquire a controlling share of Chrysler Corp., Jewish novelist Cynthia Ozick announced in the Wall Street Journal that she would never buy a Chrysler. Other Jews (some of whom would never buy a Chrysler because they'd only ever buy a Mercedes) saw the issue very differently. Last May, shortly after the merger was announced, the Jewish Bulletin carried an article by Natalie Weinstein surveying the range of opinion, particularly among Holocaust survivors. The responses ran the predictable gamut. Some agreed with Ozick. But others, such as Rabbi Ted Alexander, took their cues from Deuteronomy, which admonishes that "Fathers shall not be put to death for children, neither shall children be put to death for fathers." "Going by that verse of the Torah," said the rabbi, "I cannot blame this generation." The rabbi's analogy treats the Daimler-Benz of 1998 as the "child" of the Daimler-Benz that employed slave laborers in 1943. From a strictly legal perspective, the analogy is inaccurate: Under the law, a corporation lives forever. The entity that controls Chrysler is exactly the same entity that collaborated with the Nazis, not a descendant. But it would be wrong to view an essentially moral question from a strictly legal perspective. A corporation is not a moral entity; it's the corporation's flesh and blood owners who are moral entities. From that perspective, the rabbi's analogy fails in a different way: The current owners of Daimler-Benz are not, by and large, the children of previous owners from half a century ago. Stocks trade hands every day. That observation seems to strengthen Alexander's position. If we should not punish children for the sins of their fathers, then surely we should not punish children for the sins of their fathers' countrymen. But that analysis can be definitive only to those who believe that nothing can be added to the words of Deuteronomy; otherwise there's more to be said. When is it permissible to punish one person for the wrongs of another? The question is a tangle of moral and economic issues. Morally, we're concerned with things such as justice, fairness, and individual rights. Economically, we're concerned with creating good incentives. To see how uncomfortable it can be when economic and moral issues brush up against each other, consider the revision of accident law that's been proposed by the economist-iconoclast-law professor David Friedman. Friedman suggests that when two cars collide causing a total of, say, $10,000 worth of damage, everyone who was within a mile of the accident should be required to pay a fine of $10,000. That way, anyone who sees an accident about to happen will take all cost-justified measures to prevent it (perhaps by honking furiously to warn of impending danger). To my knowledge, Friedman's proposal has never struck anyone as fair, but at least it gets the incentives right. Or does it? My own view is that the Friedman plan fails even by its own strictly economic criteria, because it creates an incentive for people to avoid high-accident areas and take inefficiently long routes to wherever they're going--or to cancel their trips entirely. In principle, it could even increase the accident rate by scaring potential good Samaritans off the roads. Enforcement, of course, would be a nightmare. Those objections aside, Friedman's proposal does illustrate the tension between economic and moral considerations. And Friedman's innocent bystanders are at least partly analogous to Daimler-Benz's innocent stockholders. Let's keep those lessons in the back of our minds as we revisit the DaimlerChrysler controversy. Corporations can be punished for misdeeds in at least two ways. One is a consumer boycott and another is a (voluntary or involuntary) fine. Both kinds of punishment have been visited on Daimler-Benz (though arguably at levels that are small compared with the underlying offenses). In the 1980s, the corporation paid about $11 million to the descendants of its slave laborers. Who exactly suffers from those punishments? You might think the $11 million came from the pockets of those who owned Daimler-Benz stock in the 1980s, but that's not necessarily the case. Suppose, for the sake of argument, that in 1950 it becomes foreseeable that Daimler-Benz will eventually make reparations. Then every share of Daimler-Benz stock sold between 1950 and 1980 sells at a discount reflecting that expectation. Without the discount, nobody would buy the stock. So given sufficient foresight, the prospect of a 1980 punishment hurts the 1950 owners, even if they sell in the interim. And those who buy stocks after 1950 are not punished at all, because the discount compensates them for the fine. Therefore, if all companies are permanently on notice that bad behavior will eventually be punished, they have an incentive to behave well at all times. That's an outcome that seems both fair and economically efficient: The punishment falls on the sinners and thereby deters the sin. But here are two caveats: First, even if punishment is inevitable, it falls not on the owners at the time when the sin is committed, but on the owners at the time when the sin is discovered. After all, it's not till the discovery that the stock price falls. So punishing past corporate sins is not like fining everyone who was present when an accident occurred, but when it was reported, which seems both unfair and pointless. But this caveat has a countercaveat: The prospect of future punishments gives you an incentive to investigate the corporation's history before you buy, which improves the chance that bad behavior can be uncovered while the actual perpetrators can still be punished. Second, it's hard to maintain a consumer boycott, especially when the goal is to punish the past rather than to influence the future. Consumers can quite reasonably argue that history can't be changed and so is best forgotten. As a result, corporations have little to fear from boycotts unless consumers commit themselves to maintaining the boycotts even when they serve no purpose. It's hard to imagine how such commitments might be maintained, which suggests that fines are more effective than boycotts, especially if they are written into law rather than imposed on an ad hoc basis. If you're looking for a firm conclusion to all this, you'll have to look elsewhere; I hope I've at least illuminated some of the attendant moral and economic issues--though even these can become very different in situations that are superficially similar. (Click here for an example.) And punishing evil corporations is very different from punishing evil governments. In the first case, we punish stockholders who invested voluntarily, while in the second we punish taxpayers who might have bitterly opposed their government's policies. But that is a topic for another column. http://slate.msn.com/id/12950 Man, I Throw Like a Woman, The Supreme Court explores the subtleties of sex and basketball. By Dahlia Lithwick, Posted Tuesday, Nov. 30, 2004, at 3:35 PM PT Talk about taking one for the team. … Roderick Jackson bitched to his bosses about the second-class treatment accorded the girls' basketball team he coached at Ensley High School in Birmingham, Ala. Banished from the school's new gym, Jackson's team practiced in an unheated, rickety facility where its hoops literally drooped from age. When Jackson's bosses fired him, he filed suit under Title IX, a federal sex discrimination statute. The district court and then the 11th Circuit Court of Appeals rejected his claim that being fired for protesting gender discrimination itself constitutes an act of gender discrimination for which he was entitled to sue under Title IX. Title IX of the Education Amendments of 1972 bars gender discrimination in educational and other programs receiving federal funds and permits the government to stop funding entities engaging in sex discrimination. In a 1979 case, Cannon v. University of Chicago, the Supreme Court held that victims of sex discrimination also had a private right to sue under Title IX. The question for the Supreme Court today is whether Title IX additionally created a private cause of action for people who were fired for complaining about sex discrimination against others. The court will decide whether the statute covers whistle-blowers or just victims. Walter Dellinger (whom I know and edit) represents Jackson, and he argues this morning that it does no good to protect teenage athletes in a vacuum. "People like Coach Jackson need to come forward," he argues. "Students are minors, they don't know about budgets." Justice Antonin Scalia points out that the civil rights statutes that sought to protect against retaliatory firings "expressly provide for that." It's not logical to infer that Congress intended for the word "discrimination" to also include "retaliation" unless Congress explicitly said so. Dellinger responds that Title IX is identical to Title VI, which has long been understood to include retaliation in its definition of discrimination. Quoting the statute, Scalia says he can't see where Coach Jackson was "on the basis of sex … excluded from participation in … denied the benefits of, or … subjected to discrimination under any education program." He asks whether that "even remotely describes" Jackson's experience. Justice Anthony Kennedy notes that the '60s are so over: "This is not the heyday of private causes of action anymore." And Scalia objects to adding a new list of possible lawsuits to beleaguered school boards: "When the states signed on," he says, "they couldn't know this door to litigation was being opened to them." Dellinger counters that there is "no way that when the school districts accepted these [federal] funds, they thought they'd be free to retaliate." Justice Sandra Day O'Connor, who will likely be the deciding vote in this case, asks whether Jackson availed himself of the administrative remedy available to him under Title IX before trying to sue own his own behalf. David Souter rephrases that question as: "Why do we need a private cause of action and not just this administrative remedy? Is the administrative remedy too draconian?" The justices confirm that termination of federal funding for schools based on Title IX violations are rare. At which time Scalia points out that maybe Title IX works "because the sanctions are so draconian. No one in their right minds wouldn't rehire a coach" if faced with a withdrawal of federal funds. Irving Gornstein is an assistant to the solicitor general, and he argues for 10 minutes on Coach Jackson's side of the case. Many oral advocates have accidentally called Justice Ginsburg "O'Connor" over the years. Gornstein calls O'Connor "Justice Kennedy" this morning, thus proving that the two swing justices are merging inexorably into one great fungible Justice of Goo. Gornstein points out that in 1969 in Sullivan v. Little Hunting Park, the Supreme Court found that the statutory ban on racial discrimination encompassed retaliation and that Congress was well aware of the Sullivan rule when it passed Title IX in 1972. Scalia asks wryly, "Do you think we take the same approach to implied causes of action today that we took in 1969?" He rejects the idea that "we'd go skipping along forever as we did in 1969." Bong in one hand, bong in the other. … And O'Connor reminds him that "Mr. Jackson was not discriminated against because of his gender." Gornstein replies that any "person who is victimized by retaliation because he complained about sex discrimination is a victim of sex discrimination." The Birmingham Board of Education is represented by Kenneth Thomas, whose accent makes Dellinger's soft Carolina drawl sound Brooklynesque. Thomas opens with the claim that when there's a Title IX complaint, the Office for Civil Rights swoops in, and then there's hell to pay at school. "We know about OCR. They're in Atlanta, 167 miles away," he says. "And when they come, they come. …" Thomas goes on to argue that a private cause of action under Title IX offers no benefits to the team itself: "With a private suit, the award goes only to the coach," he says. "Nothing would go to benefit the girls' basketball team." Souter asks what Thomas makes of the fact that Title IX's administrative remedies are almost never deployed. How can it possibly be working? "On my watch," drawls Thomas, "the No. 1 priority is to keep OCR out." Souter persists. "Unless we allow whistle-blowers to bring a private right of action, this whole statute is a dead letter." Thomas replies that in Birmingham "we are very conscientious about the administration of our programs." " 'Trust me' is not an answer," snaps Ginsburg, "when you are telling a sixth-grader she can't play on a team." In perhaps the single greatest moment of the 2005 term, Justice Stephen Breyer then interrupts Thomas to inquire: "Can I ask you a legal question?" He goes on to offer a vintage Breyeresque three-part hypothetical, devoting at least five minutes to getting Thomas to concede that he must inevitably lose this case. To which Thomas finally responds with, "Justice Breyer, on the face of the statute, I just can't get there. I apologize." In response to a question from O'Connor, Thomas begins to cite a case that the Supreme Court declined to hear. O'Connor interrupts him: "You don't base your argument on giving some legal effect to a denial of certiorari?" she asks. And Ginsburg sums up Dellinger's side of the case again by urging that "[i]f we are talking about a sixthgrade soccer team, the only person who knows enough and is brave enough to complain is the teacher. … [I]f you cut the teacher out, forget it. [Title IX] is just nice words on paper." Thomas replies, "The teacher can call OCR." Ginsburg says, "And OCR says we're too busy." Scalia asks whether we know OCR is routinely too busy to intervene. Thomas says, "I have firsthand knowledge." Ginsburg snaps again, "Is that your personal testimony?" "Yes," says Thomas. Ginsburg then asks how many Title IX complaints he has fielded over the years. "Two," says Thomas. "In 20 years." Then he adds, "But they were all memorable." State Solicitor General Kevin Newsom gets 10 more minutes to speak in support of the Board of Education. He immediately sets out to correct the justices' assumption that "without a private right of action, whistle-blowers are left out in the cold." He urges that OCR has a lot of remedies beyond just yanking funding, and it's precisely this threat of yanking that can result in "individualized relief." He adds the "threat" of denying funds "is where the heavy lifting is done." This will be a close case, turning on whether the judges can know the unknowable: whether the vast sucking noise behind Title IX in this case is the result of its utter uselessness or its function as the perfect deterrent. Since the court can't precisely answer that question, it may be forced to answer the next best one: whether the only man truly able to stand up for womankind is always going to be a woman. http://www.slate.com/id/2110257/ How not to stifle a racist. The California Supreme Court may have been well-meaning when it banned racial slurs in a hostile workplace, but in the process it damaged the Bill of Rights. By Debra Dickerson Aug. 16, 1999 | If you happen to be an employer, a First Amendment absolutist or a trash-talking loser, life became a bit more difficult last week. That's because the California Supreme Court forbade the future use of racial slurs in a workplace that has already been found by a court to be a hostile environment and likely to remain so. While the decision is not binding outside of California, or on the federal courts, it is extremely significant nonetheless. Until now, a racist's worst nightmare was being penalized for his past behavior, but now he can be legally muzzled to prevent his invective from spewing forth in the first place. As early as 1991, Avis service agent John Lawrence allegedly began informing his Latino subordinates that they were "wetbacks," "motherfuckers" and "crooks" and routinely demeaning their English language skills, among his many other insults. Seventeen of them took Avis and Lawrence, who denies the allegations, to court. In 1995, a jury found in the workers' favor, awarding eight of them a total of $150,000 in damages. In addition, Judge Carlos Bea enjoined Lawrence (who still has his job) from engaging in further such speech, and enjoined Avis from allowing him to. Avis appealed its injunction, citing the First Amendment and both the U.S. and California constitutions' prohibitions against prior restraint on speech. The 4-3 decision last week, which generated five separate opinions (the plurality decision written by Chief Justice Ronald George, a separate, more radical concurrence and one from each of the dissenters), is controversial, to put it mildly. While courts have addressed the issue of workplace harassment many times and assessed damages after the fact, this is the first time one has taken the logical next step and enjoined the future use of offensive language. Legal experts say the decision is very narrowly tailored because it addresses only racial slurs, not religious proselytizing, sexual remarks or political statements. It also applies only after illegal employment discrimination (i.e. the existence of a hostile environment) has been found by a court of law. Narrow, shmarrow. When it comes to America, race and the Constitution, there's just no such thing as narrow. Emotions run so high, we're always either teetering on the abyss of tyranny or singing in a heavenly choir of angels, depending on your politics, and this case is no different. In her dissent, the court's most outspoken conservative, Justice Janice Rogers, blasted the decision: "A government that tells its citizens what they may say will soon be dictating what they may think." Amazingly, Rogers was joined in dissent by two stalwart liberal bedfellows, Justices Stanley Mosk and Joyce Kennard. Our hallowed freedom of speech has never been absolute. You can't yell "fire" in a crowded theater (although you may think it), solicit bribes, make terrorist threats, slander another, intentionally inflict emotional distress or be "obscene" (whatever that means). So, if speech has always been limited and the speech at issue is not constitutionally protected (because the plaintiffs are not free to walk away), why is this such a big deal? After all, as Justice George wrote, "The order simply precluded defendants from continuing their unlawful activity." Well, one reason it's a big deal is that the unlawful activity likely only seems easy to identify and outlaw. The state Supreme Court upheld the Court of Appeals requirement that Judge Bea promulgate a list of the proscribed words that Lawrence may not utter. This is ludicrous. What if Bea forgets one? Is it "spic" or "spick"? Lawrence could easily coin nonsense words to convey his contempt for Hispanics, speak with a Jose Jimenez accent, refuse to address them directly or get a buddy to say the words for him. Maybe he is just smart and evil enough to switch from harassing "wetbacks" to the "gooks" or "kikes." If so, it could take another five years of court proceedings to stifle the bum. Also, the fact that the court deemed Lawrence's bailiwick a hostile environment a few years ago doesn't mean it must always be so. Avis could install cameras and tape recorders to keep Lawrence honest. Given the turnover in minimum wage operations like rental car counters and the publicity attendant upon this case, it's entirely possible that the atmosphere could radically change at Avis with a few new hires. Justice Mosk wrote, "Like my colleagues, I abhor discrimination in any form. But I feel equally strongly that we cannot use the instrumentality of the courts to penalize speech before we know what was said, to whom, and with what effect." Kennard elaborates on the over-broad nature of the ruling, writing that it would outlaw "every utterance of a racial or ethnic insult in the workplace, not just utterances that actually produce a hostile work environment." Isolated slurs do not a hostile environment make. So if that environment is the source of the illegality and the basis for the injunction, then it is highly relevant that it might no longer exist. Silly as it is to have a learned jurist drawing up his own George Carlinesque list of dirty words that may not be uttered, and dangerous as chipping away at the First Amendment is, it's still a touching gesture. Reading the voluminous, much-footnoted decision, I'm struck once again by how hard we struggle to find solutions to our racial conundrums in this country -- affirmative action, busing, minority scholarships, constant litigation and legislation, suburban white boys talking like homeboys. We should be proud of ourselves. But we should also be realistic. Sometimes, there just isn't a litigated, legislated, law-based answer to our problems. Sometimes, we just have to stand by, helpless and frustrated, while someone like John Lawrence or Buford Furrow takes advantage of the freedoms that are so wasted on people like them. If the Constitution, and especially the Bill of Rights, is to mean anything, then sometimes, we just have to suppress the urge to implement solutions that may be even worse than the problems they are meant to address. Instead, here's a radical suggestion: What if the plaintiffs in the Avis case are encouraged to simply laugh in Lawrence's face every time he says something offensive? The last time someone called me a nigger, he did so with such a look of vicious triumph on his face -- as if he expected me to melt right into the pavement at the power of that evil word -- that I couldn't help myself: I laughed. "What, I'm not a 'bitch' too?" I found myself quipping. All of a sudden, I thought the idiot was going to cry. He was the one who felt crushed. Avis workers, listen up: If John Lawrence acts like an amoeba, treat him like one. Certainly, there's a real difference between being a powerless manual laborer working at a crap job who also has to listen to slurs from his boss all day and being a Joe Cool journalist called a name by a homeless beggar I stiffed, but the bottom line is the same. Once you've done all you can do (like win a mega-lawsuit) you just have to accept that you've done all you can do. If Lawrence doesn't stop and Avis doesn't fire him, then the plaintiffs either have to refile their lawsuit, quit or turn the other cheek. Laws are made for honest people, my mother always told me, and idiots have the same consitutional protections as the rest of us. We probably can't stop the haters from hating, but even if there are ways to stop the John Lawrences and the Buford Furrows, undermining the Constitution shouldn't be one of them. salon.com | Aug. 16, 1999 http://archive.salon.com/news/feature/1999/08/16/california/ The Jordan Effect: What's race got to do with it? THE COLORBLIND WORLD DEPICTED BY MADISON AVENUE ISN'T OUR RACIAL REALITY YET -BUT IT'S A STEP IN THE RIGHT DIRECTION. BY LEON E. WYNTER | For African-Americans, "black" has always been an absolute adjective: Like "pregnant" or "dead," there's no such thing as a little bit. Expressions such as, "I ain't gotta do nothing but be black and die," phrases that begin, "As long as you black ..." confirm black folks' awareness that the racial attitudes behind the "one drop" rule laid down in the 19th century by the Supreme Court are as immutable and eternal as the biblical creation. Since the 17th century, it has seemed that white people must hold black people firmly at arm's length for the world to keep on turning. Then enter, as he was exiting two weeks ago, Michael Jordan's legacy to American culture: the "Jordan Effect." The expression was coined in Fortune magazine last summer, when it estimated the economic impact of the basketball star's persona(s) to be $10 billion over his 14-year career. In the recent gush of appreciation over his Airness, Jordan's race was conspicuously absent, except as a footnote to the "Jordan Effect." As the editor of one upcoming Jordan book said on National Public Radio, before Jordan, "There was a line between black athletes and entertainers and corporate America; Jordan has erased that line." Say what? Isn't that the same indelible "color line" that Justice Taney drew in Plessy vs. Ferguson? The line that was looped around so many black necks for even looking at a white woman in the Jim Crow South? The line that W.E.B. DuBois recognized and immortalized in the 1950s and Derrick Bell told us to embrace and get on with our lives in the '90s? I think you can knock black America over with a feather every time it hears that the color line has gone away because non-blacks don't see Michael Jordan or Oprah Winfrey as black. White people, who presumably think this colorblindness is a good thing, seem unaware that a great many black folks are unconvinced, if not insulted, by such white pronouncements, safely uttered from living rooms in their white neighborhoods. Indeed, the most striking feature of race relations as we enter our fifth century together is the widening schism between race as it is depicted in commercial popular culture and race in sociopolitical reality. When I, a 6-foot-7 black man with a slight resemblance to his Airness, enter the car of a commuter train to the suburbs on a Friday evening, I feel some momentary stares that seem to ask, "Hey, we're not on the subway anymore -- what's he doing here?" Yet most of the passengers will go home and spend the weekend immersed in commercial media that aggressively reflects the browning of America. They'll watch television dramas whose census of lead characters, according to a recent Screen Actors Guild report, is disproportionately black. Or they will soak up professional team sports whose rosters are overwhelmingly non-white. Or they will catch their favorite trash TV talk shows, featuring a multiracial mudfest where race recedes before more important issues like "just when did you stop sleeping with your sister?" In between watching black or Hispanic detectives track down the bad guys, the suburbanites will be motivated to excess consumption by a burgeoning cast of non-whites in commercials. In Madison Avenue's world, white people will cheerfully let a black man push them out of an airplane just to catch up with a diet cola. Besides names like Jordan, Bill Cosby, Shaquille O'Neal and Vanessa Williams, commercials are increasingly filled with non-white non-celebrities, whose presence as Everyman in general market commercials was rare to unheard of as recently as 1990. And what's up with that mob of third world extras that have suddenly become fixtures in campaigns for high-tech firms like Cisco Systems, Lotus and IBM? The very people suburbanites are loathe to see on their train are pouring out in their living rooms to scare them into compliance with the digital world order with a simple haunting question: "Are you ready?" The answer, to the bigger question of whether society has really erased the color line, is "no, not yet." There is a disconnect between the multi-hued American dream portrayed in the media and America's stillblanched social reality. Whites have not begun to examine the hypocrisy that may lie beneath their colorblindness toward a Michael Jordan. But African-Americans, too, aren't prepared for the possibility that where commercial popular culture goes, social and political culture must follow. In their new book, "By The Color of Our Skin: The Illusion of Integration and the Reality of Race" (Dutton), Leonard Steinhorn and Barbara Diggs-Brown argue that today's "virtually integrated" television "merely enables whites to live in a world with blacks without having to do so in fact ... a form of safe intimacy without any of the risks." As a columnist who writes about such things, I've had endless debates with people of all colors who agree with the authors that the racial utopia depicted in commercial media is meaningless. It's true that the rainbow world promised by advertising isn't here yet. But virtual integration is still leading us toward actual integration. Virtual integration may be risk-free intimacy, but it's still intimacy. Virtual integration is exploding because it sells -- and it sells because it fortifies our deep-seated aspirations to live in a truly race-neutral society, against the fears that have kept us from achieving that society. If those aspirations didn't predate corporate media's decision to bankroll the browning of the commercial mainstream, all the advertisements in the world couldn't make white parents accept Shaquille O'Neal or Brandy as role models for their children. I believe Madison Avenue does know what it's doing. It's moving product by telling us who we are. It tells us we're comfortable with the black people who inhabit television's fantasy of the American good life. That white people are afraid of this reality in the streets is not Madison Avenue's problem or responsibility; that's what politicians are for. The transracial corporate media agenda does create a rising dissonance between the rainbow dreams of commercial culture and the harsher social reality -- but that gap can be closed, at least in part, by new leaders willing to exploit our hopes for a multiracial world instead of our fears. Think about it: Who could you see hanging out with Mike in a post-retirement Nike commercial, Bill Clinton or Pat Buchanan? Does Americans' embrace of the slogan "be like Mike" mean white people want to be black? No, and it probably never will. But by saying they don't see Jordan as black, whites may really mean they see him as human -- and that is still an unalloyed good. To identify with Jordan, whites have had to unpack many pieces of racial baggage -- the chocolate skin, the black diction, the fear, the sexual taboo -- and then pack them up again when the game ends. With every unpacking, they compare the objects of his blackness with the elements of their own whiteness, and then minimize the differences enough to hang on his every move. My theory? The more they pack and unpack, the more items are taken out of the closet and left on the table where, in time, they're easy to toss out. White folks may still be nervous around minorities in their commuter car. But as America votes with its dollars to narrow its racial differences, the distance between the American dream and the American reality is closing. SALON | Jan. 29, 1999 http://archive.salon.com/money/feature/1999/01/29feature.html Name Games, The folly in the attempts to define "African-American." By Richard Thompson Ford, Posted Thursday, Sept. 16, 2004, at 3:21 AM PT Among the many indignities racial minorities must endure are the perennial debates over the meaning of racial identity. Are the people formerly known as "Negroes" or "colored people" to be called people of color, black, Afro-American, or African-American? Are people of Mexican and Central-American ancestry Hispanic, Latino, Chicano, or Latin-American? Is it still OK to call people "Oriental," or is that a term best limited to rugs and geographic locations? More urgent than the nomenclature itself are the questions about who "counts" as a member of these groups, with their ever-increasing string of aliases. A recent version of this controversy involves immigrants from Africa or the Caribbean and whether they are "African-Americans." Harvard professors have publicly worried that over half of Harvard's "black" students did not descend from American slaves but are, rather, immigrants or the children of immigrants from Africa or the Caribbean. Though it started off on the right track, this debate predictably became as much about the "identity" of these immigrants as the direction of Harvard's admissions policies. Meanwhile Republican Alan Keyes complained that the Democratic Party's rising star, Barack Obama— the son of a Kenyan immigrant—"[wrongly] claims an African-American heritage." In reaction to which UC-Berkeley linguist John McWhorter quite reasonably pointed out that immigrants from, well, Africa, who are now residents of the United States of America, have a stronger claim to the term "African-American" than most American blacks, whose connection to Africa is generations old. Others worried that defining "African-American" as rooted in geographic origin seems to suggest that Teresa Heinz Kerry, born in Mozambique, and Charlize Theron, born in South Africa, are "African-American." The nation anxiously awaits the answers to these urgent social questions. It shouldn't. Arguments about the correct definition of racial identity are this century's version of medieval scholastic theologians' debates about how many angels can dance on the head of a pin. They seem to be of vital moral and spiritual importance, involving many contested terms, conceptual puzzles, and facts not in evidence. They're a great way for smart people to pass the time until the bartender pours the next round. But there's no way to resolve these questions or even to agree on common grounds for debating them. Do we even need official definitions of racial identity to apply antidiscrimination laws or race-conscious policies? Actually, no. Antidiscrimination law prohibits decisions driven by suspect motivations. What matters is the intent of the decision-maker—not the racial identity of those affected by the decision. An employer who discriminates against an employee based on a mistaken belief about that employee's ancestry is just as liable for discriminating as if he had been correct. In some instances the plaintiff in a discrimination suit must nevertheless establish that she is a member of a protected racial group—raising the possibility that formal racial definitions actually matter. But it's telling that neither Congress nor the courts have ever established official membership criteria. Instead, courts successfully rely on uncontested social conventions in most cases, and when those social conventions fail, the identity of the plaintiff as a member of a protected group is determined by the courts on a caseby-case basis. We frequently rely on self-reporting to establish racial identity as well. The U.S. Census Bureau, for instance, has long abandoned any attempt to assign individuals to a racial group based on objective criteria—relying exclusively on the self-identification of individuals. The same is true for affirmative-action purposes—the obvious subtext of the Harvard controversy. Although it would seem that institutions must first agree on a definition of racial identity to administer such race-based policies, they needn't and haven't. Like the Census Bureau, those universities that consider the race of applicants rely largely on self-reporting. Of course, a university might rescind the admission of a student who made an obviously disingenuous claim to an underrepresented racial group, just as it could with respect to a student who claimed to be from an unrepresented region of the nation but in fact had only visited there on vacation. But universities need not and do not apply specific objective criteria to racial identification. As such, in the Harvard controversy the real question was never who is or isn't "African-American." The real issue is the narrower—and more answerable—question of whether African and Caribbean immigrants and their children—whatever their "race"—should enjoy affirmative-action preferences. There are real dilemmas here, but they simply don't involve the correct definition of "African-American." They involve the correct rationale for affirmative action. So, let's consider three rationales commonly advanced: 1) A selective university might want a system of affirmative action to educate the future leaders of discrete, established communities. "African-Americans" are a large, established, and fairly discrete community. Here the question is whether immigrant blacks have become or are likely to become plausible future leaders of that community—are they similar to native-born blacks for purposes of community leadership? 2) A university might believe that racial discrimination is an important social issue that merits academic study and want to be sure that some people who have experienced that discrimination are represented in its student body. (Sandra Day O' Connor's opinion in Grutter v. Bollinger—the recent Michigan affirmativeaction case—endorses such a rationale: "By virtue of our Nation's Struggle with racial inequality, [minority] students are both likely to have experiences of particular importance to the Law School's mission and are less likely to be admitted in meaningful numbers on criteria that ignore those experiences." [Emphasis added.]) Here we'd want to ask whether immigrant blacks are likely to have experienced the same or similar types of discrimination as native blacks. 3) A university might believe that racial discrimination has depressed the grades and standardized test scores of black applicants and wish to correct for this bias in the available data. (O'Connor's Grutter opinion also suggests this rationale: The quotation above indicates that minority students "are less likely to be admitted in meaningful numbers" because of "our Nation's Struggle with racial inequality.") Here, we'd want to know whether discrimination has had a similar adverse effect on the performance of the immigrants as on native-born blacks. None of these questions are answered or even clarified by any abstract definition of "African-American." And conversely, the answer to the affirmative-action question may not be relevant in other contexts in which race is at issue. For instance, suppose you decided that immigrant blacks don't count as AfricanAmerican (of course I'd discourage you from putting it this way) for affirmative-action purposes. You could arrive at this conclusion—under rationale No. 3 above—based on a belief that whereas high-school grades and standardized-test scores typically underpredict the potential of native-born blacks, they are an accurate predictor of the potential of immigrant blacks. That position would still not commit you to agreeing with Alan Keyes that Barack Obama—the child of an African immigrant—is not AfricanAmerican. It would be perfectly consistent to say that although Obama doesn't qualify for affirmativeaction preferences, you consider him "African-American" in the context of his candidacy for the U.S. Senate. Here, the real question is whether Obama's experience as someone whose appearance will have exposed him to his share of antiblack racism (regardless of his cultural or ancestral heritage) is likely to make him more sympathetic to the political concerns of others victims of racism. Frequently, the words "African-American" are just shorthand for such a presumption. Arguing about who qualifies for a racial label is not only unnecessary, it also flirts with perils best left in the past. For instance, while Harvard's controversy focused primarily on immigrant blacks, to a lesser extent it called into question the identity of the children of interracial couples. Such an inquiry threatens to revive—under a new rationale—the odious 19th-century ideas of "blood quantum" and racial purity. Perhaps what's most unfortunate about these pointless debates about the meaning of racial identity is their sloppy and volatile mix of the personal and the political. For instance, Keyes (channeling the spirit of liberal multiculturalism to perfection) emotes: "My ancestors toiled in slavery in this country. ... My consciousness, who I am as a person, has been shaped by my struggle, deeply emotional and deeply painful, with the reality of that heritage." This might be a moving first sentence in an autobiography, or an important revelation to one's psychotherapist, but in the context of national politics, who cares? Subjective accounts of personal identity are at best distractions from more tangible and objective issues of racial injustice—such as employment discrimination, residential segregation, and an often racially biased criminal justice system. At its worst, the narcissism of identity politics threatens to mire the struggle for racial justice in intractable conceptual debates and ineffectual emotionalism. The correct definition of racial identities seems important to a lot of smart people. But that doesn't make it at all important in fact. Maybe if we argued about it long enough, we could all agree on an omnibus definition of racial identities. And maybe there are angels, they do dance on the heads on pins, and if we thought about it long enough, we could figure out how many could crowd on before one would topple off the edge. Because nothing whatsoever depends on the answer to the latter inquiry, we've all quite reasonably stopped caring. I expect the angels will forgive us. And soon enough the nation's blacks, whites, Latinos, Chicanos, Hispanics, Asian-Americans, Orientals, Negroes, colored people, and AfricanAmericans will thank us, if we stop caring about the terminology and definition of races and get on with the important work of fighting racism. http://www.slate.com/id/2106753 Black and white and read all over One graduate student discovers that skin color sometimes matters more than cogent argument. By Steven Pyrrho ---------June 04, 1999 | "I 'd never date an Asian. I just don't like my own people," Joy said, smirking mischievously. "Well, I would never date a white person," Regan responded in dead earnest. It was before our graduate seminar on English Renaissance literature that Joy and Regan, both Korean-American classmates of mine, began chatting about race and relationships. "Just to make sure no accidents happen," I put in sarcastically. "You could each administer blood tests to your prospective partners to ensure racial purity." There's no reason I should have known better, but now of course I wish I had. It was the beginning of my first year of graduate school at UC-Berkeley's English Department, a program known for pumping out scholars who are as well-versed in the litany of anti-colonial political correctness as the rhyme schemes of Chaucer. As green and eager graduate students, we all took (and, yes, still take) the finer points of racially tinged rhetoric very seriously. So I was surprised to hear such racial essentialism uttered by two of the department's young disciples, and I took it upon myself to point out their mistake. Now, with more irrational discussions about race under my belt than I care to admit, it's obvious that I was stepping into the trap that I've since tried mightily to avoid. Because even though people in graduate humanities programs seem to be thinking very subtly about gender and race, too often identities are dressed up as ideas. Even when people assiduously think through their positions, their skin color or sexual proclivity sometimes trumps their intellect. "You should think about what you said about blood tests," Regan chided me after class. "Race isn't about genes, it's socially constructed, it's about power relations." "Of course it is!" I exclaimed. "But you made the categorical statement about whites!" "And it's the white power relation that I don't want to be a part of," she said. I didn't ask her how she, who had gone to Harvard, was engaged to a medical student and seemed to carry a different handbag every day, imagined herself to be on the innocent end of the "hegemony." In some ways, she seemed to be a smart, fiercely intellectual young scholar, who, like all of us there toiling with nary a job prospect, had decided to devote her life to thinking about meaning, virtue and the grave implications that language can take on. I wanted to give her the benefit of my doubt and simply pursue the argument without dismissing her. "But if this power relation co-varies so exactly with white genes that you can call it the 'white power relation,'" I protested, "then it sounds like you're assuming that genes are almost the blueprint for social construction, which is the opposite of what you're asserting." She berated me and all white people for regarding race merely academically, for thinking that it can be accessed and debated just like any other subject. I confessed I had never taken a course on race and that I found academic writings on race as repugnant as academic writings on literature. "So you presume to talk about race when you haven't even deigned to study it -- you probably haven't even read one book by Cornell West!" Her argument that it was typical of white people either to study or not to study race seemed to have all the bases covered. I got a little defensive. "If being racist has anything to do with how one feels about, thinks about and treats others," I replied hotly, "then I am not racist and nothing I have said suggests that I am." "Clearly," she said, her eyes flashing with impatience, "your conceptions of race are very outdated, and this conversation is pointless because it would take too long even to get to the point at which you could understand the necessary terms. And I didn't even have to say as much as I have to you -- I could just have written you off like the other students in the department." This stopped me in my tracks. Regan informed me that various comments I had made inside and outside of classes had given me a reputation as being "reactionary" and "complacent on the subject of race." So there it was. Behind all the arguments we perennially engage in -- about racial iniquity or poverty or sexual orientation -- this possibility always looms. Through the hurled abstractions, we learn that we're unpopular. Ivory towers disintegrate to sandboxes in an instant. But for me this only tautens my determination to make the conversation about our ideas, not our identities. What had I done to alienate my classmates -- to make many people think, as she told me, that I didn't belong in the department -- when for so many years I had worked so hard to arrive? In a class, I had suggested that even in "Othello," not every line is about race, and that to think so is as monomaniacal as it would be to think that the play is not about race at all. On another, even more infamous occasion, I had complained about something my Chinese housemate was always cooking, which I was never able to identify, not because I disdained to ask but because we can't speak each other's languages. Whatever it was stunk terribly to me -- to me, not to the objective nose or to the radical nose, just my nose. Is a nose subject to ideology? If so, what's behind my loathing of my stepfather's sauerkraut? "They're not going to actually do anything," she reassured me about my classmates, "but let me put it this way: They won't go out of their way to make you feel comfortable." There were no African-Americans in the class on "Othello," nor were there any Chinese present to hear me slander their cuisine, if indeed that is what I had done. So it must have been on the behalf of these groups that my mostly white classmates who were listening were so scandalized. At my "Othello" comment, a student gasped. To the Chinese cooking complaint, a student, while rolling his head back, said slowly and deliberately, "Ouch!" "You are participating in an ideology that makes Western European-ness the model for what it means to be American," Regan said about my Chinese cooking comment. Trying to avoid a no I'm not-yes you are trap and curious to know what she really believed, I ventured. "But don't all cultures believe to some extent that they are superior to others?" "No, not like whites." "What about earlier this century when Japan invaded Korea and occupied it for 30 years?" "The Japanese didn't think they were superior, they just needed the resources. You obviously know very little about history." "This is why I haven't taken a class about race," I fumed. "I have heard too many statements like yours which employ double standards in interpreting history." "Did it ever occur to you," she asked, "that such discourse against whites might be so prevalent because it is true?" "Sure, to the extent to which the mere fact of a thing's happening legitimizes it." My most obvious fault in these arguments is my tendency to assume a position of absolute critique, and at moments like these I realize that no matter how sharply I seem to myself to be thinking, beneath is a juvenile impulse to prove people wrong. In this instance, I lapsed into full satire. "Is slavery right? Well, let's see, is it happening? I guess you'd be pleased to see history come to a complacent halt, since whatever is, is right!" "How much more deeply do I have to watch you dig yourself in?" she asked. She grimaced. Suddenly, there was nothing more important than showing her that I wasn't the schoolyard bully she'd painted me to be. "If there's something I'm ignorant of about race," I pleaded earnestly, "whether a fact or a way of thinking, and if you're genuinely committed to promoting greater understanding, then please try to explain it to me." "It's not my responsibility to educate you, and I can see that our classmates are right about you," she said. I could have tried to explain myself again -- that my comments about race were in fact anti-racist if anything and my comments about food, were well, about food, but I didn't. Instead, I surrendered to my fear of being excluded. I played my identity trump card. I told her about my sister who is half AfricanAmerican, half Vietnamese, and my half-Latino, half Native-American brother. I told her how my parents adopted them before I was born. I told her that I was born into a family where racial difference is just an everyday fact of life, not something to be afraid of. But more importantly, I cried -- so that she could see my multicultural, albeit invisible, identity shining through me. "I'm glad we had this conversation," Regan said, at last relaxing. "I'm very glad." My Oprah-esque confessional meant something to her, and she responded with something like forgiveness for my seeming like an average, white, middle-class, neo-liberal bigot. But I felt as though I had just failed an exam more important than any Ph.D. orals, and I couldn't forgive myself. http://dir.salon.com/books/it/1999/06/04/race_argument/index.html?pn=1 Can a Dog Be Racist? The case of the prejudiced pit bull. By Clara Jeffery Posted Wednesday, Feb. 26, 2003, at 8:06 AM PT To be an American is to receive a continuing education on race. But one does not, perhaps, expect to receive lessons from a dog. Then along came Percy, a young pit bull friends of mine found in Brooklyn's Fort Greene park last summer. The couple had little dog experience between them, but Percy appeared at that point in a relationship when increasingly large gestures of commitment are required (the engagement would come five months later), and he was taken in on a probationary basis. He proved to be sweet-tempered, if excitable, goofy and energetic, easily house-trained. In balance, a lot of fun. There's just one problem: Percy is a racist. His prejudice was revealed in dribs and drabs. The first clue came a week after his adoption when, while on a Brooklyn beach, he eyeballed and growled at two fishermen a hundred yards away. They approached, lugging buckets of fish, and he began ferociously barking and lunging. As the men gingerly passed by, we could see that they were Hispanic. A lone incident would have been dismissed, but Percy targeted my thenboyfriend—also Hispanic—for similar treatment. And he was prone to lashing out at black men, too. Teased for taking in a racist dog, my friends—who are white—initially objected. He was a good dog, a sweet dog, people are already biased against pit bulls, don't call him a racist. Not all men of color were targeted, they pointed out. And indeed, the odds seemed to increase if the man was carrying bags or luggage, or if his clothes were particularly baggy. But as Percy now resided just off a main shopping district, and in the heart of hip-hopping Fort Greene, these distinctions provided little solace. Most dog owners and people of color will admit (bashfully or forcefully, depending) that dog racism exists. Many non-pet-owners (and Cartesians) will sniff disdainfully. Racism requires malice aforethought, they'll say. Dogs can't think, therefore they can't be racist. Nonsense, says Dr. Nicholas Dodman, a professor at Tufts University School of Veterinary Medicine and author of several books on animal behavior, most recently If Only They Could Speak. "Any behavioralist knows that dogs don't like subsets of people," he says, and though the most common subsets are broad—strange men or little children—"sometimes it can be quite specific. It could be tall men, or men with beards. It might be men who are wearing big shoes, might be as subtle as men who smoke cigarettes—which can be hard to pick up on—but it can also be black guys." Dogs can be trained to discriminate. Some Jamaican resorts feature dogs that chase blacks off the beach while leaving white frat boys to fry like bacon. South Africa's apartheid government bred "Boerbuls" by crossing Rottweilers, Dobermans, bloodhounds, German shepherds, and even wolves to create very aggressive dogs for its security services. In the 1980s, the Herstigte Nasionale Party advertised such animals as "racist watchdogs" created "especially for South African circumstances." In his 1982 film White Dog, director Sam Fuller explores the socialization of racism by having a black man attempt to retrain a dog taught to kill blacks—a so-called white dog—only to have the dog attack whites instead. Paramount found the film disturbing enough to block its release for more than a decade. Barring human intent, however, what turns an otherwise sweet dog like Percy into a bigot? Typically, such behavior indicates that the dog was not exposed to the people it now targets during its developmentally "sensitive time"—weeks 3 through 12—when its understanding of the world was formed. "If you take a dog who has never encountered a black man, or someone who has a funny walk, who uses a walker, or has a gimp or a limp, and he sees the first one in his life when he's six months old. … it's going to be a shock," says Dodman. "He's going to think 'Jinx! That's pretty strange! What the heck is that!' They might hide—that's the more fearful type of dog. But if they're a little bit macho"—known in the trade as "fear aggressive"—"they might try and go for it, to try and drive it away. And it's because they're unfamiliar." But even if unfamiliarity breeds contempt, how does this explain Percy? Whatever the circumstances of his early life, being abandoned in Fort Greene indicated that he was, if not raised by, at least exposed to people of color. In such a case, a dog probably has had a bad experience at the hands (or feet) of those it doesn't like. This does not necessarily incriminate Percy's previous owner. In The Dog Who Loved Too Much, Dodman profiles a dog who developed a mysterious hatred of white-bearded men late in life. Eventually Dodman determined that the owner's white-bearded ex-boyfriend, left alone with the dog just once, was the likely culprit. "A dog's memory is like a photographic plate," Dodman says, "whatever happened, it just took a snapshot of that person and logged it in its long-term memory as 'bad'." (In the same vein, dogs can develop an aversion to certain breeds, sizes, and colors of other dogs.) Extreme trauma can even cause a dog to exhibit the symptoms of post-traumatic stress disorder. Whether it's bad experience or lack of experience that turns a dog into a racial profiler, the habit is hard to break. If the dog barks and the person recoils, the dog registers a victory. (Such "positive" reinforcement goes a long way to explain dogs' fixation on mailmen: He comes, I bark, he leaves.) And even if the person doesn't recoil or show fear visible to the human eye, the dog's sharp eye and sharper nose can sense fear in a tiny gesture or a whiff of sweat. And given the Percys out there, maybe people of color are more likely to be afraid of dogs. According to a national Purina poll, people of color account for less than 15 percent of all dog owners in this country. Historically, dogs have been used to suppress blacks, and those who now live in inner-city neighborhoods must contend with the Rotts and pits gangbangers use to instill "respect." Unfamiliarity fortified by bad experiences could generate a disproportionate number of fearful responses. Apprehension on the human's side and ignorance on the dog's can lead to a didactic encounter that reinforces prejudice and fear on both sides. The personality of the owner can make matters even worse. Dodman recently completed a large study of the personality profiles of owners whose dogs are fear aggressive and—no surprise—the owners tend to be somewhat fearful and awkward themselves. "If you are nervous around people, the lead becomes a telephone line going straight to the dog," he says. "As you tense up on the lead, the dog will pick up on the tension. He might glance at you and see the expression on your face and then he is keyed and ready to go. Cocked and loaded." Add race to the equation, and the potential for ugliness deepens. If a white owner is apprehensive about say, blacks, the dog could manifest that apprehension, which could encourage blacks who encounter that aggressive canine to fear dogs and dislike their white owners. Even owners like my friends, who I'll posit didn't come into the situation with prejudice, now find themselves tightening the leash or crossing the street when they see someone Percy is prone to bark at coming their way. And while they do this to avoid a bad situation, it could reinforce the very qualities they wish their dog didn't possess. It is possible to mitigate such behavior, through a sort of doggie diversity training, whereby the pet is gradually exposed to what sets it off. But it can be hard to persuade your black or white-bearded friends to participate in such cultural immersion exercises. (My friends had serendipitously hired a black trainer for Percy, whose behavior has since improved.) And even careful training can never totally eliminate the possibility that a trigger too similar to the traumatic event could cause the dog to lash out. Some will argue that what dogs display is not racism, but something more akin to cause-and-effect conditioning. Really, though, is there a difference? Consider that many people become prejudiced by being raised in a very insular way, in their own enclave of whites or Hispanics or blacks, largely ignorant of people who are different. Humans, too, fear the unfamiliar and use a bad experience or two to tar a whole class of people. The difference between dogs and people is that people are supposed to be smart enough to recognize the logical fallacy of such a reaction and a dog is, well, just a dog. http://www.slate.com/id/2079214 The Bestiality Perplex Timothy Noah Posted Monday, April 2, 2001, at 2:23 PM PT Chatterbox has been brooding all weekend about what his policy should be regarding bestiality. It hasn't come up before, partly because Chatterbox doesn't own any pets, and partly because he wasn't aware that bestiality had become a political issue until he read an outraged March 30 editorial on the subject in the Wall Street Journal. As a matter of personal preference, Chatterbox would characterize himself as a heterosexual speciesist (and happily married man). But what are Chatterbox's views concerning interspecies congress among others? Perhaps we should back up a bit. The Journal's ire was directed at an essay titled "Heavy Petting" by Peter Singer on the highbrow porn Webzine Nerve. Singer is, of course, the notorious bioethicist whose Princeton appointment three years ago caused a mild ruckus because of his hard-line views about animal rights. (It was Singer who coined the term "speciesist.") In the Nerve essay, which is actually a review of a new book about bestiality called Dearest Pet, Singer argues that the taboo against bestiality should be dispensed with. The foundation for Singer's argument is the Aristotelian view that man is part of nature, as opposed to the Platonic view that man exists apart from nature. (A chunk of Al Gore's sophomoric ecotome, Earth in the Balance, is dedicated to criticizing the Platonic worldview and embracing the Aristotelian one, a stance that Lynne Cheney attacked rather unfairly in her plodding anti-politicalcorrectness jeremiad, Telling the Truth. Had Singer's Nerve essay surfaced before the November election, Gore's Aristotelianism might have tempted the Journal's high-spirited partisans to declare Gore the animal fanciers' fellow traveler. Though, as Chatterbox has written before, Gore toward the end of the campaign attempted a bold raid on the Platonist camp.) In Singer's philosophical construct, zoophilia is just another, slightly less conventional way for humans to assert fellowship with the rest of God's creatures: There are many ways in which we cannot help behaving just as animals do--or mammals, anyway--and sex is one of the most obvious ones. We copulate, as they do. They have penises and vaginas, as we do, and the fact that the vagina of a calf can be sexually satisfying to a man shows how similar these organs are. The taboo on sex with animals may, as I have already suggested, have originated as part of a broader rejection of nonreproductive sex. But the vehemence with which this prohibition continues to be held, its persistence while other non-reproductive sexual acts have become acceptable, suggests that there is another powerful force at work: our desire to differentiate ourselves, erotically and in every other way, from animals. To Singer, then, you're a bigot if you'll accept a Great Dane into your home but draw the line at letting your sister marry one. As with other sexual taboos, Singer argues, the one against bestiality has been violated regularly down through the ages: [Dearest Pet author Midas] Dekkers, a Dutch biologist and popular naturalist, has assembled a substantial body of evidence to show that humans have often thought of "love for animals" in ways that go beyond a pat and a hug, or a proper concern for the welfare of members of other species. His book has a wide range of illustrations, going back to a Swedish rock drawing from the Bronze Age of a man [engaged in sexual congress with] a large quadruped of indeterminate species. There is a Greek vase from 520 BC showing a male figure having sex with a stag; a seventeenth-century Indian miniature of a deer mounting a woman; an eighteenth-century European engraving of an ecstatic nun coupling with a donkey, while other nuns look on, smiling; a nineteenthcentury Persian painting of a soldier, also with a donkey; and, from the same period, a Japanese drawing of a woman enveloped by a giant octopus who appears to be. ... Oh, never mind about the octopus. Singer concedes that few of these art works likely depict events that actually occurred, but he adds that in the 1940s, 8 percent of males and 3.5 percent of females reported at least one interspecies tryst to Dr. Alfred Kinsey, and that among men living in rural areas, it was more like 50 percent. In fact, subsequent surveys have found much lower percentages, leading one to suspect that Kinsey was demonstrating a bias having something to do with his training as a zoologist. (Click here to read a debunking of various bestiality urban legends.) Singer is clearly right that any sexual taboo based on the idea that sex exists solely for reproduction doesn't make much practical sense, even for the boring heterosexual mainstream, in this age of contraception. But Chatterbox can't join Singer in concluding that the sexual revolution should give bestiality a free pass. Singer is so focused on trying to persuade his readers that people are no better than animals that he forgets to take into account the welfare of the animal. The Journal editorial describes Singer's essay as arguing that "the only real issues are whether you get the animal's consent--and you don't kill it as part of your pleasure." In fact, though Singer does denounce sexual practices that involve outright cruelty, he doesn't really explain how an animal can go about giving consent because, well, you know, animals can't talk. Sure, a dog humping your leg may be conveying a certain message, but without the kind of verbal confirmation required these days by every college freshman manual ("no means no"), how can you be certain? Moreover, it isn't immediately obvious that even if an animal could tell you its intimate desires that this would constitute informed consent, any more than would a "yes" from a homo sapiens under the age of 18. But wait, you say. Who cares whether an animal gives its consent or is the moral equivalent of jailbait? It's not a person; it's just a dumb animal. Who cares what an animal thinks? But this, of course, is not only an invitation to all kinds of animal cruelty, but also a contradiction to Singer's core belief that animals and humans should be valued the same. Singer's tolerance for bestiality is therefore not only repulsive and weird. It's also ... speciesist! http://www.slate.com/id/1007408 Frank Admissions. The Supreme Court finally talks seriously about race. By Dahlia Lithwick, Posted Tuesday, April 1, 2003, at 6:23 PM PT Several of the links in this piece launch audio clips from Tuesday's oral arguments. If this kind of wanton openness and transparency on the part of the Supreme Court continues, I'll be out of a job. But the court's decision to permit live audio broadcasts of today's oral argument in two affirmative action cases from Michigan has welcomed the entire nation into the courtroom for only the second time in history. (Bush v. Gore was the first.) I urge you to help put me out of a job by listening to the broadcast on C-SPAN, reading the transcripts on the Detroit Free Press (click here for the second argument), and generally experiencing that infrequent, warm fuzzy glow that can be achieved only through participatory democracy. Argument in the two cases, Grutter v. Bollinger and Gratz & Hamacher v. Bollinger, takes place over two consecutive hours this morning. Both suits were filed by rejected white applicants to University of Michigan schools. Grutter is a challenge to the affirmative action policy at the law school, and Gratz involves the policy at the undergraduate school. A divided 6th Circuit Court of Appeals upheld the law school policy as constitutionally permissible and never quite got around to deciding the undergraduate case. The undergraduate case is the tougher one since their admission policy automatically awards 20 points (out of a possible 150) to applicants who are black, Hispanic, or American-Indian while the law school uses a less formal "critical mass" test to admit what it deems a racially diverse class each year. One of the most striking aspects of today's arguments was how very untechnical and legalistic the discussion actually was. Constitutional law professors expecting the court to turn the emotional and moral issues into theoretical nitpicking over the appropriate level of constitutional scrutiny or the legal significance of Justice Lewis Powell's inscrutable opinion in that last major university affirmative action case—Bakke v. Regents of University of California—would have been disappointed. The court showed less interest in arcane three-part tests than in fundamental fairness questions: How can racial equality be imposed on the backs of whites? Is there any race-neutral policy that could adequately address the problem of racial disparity in this country? Are we supposed to allow racial preferences to continue indefinitely? How can we fix our racial problems without taking race into account? Every one of the justices proved today that the court is neither out of touch nor inclined to hide behind jargon; their discussion was closer to the one you're having around your dinner table tonight. While some of the oral advocates seemed surprised at the twists and turns of the argument, the morning proved—in more than one way—that this court is capable of "getting it" when it really matters. First, in Grutter, Kirk Kolbo argues for Barbara Grutter, the white applicant refused entry to Michigan Law School despite a 3.8 GPA and an LSAT score in the 86th percentile. Not surprisingly, Kolbo engages in a skirmish almost immediately with Sandra Day O'Connor—widely viewed as the swing vote in these cases—when she asks how a school with a very limited number of spots can make hard choices about admissions and not use race as a relevant factor. Kolbo—opposing any race-conscious decision-making at all—replies that other factors don't violate the 14th Amendment's guarantee to equal protection under the law for all races. O'Connor points out that "the Supreme Court has upheld using race in certain contexts ... you're speaking in absolutes, and it isn't like that." Justice Ruth Bader Ginsburg then stages what can only be characterized as a hijacking by amicus, invoking a green friend-of-the-court brief filed on behalf of retired military officers stating that (as paraphrased by Ginsburg) "to have an officer corps that includes minority members in any number, there is no way to do it other than to give ... a plus for race." When Kolbo says he cannot take that contention as a matter of fact, Justice David Souter almost loses his mind: "Are you serious that you think there is a serious question about that? That we cannot take that green brief as a representation of fact?" The court goes on to argue about the factual accuracy, relevance, and implications of gutting affirmative action in military academies, none of which sounds like a very good idea in wartime. Justice Stephen Breyer jumps in to make his first of two pitches for upholding affirmative action based not on Powell's "diversity" rationale but on the need for minority leadership. Listen to this piece of real-world eloquence. Kolbo argues that the 14th Amendment's equal protection clause isn't violated by the sorts of minority recruiting undertaken by military academies but is violated by Michigan's alleged quota system. Solicitor General Ted Olson then takes a few minutes to condemn the Michigan plan. As a result of the weird split-the-difference approach taken by the Bush administration, he has to both attack the Michigan approach and defend efforts to promote racial equality in the abstract. Again he has to fend off an assault from the military amicus brief (now being cited as "the Carter Phillips brief," if you please), and he sounds greener than the brief by the end of it. When asked by Ginsburg whether he accepts that the military academies all have race-preference programs, his response is that the Coast Guard does not. Here is where Olson describes the Michigan plan as a "thinly disguised quota" (Tomorrow's headlines today!) and makes the nice point that Michigan is wrongly "using stereotypes in an effort ... to break down stereotypes; they're using race as a surrogate for experience." O'Connor then telegraphs her views on the force of the Powell decision in Bakke by stating bluntly that "I don't think it commanded a court." Or that Powell's "diversity" rationale is simply not the holding in Bakke. This makes it easy for a majority of the court, if they want, to ignore Bakke and cook themselves up a new batch of affirmative action law. Maureen Mahoney, representing Michigan Law School, battles Chief Justice William H. Rehnquist over whether the law school's policy is merely a quota system. Setting aside a fixed number of seats would constitute a quota, she says, but the annual variation in minority acceptance and enrollment suggests that their "critical mass" plan does not. Here Justice Antonin Scalia makes the point he'll make several times today: Michigan's problem is of its own creation. "If Michigan really cares about that racial imbalance, why doesn't it do as many other state law schools do, lower the standards and not have a flagship elite law school." Scalia proceeds to get incredibly annoyed with Mahoney when she refuses to give him a fixed number (i.e., "quota") of how many minority students would represent a "critical mass" or "sufficient number" of minority students at Michigan. "Is 2 percent a critical mass? ... OK, 4 percent? ... You have to pick some number don't you? ... Like 8? Is it 8 percent??" O'Connor reveals her own biggest concern in these cases when she asks whether there is any end to the program or whether the racial preferences will continue indefinitely. And Justice John Paul Stevens inquires whether affirmative action doesn't just engender more racial hostility in the long run. Mahoney replies that the overwhelming number of students at Harvard and Michigan still support it, and Scalia informs her that this is because "they're in already." If she wants to see racial resentment, ask high-school seniors. Finally, and with two minutes left to her argument, Scalia asks Mahoney the following "question" (that's really a lecture), and, amid much laughter, Chief Justice William Rehnquist gives her permission to treat it as a statement. Gratz, the second case, proceeds along similar lines as Grutter, except the undergrad policy, with its points system, smells somewhat fishier. John Payton—who subs in for Mahoney in the university's defense—is a little more inclined toward flowery rhetoric about the wonders of educational diversity. Kolbo, arguing again for the rejected white applicants, tussles with the justices for a while over whether one of the plaintiffs in the suit even has standing to sue. But mostly he argues that affirmative action policies give administrators too much discretion to decide what constitutes a minority, who is a minority, and what makes for a diverse student body. Stevens and Breyer point out that such a lack of standards may be upsetting, but it's not, according to Breyer, "constitutionally relevant." And Ginsburg notes the importance of this case: It would affect private schools as much as public ones. Ted Olson has a slightly easier time in this round, mostly because he's not up against the dreaded "green" brief. He argues that affirmative action simply perpetuates stigma, and when Souter says that the point of affirmative action is to have enough minorities in a class to show that "there is no correlation between race and points of view," Olson argues that it's nuts to give minorities preferences to prove that minorities don't have monolithic views. John Payton speaks finally for the university. He makes a long, moving speech about how outrageously segregated the city of Detroit and state of Michigan are and how only campus encounters between students can undo this damage. He scuffles with Rehnquist about how many students exactly make up a "critical mass," and Kennedy basically puts his vote on the table with the comment that this program looks like a "disguised quota." After more discussion about what exact number constitutes an amorphous "critical mass" and more on why Michigan can't just lower its high standards, Justice Clarence Thomas rocks the house by asking a question: "Do you think that your admissions standards overall at least provide some headwind to the efforts that you're taking about?" (It's a trick! If Payton says it's working, it's unconstitutional; if he says it's not, then it's irrelevant.) Payton doesn't get the chance to answer properly before his time runs out. The case is submitted until a decision comes out in June. For what it's worth, and to the extent it's all going to come down to O'Connor, she doesn't sound like a woman willing to completely do away with using race as at least a factor in admissions decisions. In fact, even Kennedy sounds like he might still be on the fence himself, at least as far as a sweeping decimation of all race-conscious policies is concerned. All this makes for a long morning of head-scratching. Everyone seems to agree that the racial divisions in this country are a terrible problem, and almost everyone agrees that they need to be handled via subterfuge: The affirmative action camp is for "critical masses" that look like quotas and for "diversity" that may not bring about diversity. The anti-affirmative action camp is for pretending that other remedies work when it's clear that you can't fix race problems by ignoring race. These are not really legal questions at heart; they are almost insoluble social and moral ones. Take heart in the fact that the court at least respected us enough today to address them as such. http://www.slate.com/id/2080999 A "poison" divides us, The man who has made it a personal mission to destroy affirmative action one state at a time explains why the policy is so damaging. By Alicia Montgomery ---------March 27, 2000 | Depending on who you talk to, University of California Regent Ward Connerly is either a crusader for a color-blind society, or an Uncle Tom serving as a front man for racist whites. He authored California's Proposition 209, which did away with affirmative action programs in government and higher education, and repeated this triumph two years later in Washington state. With the rallying cry "two down and 48 to go," Connerly has moved on to Florida. In the Sunshine State, Connerly's mission has proved to be problematic for Republicans, particularly Gov. Jeb Bush. Like his "compassionate conservative" brother George W., Jeb once enjoyed as friendly a relationship with the minority community in his state as any Republican governor could hope for. But that good feeling is now being undermined by Connerly's campaign. Connerly, however, believes that affirmative action is the real poison ruining relationships between blacks and whites. So he is trying to undo it one state at a time. In an interview with Salon, he defends his initiative, and his new book, "Creating Equal." What led you to write this book? I started [it] five years ago just as an act of frustration when I was bringing this issue up as a regent. One of my colleagues attributed my beliefs to some sort of political ambition, you know, that I was preparing to run for office in California. That certainly was not the case. I've found that it is very difficult for black people to let go of what I believe is a crutch. No matter how much you can demonstrate that affirmative action is touching a very few people, there are those who believe that their lives will be over without it, and that all that they've accomplished is a result of their being "affirmative action babies." So I wanted to show that I, for example, who grew up with modest means, am rather typical of a lot of black people, many of whom in prior generations had nine, 10, 11, 12, 13 kids in the family. The husband dies or leaves the house, the wife still raises the children and they end up leading productive lives because of very strong families. Yet there's this myth that we're all dysfunctional. [I also wanted] to get the nation to start confronting the broader issues of race: interracial marriages, what does it mean to be called a minority, and affirmative action as opposed to preferences, and the issue of profiling. I wanted to reveal my own experiences in the context of all those issues, and to suggest to the nation that we need to start rethinking this concept of race, and to get beyond it. What is the difference between affirmative action and preferences? In my view, using the powers of government to make sure that people are not discriminated against, I think that was the original intent of affirmative action. I think that is legitimate. Making sure that people know about job opportunities by advertising in different newspapers, even going to a Cinco de Mayo fair and letting people know that jobs are available or that public works contracts are being let. Using affirmative action to -- as we're doing at the University of California -- in a non race-based way to provide outreach to under-performing schools. Those things are affirmative action. But when it gets to the point where you are making a selection for someone to be admitted to the university or someone to be hired for a job, and to have one standard for someone who is black and another standard for someone who is white ... I think that's a preference. And I think that those things are wrong, and those things are being applied in many government arenas for the purpose or rationale of trying to level the playing field, trying to achieve diversity. [B]ut I think that when you apply different standards to people, that's discriminatory, no matter what you want to call it. If, as you say, affirmative action touches a very few people's lives, why do you feel it's so important to roll it back? I think it's poisonous. I think it poisons the relationships between people based on their groups and based on the perception that some are being left behind because of it. I can't tell you the number of people who are white and male who say that "I would've been here except for affirmative action." There's no evidence of that, but there's that perception in their minds. And perception becomes reality. It poisons relationships and builds resentment, often needlessly. It also marginalizes people, if you are female or you are black or you are Latino. Asians somehow largely escape this stigmatization possibly because of the stereotype that Asians are better performers academically. But those of us who are in that group called "minority and women," if we are performing in any role that is not seen as being a traditional role, the impression is that we did not get that by reason of our own accomplishment. We got that because of somebody giving it to us, because of affirmative action. The same kind of talk you describe from white men comes from some in the black community who say "I could've gotten that job if it weren't for 'the man.'" How would these perceptions go away just by eliminating affirmative action? I think that both groups are blaming something else. There is discrimination, but I think a lot of black people invoke racism in a chicken-little sort of fashion. They overstate it. On the other hand, a lot of whites blame affirmative action for something that had nothing to with it. They lost a job because somebody better got it. But as long as you have this paradigm where people seem to be using race and gender as a means of making hiring decisions, as long as they keep uttering this mindless blather about "we've got to achieve diversity," it kind of taints the whole process. And the decisions that they're making would be no different, in my view, if they just discarded the whole system. If you argue that eliminating affirmative action helps create a true meritocracy, what about cases like George W. Bush who got into Harvard and Yale with a C average? If it's in the private sector, I don't necessarily like it, but I don't care what happens [there]. But when it comes to government, one's connections should not play a role. That's precisely why I offered a resolution successfully [at the University of California] to eliminate these "legacy admits," the preferences that we were giving to the sons and daughters of U.C. alums, as well as what I call the fat-cat preferences, in which a certain number of seats were assigned to the chancellor that he or she could fill solely on the basis of who picked up the phone and called the chancellor. At Berkeley, we gave one to the son of a king. The argument was, well, this will really help diversity. Baloney. It wouldn't help diversity. It probably rewarded the U.S. senator who called and asked for that favor. It's the public sector I've been addressing. I haven't been directing attention to the private sector. I'm talking about government, and how government treats its citizens. In your book, you say that encounters with helpful whites helped shape your opinions about racial preferences. Do you see how a black person with different types of experiences might reach another conclusion about affirmative action? Absolutely. I've never discounted the experiences of somebody else. We are creatures of our own experience. We begin early in life to form attitudes about other people based on our own experiences. What I am saying is that my experience refutes the notion that you can only learn from people who look like you, and that America is not racist at its core. There are bigots; there are racists. They come in all colors, believe me. But America is not a racist society. [But] I can't tell you the number of campuses that I've been to where I meet bright black kids who say "America is racist". How do you get to an institution like Harvard or Yale without encountering the helping hands of people who are white or Asian or Latino? What about the attitude you encounter from the political left, the kind of patronizing racism of a liberal who assumes that race will always be this intractable problem? The whole debate about college admissions really is more a class argument, in my view, than a race argument. Because we have the largest share of people, who are low and moderate income for the most part, supporting the higher education of a small number of people, especially at the select institutions. That's why the whole debate about who gets into Berkeley, I think, is a very misleading one. If we really wanted to help black people -- let's just take black people for an example -- we would not be putting so much emphasis on getting them into Berkeley as we would giving them the equivalent money to go out and buy their own cabs, or get the tools to become an electrician or a plumber, or the money to take a vocational course. Because the overwhelming majority of people, regardless of their color, are not going to go to college. But we are so preoccupied with the concept of making sure we get X number of black kids into Berkeley that we totally overlook the masses. It costs $12,000 a year to subsidize sending a student to the University of California. It takes three taxpayers to pay that $12,000 in California. If we said we think it's important that every person get a start in life -- I'm not proposing this, but I'm saying it as a way to clear our thinking a little bit -- every person in life deserves something to jump-start them into being productive. And if we're going to spend $48,000 to $60,000 to educate somebody at the University of California, let's say we're going to give you effectively a line of credit of $25,000 to use however you want to pursue you're dream of becoming productive. If you want to be an electrician and you need to take two years of electrical engineering at a vocational school, OK. We're going to finance that. But we don't even look at that. If I proposed that, they'd think I was a kook, because we're so hung up on the notion that you either go to college or life's a failure. And if you don't get into Berkeley and you're black, there must be some institutional racism there. Don't you ever feel that some of your political allies are using the anti-affirmative action initiative to mask their hostility to any forms of minority outreach? Sure, there are those. They are very small in number, but I've seen them. There are people who I talk to who, as I listen to them, that I come away thinking, "I don't like this person's motives." I'm in the unique position of being kind of like the filling of a sandwich. I get to talk to those and interact with those who agree with me, who are fellow quote conservatives, and I also interact with those who hate my guts. I'm kind of caught in the middle, because I don't want to end all affirmative action, and I think the record proves that with my support of the outreach programs that we're doing big time in California. But at the same time, I think that preferences are bad and wrong and that they do exist. There are agencies that started out with the best of intentions of simply eradicating discrimination. They then did not accomplish their objective, and so they ratcheted it up a little more, and then they started imposing goals and timetables. They still don't get their objectives, and so they ratcheted it up a little more, and say, "Manager, if you don't meet your goals, you won't get your merit pay increase," making those goals the functional equivalent of quotas. Why did you choose Florida for your next initiative? I think Florida is a state with the same elements of diversity as California, an urban state, a Southern state with a large black presence. And I believe that this problem of race in America will only be solved when black people come to the conclusion that the time is right. Whites are largely afraid to force the issue, and black people, many of them, many of us, feel kind of caught back in the '60s. Many people don't really trust whites. In Florida, one thing that comes up is "Well, it might be a better plan than what we have now, but we shouldn't have to trust you." So I thought of all those things plus the fact that it was going to be a hotly contested state in the presidential race. The effect of having it happen in the fourth largest state with all those other factors that I mentioned is tremendous. What's the next state on your list? We've been looking at Michigan, Oregon, Colorado. A lot depends on what happens with Florida's Supreme Court on our initiative. And what's the prognosis in Florida? It could go either way. I'm optimistic. I can't see how in the world they can say that this doesn't represent discrimination. In California, in Washington, in the Civil Rights Act of 1964, the language is almost identical. And if everybody else can come to that conclusion, then why wouldn't the Florida Supreme Court come to that conclusion. But it is an activist court. It's a court that really doesn't want this on the ballot. The whole establishment there doesn't want it on the ballot. So it could go either way. In your book, you mention some unpleasantness that transpired between you and Vice President Al Gore during a White House meeting. The encounter was a distasteful one. Gore made the statement that "we are all prone to bigotry," and that "there is evil that lies coiled in the human soul." And I said that this is truly frightening. The premise of being a democracy, of being a free people, is that we're basically good people. And that doesn't mean that we're all good or that we're going to do good things all the time, but I think that the premise is that we are good people, and that we don't need our government to keep us from ourselves. President Clinton, I think is genuinely a good person [who] genuinely likes people, and that seeps out of every pore of the man. But Vice President Gore, when he shook my hand, he kind of crushed it. Typically, public officials, since they shake hands so much -- and I'm now doing this a lot -- you learn not to overuse your hand. The first thing that you're told is firm, not loose wrist, but firm. But don't overdo it because you end up sending out the wrong signals, and you end up having your hand get weary. This man literally crushed my hand. And I came away from that with the impression that he is a hateful man, and nothing that has happened since then has softened that impression. When he goes to black churches [he] talks about those who want a color-blind society having their blinders on. He went to Washington, he went to Florida and singled me out. He said, "Florida doesn't need Ward Connerly here," and he gets really personal in his attacks. And I've seen that ever since that meeting in the way he approaches this issue. It's not just that he disagrees with you, he wants to hammer you into the ground and cut you off at the knees, it seems to me. And I just have the impression that he's just a hateful man. http://dir.salon.com/politics2000/feature/2000/03/27/connerly/index.html Why gays shouldn't serve There really is a valid military argument against military inclusion, but the forces of political correctness won't allow it to be heard. By David Horowitz ---------June 25, 2001 | Political correctness is a doctrine widely presumed dead. An object of ridicule that no one defends these days outside the margins of the ideological left. Yet my recent tour of college campuses under the necessary armed protection of campus security guards suggests that it is obviously alive and well -- and itself protected -- in certain regions of the political culture. A sure sign of p.c. thinking is when the other side of a controversial subject is successfully identified as forbidden territory. To cross the invisible boundary that embargoes a politically incorrect view renders one's motives immediately suspect. To argue the position is a sign of one's indecency. It is to mark the holder of the position as a bad person, a relic of the reactionary past, an obstacle on the path to human progress. This was the object of the campaign of vilification I encountered when I suggested that reparations for an injury committed 136 years ago and payable on the basis of skin color instead of injury was "a bad idea and racist too." For the heresy of opposing the left on an issue it considered a political litmus, I was accused of expressing ideas that were "offensive," and then tarred and feathered as a bonehead "racist." The attacks weren't limited to me; they were also directed at the journalistic institutions that printed my ad in the interest of free speech. My Salon colleague Joan Walsh accurately described these attacks as "political correctness run amok. Yet they were also lent credence and support by pundits who generally opposed political correctness like Jonathan Alter, Clarence Page and the Washington Post's Richard Cohen. This is a sure sign that the tenets of political correctness are still very much alive and well. An interesting case of this was recently provided by my good and courageous friend Andrew Sullivan in a column that appeared in the New York Times Magazine. In it, Sullivan addressed the subject of gays in the military in a way that I found morally persuasive and poignant on the one hand, but politically correct and obtuse on the other. His column was titled "They Also Served," and it asked for "some ... recognition in today's war nostalgia of the role that gay men have played in the past in defending their country." In the film "Pearl Harbor," for example "Cuba Gooding Jr. played the brave segregated Negro, fighting back for his country." In "Saving Private Ryan," "the sensibilities of the '90s were projected backward. We didn't see just soldiers; we saw a Jewish American soldier, an Italian, a WASP and so on." Actually, Sullivan is wrong on that count. This wasn't the sensibility of the '90s. It was the same sensibility I saw as a kid in the 1940s when World War II films invariably featured the identical rainbow and, in features like "Home of the Brave," included black soldiers and was accompanied by a powerful anti-discrimination theme. This is the part of Sullivan's argument I can wholeheartedly embrace -- and I believe a majority of Americans do, too. When a socially conservative president appoints an openly gay man to an administration post, it is a sign that things have really changed. But the recognition of gays who served the country was not Sullivan's main agenda in his New York Times Magazine essay. Having established the point that we should, but do not, acknowledge the service that gay men have performed for this country, he wants to use it as a wedge for the argument that the armed services should abandon their "Don't ask, don't tell" policy and embrace a gay presence in their ranks. Sullivan calls this goal a "diverse military" and wonders why "we seem to be going in reverse." It is at this point that Sullivan's argument abruptly incorporates the telltale syntax of political correctness. His opponents are reactionaries, prejudiced against "diversity" -- i.e., gays. The assumption is that no serious rationale other than lingering social prejudice exists for current military policy. Opposing it requires no military argument, while defending it is a sign of failure to fully qualify for the ranks of the decent and humane. As Sullivan presents the case, no other possibility exists. Sullivan's argument, however, is counterintuitive. Of all social institutions, the military is the most pragmatic. Its task, brutal in its simplicity, is to develop the most efficient killing machine that money can buy and intelligence can devise. This singularity of purpose creates a paradoxical result. The military is indeed retrograde in some of its aspects. (It's not a democratic institution, for example.) On the other hand, it is more progressive in others. Precisely because the military's overriding purpose is to win wars, free black fighting units were incorporated into its ranks more than a century ago, at a time when slavery was still legal. Less well known is the fact that free black troops and military support units were part of the Confederate war effort as well. For almost a century after that, black soldiers were still segregated and confined to subordinate roles. But in 1947 the military was integrated. That was seven years before the Supreme Court integrated the nation's schools and 18 years before progress in the political realm made it possible to end segregation in the South. (All this military progress was made notwithstanding the fact the military culture is largely a Southern culture.) In short, because of its pragmatic focus, the military -- rigid in other areas -- in this crucial terrain of social conflict has shown itself to be historically more flexible, progressive and ready to adapt than the democratic political process itself. Then what is the military's problem with including gays, other than prejudice? It is a sign of the force of political correctness in our culture that there is probably not one among a hundred readers of these words who could answer that question. Because of the embargo that political correctness puts on even considering the arguments of the other side, the conventional "wisdom" is that an institution that pioneered integration is run by individuals -- many of whom are themselves minorities -- who are more prejudiced against gays than they were against blacks. And by 100 years! Is this an argument that any self-respecting pundit -- in other circumstances -- would even want to be associated with? Yet it is precisely the argument that all proponents of including gays in the military currently make. For all such advocates, including my friend Sullivan, the "don't ask, don't tell" policy is just a hypocritical attempt to appease lingering social prejudice. That's the voice of political correctness. In fact, there is a military argument against the inclusion of gays in combat, which has nothing to do with social prejudice. It may or may not be a sound argument. I am not a military expert, and any opinion I have about the armed forces is necessarily based on intuition rather than experience. I certainly am open to counter arguments. It's just that nobody on the inclusion side is offering any. Sullivan's argument in the Times article is more interesting than most in that it credits the Army with having important agendas that are worthy of respect. He observes that the current policy of "don't ask, don't tell" creates a standing loophole for anyone who wants to leave the service. This is bad for the military, and an argument for changing the policy. That's well and good, but hardly persuasive for a service that relies on volunteers. To make a credible argument for changing the policy, Andrew and others will have to address the military rationale for the policy itself. "Don't ask, don't tell" is a way of containing the destructive force of sex on a combat capability called "unit cohesion." To create the perfect killing machine, the military works hard to drain recruits of their individuality and their self-interested desires in order to make them think like cogs in a machine. An essential part of the military mind is that the members of fighting units don't think for themselves but do as they are told. They work as a unit in which each performs an appointed task. The mission objective -- not personal consideration -- guides their actions. Suppose a commander were faced with the choice of risking his unit or risking the life of his own son, for example. Suppose the life of his son were threatened, but to save him would risk the military objective his superiors had set. Suppose he let the human override the imperatives of the machine. He would be doing what was natural, but the military objective he sacrificed might cost the lives of hundreds or thousands. To avoid such breaches of military discipline, military policy does not allow family members to fight in the same unit. The same principle underlies its policy towards gays. Sacrifice of unit cohesion and military order is the threat that sex between soldiers poses for any combat force. The open inclusion of gays in the military is regarded by military men who oppose it a threat to effectiveness of the military as a fighting force. This has nothing to do with the individual fighting capability of gay males. It is about unit cohesion. It's about making every soldier a cog in a machine whose larger purpose he cannot understand, but he is bound to serve. Suppose two men in a five-man unit are sexual partners. What will that do to the cohesiveness and effectiveness of the fighting unit? What impact will it have on its ability to carry out its mission? These are the questions that led to the ban on gays in the military and then to the subsequent "don't ask, don't tell" policy. Because once you are able to tell -- and stay -- then there is no containing the sexual problem. As a comeback, some may be tempted to ask: What about the fact that women now serve in combat units? Far from taking care of the problem, this comparison only underscores the dangers in letting politicians treat the military as a social experiment. In one sense, of course, we don't really know the magnitude of the threat since we haven't been in a ground war since women were allowed in combat roles. (And there may, indeed, be a connection between the two.) But we do know that every military that has attempted to place women in combat positions -- the Israelis, the Germans and the Russians provide three examples -- has abandoned the practice, because of its negative impact on unit cohesion. (In part, because men will instinctively sacrifice their tactical missions to protect the women.) We do know that since women have been included in these roles, requirements and standards have been dramatically lowered, and along with them morale -- a crucial, if immeasurable, element of military success. Moreover, we know that once the politically correct foot is in the door, the possibility of reasserting pragmatic controls becomes ever more remote. The same "progressive" intolerance that forced the original issue will prevent any rational assessment of the result. The admission of women into the American military was not a military decision but a political act. The Presidential Commission on the Assignment of Women in the Armed Forces, which was created during Bush père's administration, recommended against putting women in combat positions. The Clinton administration ignored the recommendation and slipped the new policy into place without a public discussion or congressional debate. During the Gulf War, women in the armed services failed to report to combat duty at rates many multiples that of men. When you don't show up for your combat assignment you are effectively sabotaging existing battle plans. On one ship, the Aurora, 10 percent of the women en route to the war zone got pregnant. The military looked the other way. None was courtmartialed for cowardice or dereliction of duty. In other words, under the force of political correctness, the military has surrendered to the fact that it will be a less effective fighting machine. The integration of women in the military and in combat forces is a politically created debacle that has already weakened America's defenses. The open inclusion of gays in the military could have an even more damaging effect, with unknown consequences for untold lives. If proponents of gay inclusion want to make their case persuasively, they need to make it not on the battlefields of political correctness, but here in the real world. http://dir.salon.com/news/col/horo/2001/06/25/gays/index.html We're here, we're queer, I'm sick of it The gay pride agenda is about partying, not politics. It's time to talk about "gay equality." By Christopher Ott ---------June 30, 1999 | Gay pride month is finally over, after a big weekend of partying and parades in New York, San Francisco, Chicago and other cities around the world. Millions of people commemorated the Stonewall rebellion, the shot-heard-'round-the-world brawl in 1969 that catalyzed a movement. We got together and restated positions on everything from hate-crimes to gay marriage, and if dykes on bikes, feather boas and shirtless gym boys are any measure, a good time was had by all. In the midst of this good-natured celebration of Stonewall, however, a reappraisal of the pride strategy is beginning to emerge. After three decades, the politics of pride is beginning to look a little stale and out of step with the times, and it is becoming clear to both gay people and our straight allies that we need to take a new step forward. With June's pride celebrations over, that step is to ask what the politics of pride has left undone, and why. Gay pride has been an enormous success. It's increasingly safe to come out, we've won passage of a few gay-rights laws and it's becoming politically expedient (at least for Democrats) to support us. But there have been setbacks. Anti-gay legislation like the 1996 Defense of Marriage Act is the law of the land. Brutal hate crimes like the murder of Matthew Shepard are reminders of what can still happen to any gay person in the country -- or even straight people suspected of being gay -- if we're in the wrong place at the wrong time. We need to understand why we seem to take a step back for almost every step we take forward. The usual answer is simply that we're up against a deep, powerful prejudice. There's more to it than that: The politics of gay pride is in a rut. It seems unable to appreciate its own success or acknowledge that circumstances have changed. Instead, pride is becoming an end in itself. Once pride was essential to curing the shame of the closet. Today it is the medication we're addicted to. Once pride captured the spirit of a revolution. Today it is too often the gay equivalent of pro forma patriotism. Once pride made a compelling moral argument. Today it is becoming the Ten Commandments on every wall. And when pride in the simple courage that it takes to come out of the closet in a hostile world turns into complacence and ideological rigidity, it threatens everything that we've won so far. Recognizing this isn't easy. A few years ago, Bruce Bawer, the author of "A Place at the Table: The Gay Individual in American Society," was almost burned at the stake as an allegedly sex-negative, assimilationist conservative by gay activists without much more tolerance for questions than their counterparts on the right. Among other blasphemies, Bawer suggested that stereotypes reinforced by gay publications and events might have the same negative effects as stereotypes promoted by anti-gay conservatives. Even gay activists as outspoken as Larry Kramer have been charged with neoconservatism for asking forthright questions about the overt sexualization of gay culture. The resulting fury has said less about Bawer and Kramer's arguments than it did about the touchiness of their attackers. I've been through a limited version of this treatment myself. I recently wrote a piece for the Los Angeles Times that asked whether gay pride might be easily -- and needlessly -- misunderstood. In a circulated response, Robin Tyler, executive producer of the Millennium March on Washington for Equality, objected. She insisted that concern about how gay pride is interpreted is of no concern because everybody on the other side is an irredeemable bigot. She bragged, "The Radical Right is in decline ... We have the numbers and the commitment not to have to choose 'which fight,' but to continue to mobilize on all fronts." And equating pride with self-esteem, she asked, "How can you have too much self-esteem?" Well, how about when it leads to conceit, overconfidence and solipsism? Tyler's statements are an extreme example, but this is where overuse of the pride slogan is headed. And although it's frightening to think that anybody in a position of leadership in gay politics could actually believe that we are gloriously advancing on all fronts against an enemy whose tactics we can ignore, we can take some comfort in the fact that questions about the pride strategy are becoming more widespread, and harder to dismiss. Today the questions are less about what other people will think of us -- does whipping the slave boys down Main Street send the right message? -- than what we think of ourselves. Do constant exhortations to gay pride encourage us to become self-absorbed? As Dan Savage has recently argued, pride wasn't counted as one of the Seven Deadly Sins for nothing. "The fwap of rainbow windsocks is making us dull and slow," he writes. "Thirty years after the antidote arrived, gays and lesbians stand in renewed danger of being poisoned. The poison threatening us now isn't shame, however, it's pride ... we'll never be truly whole until gay people are neither crippled by shame nor addicted to pride." Raising questions about whether pride is still effective is emphatically not to say that gay people need to tone down, fit in and ask bigots for acceptance. Most gay people, after years of pressure not to "flaunt it," are rightly leery of any suggestion that we should "assimilate." But we can't rule out consideration of a more sophisticated approach that allows us to become even more forceful and assertive about the need for equality. In the reevaluation that this requires, we need to admit that pride isn't always helpful anymore. In some cases, in fact, it simply gets in the way. Like fabulous versions of Soviet parades to commemorate the October revolution, pride celebrations prop up the memory of a victory that, while no less important, is less and less relevant. I started to understand the problem with pride through a conversation in an airport. The last flight of the night to my destination, Atlanta, had been canceled, and while I was in line for a hotel voucher, a straight guy named Will struck up a conversation with me. For every gay person, daily life means coming out to strangers if you're not going to lie or go to absurd lengths to avoid the subject. So when my conversation with Will turned to why I was going to Atlanta -- my boyfriend lived there at the time -- I told him. For a second, Will looked like he was afraid I would kiss him right there on the moving sidewalk. He thought he had been talking to just another ordinary guy in his mid-20s, not somebody gay. And to make matters worse for poor Will, he had even asked me to dinner at the airport restaurant. To his credit, Will recovered quickly, and he asked if I'd mind answering some questions about what it's like to be gay. I didn't mind, but I was caught off guard by what he asked over the next hour. He was polite, curious and candid, but his questions were surprisingly negative. One of them was, "Why would anybody be proud to be gay?" I don't know if Will -- a recent college graduate, a friendly enough guy and kind of a dude -- had ever seen a pride parade, but he had certainly heard all the politically correct explanations about gay pride and they made no impression on him. Or rather, they made the wrong impression. He continued to think that for some reason, gay pride meant that gay people are strangely proud of something alien and bizarre, like an illness or a bad habit. Will was not a fire-breathing homophobic lunatic, he was just a guy who didn't know what he was talking about. Lots of talk about pride -- the cornerstone of gay politics -- hadn't changed what he thought he already knew. But a more direct approach, highlighting the discrimination that gay people still face, did. The fact is that the concept of pride remains useful, but it's crucial to ask who it's useful for. It's useful to us to help counteract the shame of the closet, and it's a nice pat on the back for being honest about who we are. But people like Will -- and there are millions of them, and they can vote -- don't get it. Talk to antigay conservatives (as I make a point of doing, if for no other reason than a kind of clinical curiosity), and over and over again what you'll find is that they misinterpret the idea of gay pride. At first it's easy to think, "Well, fuck them if they're not comfortable with out-and-proud sexuality." This is dangerous and unnecessary. It's true that we'll never reach the rabid anti-gay kooks, but writing off average people like Will assures that millions who might be persuaded to help us -- or who at least might be vaccinated against inflammatory anti-gay rhetoric -- will remain obstacles to overcome. These are basically well-intentioned people who are doing what's "right" based on the wrong premise. Shake up that premise and it gives them pause. It even, occasionally, changes their minds. Pride can't do this because it doesn't take into account their false assumptions about us. The problem with pride is not that it's too in-your-face, but that it's not in-your-face enough. It doesn't state clearly what the gay-rights movement is really all about: equal legal and social treatment for lesbians, gay men and bisexuals. The "gay pride" slogan doesn't reach people who don't already know the facts of sexual orientation. In fact, the rallying cry of pride may even have helped provoke the backlash against us. The language of gay pride reinforces the idea that gay people are fundamentally different -- an impression to avoid if we can, given the way anti-gay conservatives portray our human rights as "special rights." In everyday speech, people use the word "pride" to talk about things they believe are special, extraordinary and exclusive. Talking too much about pride, therefore, can be counterproductive. Gay people base our claim to civil rights on the fact that our sexual orientation and our relationships are no different -- no more worthy of shame or pride -- than anyone else's. Endless declarations about pride also reinforce negative stereotypes. Talking too much about pride can give the impression that we have something to prove, and that we still can't quite put the shame of the closet behind us. As Savage says, "Surrounding oneself with constant reminders to feel prideful is to constantly be reminded of shame ... American gays and lesbians act like cancer patients who, having been cured, remind themselves that they aren't sick anymore by dropping by the hospital every once in a while for a little chemotherapy." The good news is that more and more of us are putting the shame of the closet behind us -- but this means that pride-based celebrations have less and less to offer. It's not that we're "unproud" of what's been accomplished, and we're grateful to those who blazed the trail. We owe them, but we also recognize that their efforts have paid off. We don't question our basic self-worth anymore. Yet pride-based activism, with its constant doses of self-esteem, implies that the problem is never getting any better, and that we're all going to need pride pep talks and a rainbow-colored I.V. drip for the rest of our lives. That's not just depressing, it's not true. We're OK. Let's talk about something else. What might a movement more focused on equality than pride look like? Well, nobody at the time knew exactly what Stonewall would lead to either, but a shift to a strategy that emphasizes equality instead of pride could be just as significant. Gay equality -- which wouldn't be a bad replacement for the "gay pride" slogan -- would be more open to people who are "not proud," whether they are simply gay people who are over the need for self-esteem therapy, or straight people who support gay rights but see little point in participating in typical pride celebrations today. As it is, lots of us continue to show up every year at pride celebrations out of habit. We usually have a good time, but we have only a vague idea of why we're there anymore. Showing support and being counted is all well and good, but take away the party -- we might even go so far as to call gay pride month "gay party month" -- and there wouldn't be much left. There's no reason why we can't have a party -- and do we know how to throw one -- but it's a PR disaster if a party is the main way in which we as a group bring ourselves to the attention of society every year. The focus on gay pride ends where a focus on equality would begin. Pride has become an event in June, and a mantra the rest of the year. Equality is a cause. A focus on gay equality could also change our thinking. It would move us beyond the oddly passive "we're here, we're queer, get used to it" aspect of current pride celebrations. The fact is that we want people to do a lot more than get used to us. We want them to help us get the equality we deserve. Current pride celebrations are, at best, a roundabout way of motivating anybody to do that. Finally, a new slogan like "gay equality" would help to make absolutely clear what we're after: legal and social equality. When our message to the rest of society is "gay pride," people who aren't already on our side can comfortably ignore it and continue to think, "Who cares if the queers are proud?" If the focus instead were on "gay equality," these same people would be forced to argue that we either already have equality or don't need it. Those are arguments they cannot win, and often don't even feel comfortable making. Pride helped get us where we are today. We're in a better position than ever to put tough questions to the people who aren't on our side yet, and to set the terms of this debate. But whether we are proud has become politically irrelevant, and this is no cause for alarm. The fact that we're outgrowing the need for pride is the biggest testament to its success. http://dir.salon.com/news/feature/1999/06/30/pride/index.html?sid=129902 How Do You Solve the Problem of Sharia? Canada grapples with the boundaries of legal multiculturalism. By Dahlia Lithwick Posted Friday, Sept. 10, 2004, at 2:55 PM PT This week has seen protests around Canada—and at Canadian Embassies worldwide—as citizens grapple with an issue that blurs the boundary between religious tolerance and oppression. The Ontario government is considering a proposal to allow certain family law matters—including divorce, custody, and inheritance—to be arbitrated by panels of Muslim clerics. Supporters of the proposal say that Canada's commitment to cultural diversity requires that Muslim law be accorded the same respect as other legal systems. Opponents say Muslim law inherently conflicts with the basic freedoms guaranteed Canadians. Marion Boyd, Ontario's former attorney general, has been appointed by Ontario Premier Dalton McGuinty to determine the appropriateness of these sharia, or Islamic law, tribunals. She's in a tough spot. Ultimately, the question comes down to whether sharia is fundamentally different from other religious codes. And making that sort of determination should not be the responsibility of any democratic government. The plan to use formal panels of imams and Muslim scholars to resolve family-law disputes is neither radical nor subversive. For one thing, Canadian imams have been informally using sharia law to settle disputes between Muslims for years. For another, a 1991 Ontario law known as the Ontario Arbitration Act permits Orthodox Jews and Christians to submit to voluntary faith-based arbitration. These agreements are then ratified by secular civil courts, so long as their rulings conform to Canadian law, and both parties were willing participants. Ontario Muslims have merely sought to officially reap the benefits of the Arbitration Act, leaving the Ontario government with two unpleasant alternatives: They must either scrap the act altogether or unearth some principled justification for allowing some religious citizens, but not Muslims, to benefit from its protections. The question somehow comes down to whether sharia is too inherently sexist to be reconciled with Canada's civil rights laws. And if anything definitive can be said about sharia, it's that no such definitive pronouncements can be made. It's probably no surprise that some religious groups find themselves in the strange position of wholeheartedly embracing the wonders of sharia. For instance, this week B'nai Brith Canada endorsed the tribunals. And while Canadians are deeply divided over this matter, no one is more divided than the Canadian Muslim community. The Muslim Canadian Congress urged the Ontario government to reject the tribunals, describing sharia as uncodified, racist, and unconstitutional. The Canadian Council of Muslim Women similarly says, "We want the same laws to apply to us as to other Canadian women." But Syed Mumtaz Ali—the lawyer demanding that sharia be made available under the Arbitration Act—last month declared that Muslims cannot live under secular law alone: "Every act of your life is to be governed by [sharia]. If you are not obeying the law, you are not a Muslim. That's all there is to it." If you hear echoes here of religious citizens of the United States who claim they cannot be asked to abide by any secular law that conflicts with God's law, you'll begin to grasp the problem: How does a liberal democracy permit unfettered religious freedom without eventually becoming a theocracy? Sharia is a centuries-old system of justice based on Quranic law, and while it includes general provisions about the importance of justice and equality, as practiced throughout the world it has been used to justify stonings, the flogging of rape victims, public hangings, and various types of mutilation. In her weird and provocative book, The Trouble With Islam, Canadian commentator Irshad Manji reminds us that on average, two women die each day in Pakistan from "honor killings" (a husband's revenge for adultery, flirtation, or any perceived sexual shaming) and that, in Malaysia, women may not travel without the written consent of a male. Saudi Arabian women may not drive. Moreover, under sharia, male heirs receive almost double the inheritance of females. Spousal support is limited from three months to one year, unless a woman was pregnant before she was divorced. Only men can initiate divorce proceedings, and fathers are virtually always awarded custody of any children who have reached puberty. Still, supporters of sharia tribunals in Canada have strong arguments—in addition to claims of basic fairness suggesting that if Catholics and Orthodox Jews can have divorces settled by religious courts, fundamentalist Muslims must be allowed to do the same. They insist that these religious arbitrations are voluntary. No one is forced into religious courts. They say that if a party to an arbitrated agreement is dissatisfied, she may always ask the civil courts to overturn it. And proponents urge that this is an opportunity to reform and revitalize sharia; creating a hybrid of Canadian-style freedoms and traditional values. Perhaps most important, supporters of these tribunals argue that any aspect of sharia that conflicts with the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms would simply not be enforceable by the tribunals. The charter expressly provides that "Notwithstanding anything in this Charter, the rights and freedoms referred to in it are guaranteed equally to male and female persons." Worries about a subclass of impoverished women and their abandoned children are misplaced, they insist, as is xenophobic hysteria over stonings or polygamy. Such measures violate the laws of Canada and are simply not available to sharia panels. Truth be told, it's pretty hard to tease out a meaningful objection to sharia panels under these circumstances. If participation is indeed purely voluntary, if all agreements are reviewable by civil courts, if parties are already submitting to these panels informally anyhow, and if any provision that violates the Canadian civil rights laws is null and void, what do Muslim and feminist groups find so appalling? At worst, some kind of toothless sharia-lite will govern. At best, a more equitable, kinder, gentler sharia may be forged. But Canadian feminists argue that there is no such thing as purely voluntary arbitration. They insist that isolated immigrant women with limited English are coerced into appearing before sharia panels and never advised of their rights. Refusal to abide by the dictates of these panels results in being shunned in the Muslim community. Supporters of the panels, including B'nai Brith, say this problem can be easily solved by educating women about their rights under the law and enacting protections and safeguards into the arbitration process, including female arbitrators and formal records. This raises another objection to sharia: Unlike other forms of religious law, there is little consensus on any standardized interpretation. It's hard to advise women about their rights under a set of rules that are always subject to reinterpretation. Inadvertently setting his cause back a few steps, Mohammed Elmasry of the Canadian Islamic Congress—another group endorsing sharia in Ontario—recently claimed that: "There are only a handful of scholars in Canada who are fully trained in interpreting and applying Sharia law—and perhaps as few as one." All of which makes the sharia panels sound less like a court than a Magic Eight Ball. Elmasry confirmed that point when he added cheerfully that: "The arbitrators use gut feeling, they use common sense, and in many cases they are successful." Despite this protest, it is hard to distinguish sharia law as uniquely more sexist, homophobic, or misogynistic than other religions. The brutal truth is that there are sexist and homophobic aspects to most religious law—including Orthodox Jewish and Christian law. (Indeed, some Orthodox Jewish women have used this period of review to question the appropriateness of grafting Jewish law onto the Ontario civil laws in the first place.) Certainly anyone can waive the right to have a court settle a civil dispute, and religious Canadians have every right to submit privately to tribunals of any religious stripe to mediate their differences. The question is whether the state should be putting its imprimatur on these negotiated agreements. This Canadian fondness for multiculturalism at any cost stands in stark contrast to the French approach to religious diversity. Last week, the French government began enforcing its controversial new ban on the wearing of overtly religious symbols—Muslim headscarves, large crosses, yarmulkes—in public schools. French democracy now means that everyone must subordinate their religious differences to their French citizenship, whereas Canadian multiculturalism means the civil law must bend and bend again to accommodate religious differences—even where those religious differences violate the spirit of Canadian equality. Somehow, the Canadians are prepared to sell the farm, while the French will settle for shooting all the animals. When an official government policy of diversity and tolerance gives its official thumbs up to any legal system—Jewish, Muslim, or Martian—fraught with judgment and intolerance, the consequence is a legal hall of mirrors: A system of laws equally protecting the rights of religious minorities to treat one another unequally. http://slate.msn.com/id/2106547 The latest civil rights disaster, Ten reasons why reparations for slavery are a bad idea for black people -- and racist too. By David Horowitz May 30, 2000 | It began as a fringe proposition favored by the politically extreme. But the idea that taxpayers should pay reparations to black Americans for the damages of slavery and segregation is no longer a fixation of the political margin. It is fast becoming the next big "civil rights" thing. Rep. John Conyers, D-Mich., has already introduced legislation to set up a commission that would examine the impact of slavery as a foreordained prelude to some kind of legislated payback. (Conyers will become chairman of the Judiciary Committee if Democrats win back the House.) A coalition of African-Americans is claiming a debt of $4.1 trillion. A coalition of African nations is claiming a debt of $777 trillion against an assortment of governments including the United States. Distinguished black intellectuals like Henry Louis Gates have given the idea their imprimatur, while Randall Robinson, who led the successful boycott movement against South Africa a decade ago, has written a strident, anti-white, anti-American manifesto called "The Debt: What America Owes to Blacks," which has become a bible of the reparations cause. Nor is it just in the realm of ideas that the payback demand is gaining ground. Last week, the Chicago City Council voted 46-1 in favor of a reparations resolution. The lopsided nature of the vote persuaded Mayor Richard Daley to apologize for slavery (in Chicago?), thus joining what has become a familiar and unseemly ritual of contrition for the Clinton-era left. The primary sponsor of the resolution, Alderwoman Dorothy Tillman, has announced she is going to organize a "national convention" to push the issue of reparations in the coming year. So what is wrong with the idea? In truth, just about everything. Examined closely, the claim for reparations is factually tendentious, morally incoherent and racially incendiary. Logically, it has about as much substance as the suggestion that O.J. Simpson should have been acquitted because of past racism by the criminal courts. Its impact on race relations and on the self-isolation of the African-American community is likely to be even worse. If the reparations idea continues to gain traction, its most obvious effect will be to intensify ethnic antagonisms and generate new levels of racial resentment. It will further alienate African-Americans from their American roots and further isolate them from all of America's other communities (including whites), who are themselves blameless in the grievance of slavery, who cannot be held culpable for racial segregation and who, in fact, have made significant contributions to ending discrimination and redressing any lingering injustice. 1. Assuming there is actually a debt, it is not at all clear who owes it. Tillman articulated the argument for the existence of the debt this way: "America owes blacks a debt because when we built this country on free labor ... wealth was handed down to the white community." Robinson reaches back in time even further: "Well before the birth of our country, Europe and the eventual United States perpetrated a heinous wrong against the peoples of Africa and benefited from the wrong through the continuing exploitation of Africa's human and material resources." To sustain this claim, Robinson's book devotes entire sections to the alleged depredations of whites against blacks hundreds and even thousands of years before the "eventual United States" -- i.e., the government that is expected to pay the reparations -was even created. It is necessary to insert the qualifier "alleged" because, like so many who wave the bloody shirt, Robinson makes little effort to establish causal responsibilities, but invokes any suffering of blacks where whites were proximate as evidence that whites were to blame. Slavery itself is the most obvious example. It was not whites but black Africans who first enslaved their brothers and sisters. They were abetted by dark-skinned Arabs (since Robinson and his allies force us into this unpleasant mode of racial discourse) who organized the slave trade. Are reparations going to be assessed against the descendants of Africans and Arabs for their role in slavery? There were also 3,000 black slave owners in the antebellum United States. Are reparations to be paid by their descendants too? 2. The idea that only whites benefited from slavery is factually wrong and attitudinally racist. By accusing the U.S. government of crimes against black people in advance of its existence, Robinson reveals the ugly anti-white racism beneath the surface of many arguments for reparations, especially his. According to this line of reasoning, only white Americans are implicated in slavery, just as only whites are the presumed targets of the reparations payback. Both presumptions, however, are wrong. If slave labor created wealth for all Americans, then obviously it created wealth for black Americans as well, including the descendants of slaves. Free blacks in the antebellum United States surely benefited from the free labor of slaves, along with whites. Are they to be exempted from payment of the debt just because they are black? But if the "free labor" argument of the reparations claimants is correct, even the descendants of slaves have benefited from slavery. The GNP of black America (as black separatists constantly remind their followers) is so large that it makes the African-American community the 10th most prosperous "nation" in the world. To translate this into individual realities, American blacks on average enjoy per capita incomes in the range of 20 to 50 times those of blacks living in any of the African nations from which they were kidnapped. What about this benefit of slavery? Are the reparations proponents going to make black descendants of slaves pay themselves for benefiting from the fruits of their ancestors' servitude? 3. In terms of lineal responsibility for slavery, only a tiny minority of Americans ever owned slaves. This is true even for those who lived in the antebellum South, where only one white in five was a slaveholder. Why should the descendants of non-slaveholding whites owe a debt? What about the descendants of the 350,000 Union soldiers who died to free the slaves? They gave their lives. What possible morality would ask them to pay (through their descendants) again? 4. Most Americans living today (white and otherwise) are the descendants of post-Civil War immigrants, who have no lineal connection to slavery at all. The two great waves of American immigration occurred after 1880 and after 1960. Is there an argument worth considering that would, for example, make Jews (who were cowering in the ghettos of Europe at the time) or Mexicans and Cubans (who were suffering under the heel of Spain) responsible for this crime? What reason could there be that Vietnamese boat people, Russian refuseniks, Iranian refugees, Armenian victims of the Turks or Greek, Polish, Hungarian and Korean victims of communism should pay reparations to American blacks? There is no reason, and no proponent of reparations has even bothered to come up with one. 5. The historical precedents generally invoked to justify the reparations claim -- that Jews and JapaneseAmericans received reparations from Germany and the United States, respectively -- are spurious. The circumstances involved bear no resemblance to the situation of American blacks, and are not really precedents at all. The Jews and Japanese who received reparations were individuals who actually suffered the hurt. Jews do not receive reparations from Germany simply because they are Jews. Those who do were corralled into concentration camps and lost immediate family members or personal property. Nor have all Japanese-Americans received payments, but only those whom the government interned in camps and who had their property confiscated. The reparations claims being advanced by black leaders seem to imply that the only qualification required for reparations is the color of one's skin. Robinson's book is pointedly subtitled "What America Owes to Blacks." If this is not racism, what is? 6. Behind the reparations arguments lies the unfounded claim that all blacks in America suffer economically from the consequences of slavery and discrimination. It would seem a hard case to prove over a 150-year (or even 50-year) gap, and the only evidence really offered by the claimants is the existence of contemporary "income disparities" and "inequalities" between the races. No actual connection (as far as they're concerned) need be made. On the other hand, African-American success stories that contradict the conclusion are abruptly dismissed. Thus, to take the most obvious case, Oprah Winfrey may have been a sharecropper's daughter in the most segregated of all Southern states, but -- victim of slavery and segregation or no -- she was still able to become one of the 400 richest individuals in America on the strength of her appeal to white consumers. This extraordinary achievement, which refutes the reparations argument, is echoed in millions of other, more modest success stories, including those of all the prominent promoters of the reparations claim, even the unhappy Robinson. No wonder the only argument against these obvious counterfacts is that all successes must be exceptions to the (politically correct) rule. But the reality is that this black middle class -- composed exclusively of descendants of slaves -- is also a very prosperous middle class that is now larger in absolute terms than the black underclass, which is really the only segment of the black population that can be made to fit the case. Is this black middle-class majority -- numbering millions of individuals -- really just a collective exception of unusual people? Or does its existence not suggest that the failures of the black underclass are failures of individual character, hardly (if at all) impacted by the lingering aftereffects of racial discrimination, let alone a slave system that ceased to exist well over a century ago? West Indian blacks in America are also descended from slaves, but their average incomes are equivalent to the average incomes of whites (and nearly 25 percent higher than the average incomes of Americanborn blacks of all classes). How is it that slavery adversely affected one large group of descendants but not the other? And how can government be expected to decide an issue that is so subjective -- yet so critical -- to the case? The fact is that nobody has demonstrated any clearly defined causal connection between slavery or discrimination and the "disparities" that are alleged to require restitution. And how, by the way, are blue-collar whites and ethnics expected to understand their reparations payments to these African-American doctors, lawyers, executives and military officers who make up the black middle class? 7. The renewed sense of grievance -- which is what the claim for reparations will inevitably create -- is neither a constructive nor a helpful message for black leaders to be sending to their communities. Virtually every group that has sought refuge in America has grievances to remember. For millions of recent immigrants the suffering is only years behind them, and can be as serious as ethnic cleansing or genocide. How are these people going to receive the payment claims from African-Americans whose comparable suffering lies in the distant past? Won't they see this demand as just another claim for special treatment, for a rather extravagant new handout that is only necessary because some blacks can't seem to locate the ladder of opportunity within reach of others, many of whom are even less privileged than they are? Why can a penniless Mexican, who is here illegally and unable even to speak English, find work in America's inner cities while blacks cannot? Can 19th century slavery or even the segregation of 50 years ago really explain this? To focus the social passions of African-Americans on what some Americans did to their ancestors 50 or 150 years ago is to burden this community with a crippling sense of victimhood. It is also to create a new source of conflict with other communities. A young black intellectual wrote the following comments about reparations: "I think the reparations issue will be healthy. It will show all Americans (white, Hispanic, Asian) how much blacks contributed to helping build this country." Actually, as Robinson's book makes clear, what it will accomplish is just the opposite. It will provide black leaders with a platform from which to complain about all the negative aspects of black life -- to emphasize inner-city pathologies and failures, and to blame whites, Hispanics and Asians for causing them. How is this going to impress other communities? It's really just a prescription for sowing more racial resentment and creating even greater antagonism. 8. This raises a point that has previously remained off the radar screen, but will surely be part of the debate to come: What about the "reparations" to blacks that have already been paid? Since the passage of the Civil Rights Acts and the advent of the Great Society in 1965, trillions of dollars in transfer payments have been made to African-Americans, in the form of welfare benefits and racial preferences (in contracts, job placements and educational admissions) -- all under the rationale of redressing historical racial grievances. In fact, reparations advocates already have an answer to this argument, and it is a revealing one. Here is how Robinson refers to this massive gesture of generosity and contrition on the part of the white political majority in America during the past 35 years: "It was only in 1965 ... that the United States enacted the Voting Rights Act. Virtually simultaneously, however, it began to walk away from the social wreckage that centuries of white hegemony had wrought." Take that, white, Hispanic and Asian America! If a trilliondollar restitution and a wholesale rewriting of American law and fundamental American principle in order to accommodate racial preferences and redress injustice are nothing, then what will fill the claimants' bill? 9. And this raises another question that black leaders might do well to reflect on: What about the debt blacks owe to America -- to white Americans -- for liberating them from slavery? This may not seem like a serious question to some, but that only reveals their ignorance of the history of slavery and its fate. Slavery existed for thousands of years before the Atlantic slave trade was born, in virtually all societies. But in the 1,000 years of its existence, there never was an anti-slavery movement until white Englishmen and Americans created one. If not for the anti-slavery attitudes and military power of white Englishmen and Americans, the slave trade would not have ended. If not for the sacrifices of white soldiers and a white American president who gave his life to sign the Emancipation Proclamation, blacks in America would have remained slaves indefinitely. If not for the dedication of Americans of all ethnicities and colors to a society based on the principle that all men are created equal, blacks in America would not enjoy the highest standard of living of blacks anywhere in the world, and indeed one of the highest standards of living of any people in the world. They would not enjoy the greatest freedoms and the most thoroughly protected individual rights. Where is the gratitude of black America and its leaders for those gifts? 10. The final and summary reason for rejecting any reparations claim is recognition of the enormous privileges black Americans enjoy as Americans, and therefore of their own stake in America's history, slavery and all. Blacks were here before the Mayflower. Who is more American than the descendants of African slaves? For the African-American community to isolate itself even further from America would be to embark on a course whose consequences are troublesome even to contemplate. Yet the black community has had a long-running flirtation with separatists and nationalists in its ranks, who must be called what they are: racists who want African-Americans to have no part of America's multiethnic social contract. This separatist strain in black America's consciousness has now been joined with the anti-Americanism of the political left to form the animating force behind the reparations movement. In this regard, Robinson -- himself a political leftist -- is a movement archetype. Anti-white sentiments and anti-American feelings stand out on every page of "The Debt," including a chapter he devotes to praising Fidel Castro, one of the world's longest-surviving and most sadistic dictators. A rhapsody for Fidel Castro's Marxist police state would seem a bizarre irrelevance to a book on reparations for American blacks, except that for Robinson, Castro is a quintessential victim of American "oppression." Robinson despises America that much. "Many blacks -- most perhaps," he asserts in his discussion of Castro, "don't like America." Is Robinson saying they prefer Castro's gulag? This unthinking, virulent anti-Americanism is the crux of the problem the reparations movement poses for black Americans, and for all Americans. The reparations idea is about not liking America. It is about an irrational hatred of America. It is about holding America responsible for every negative facet of black existence, as though America were God and God had failed. Above all, it is about denying the gift America has given to all of its citizens through the inspired genius of its founding. To Robinson, Thomas Jefferson, author of the proclamation that "all men are created equal," was merely "a slave owner, a racist and -- if one accepts that consent cannot be given if it cannot be denied -- a rapist." The fact that Americans still honor the author of the Declaration of Independence makes his personal sins into archetypes that define America. Robinson: "Does not the continued un-remarked American deification of Jefferson tell us all how profoundly contemptuous of black sensibilities American society persists in being? How deeply, stubbornly, poisonously racist our society to this day remains?" This hatred for America and, specifically, for white America blinds Robinson -- and those who think like him -- to a truth far more important than Jefferson's dalliance with Sally Hemings, which may or may not have been unwilling. (Contrary to Robinson, consent obviously can be given, even if it cannot be denied.) For it is the words Jefferson wrote, and that white Americans died for, that accomplished what no black African did: They set Robinson's ancestors free. For all their country's faults, African-Americans have an enormous stake in America and above all in the heritage that men like Jefferson helped to shape. This heritage -- enshrined in America's founding and the institutions and ideas to which it gave rise -- is what is really under attack in the reparations movement. This assault on America, conducted by racial separatists and the political left, is an attack not only on white Americans but on all Americans -- African-Americans especially. America's black citizens are the richest and most privileged black people alive -- a bounty that is a direct result of the heritage that is under attack. The American idea needs the support of its African-American citizens. But African-Americans also need the support of the American idea. Dredging up a new reason to assault this idea is not in the interest of African-Americans. What would serve the African-American community better would be to reject the political left as represented by people like Robinson, Jesse Jackson and every black leader who endorses this claim. What African-Americans need is to embrace America as their home and to defend its good: the principles and institutions that have set them -- and all of us -- free. salon.com | May 30, 2000 About the writer David Horowitz's odyssey from '60s radical to cultural conservative is described in his autobiography, "Radical Son." He is the president of the conservative Center for the Study of Popular Culture in Los Angeles and the editor of FrontPage Magazine. For more columns by Horowitz, visit his column archive. http://archive.salon.com/news/col/horo/2000/05/30/reparations/index.html The price of pain The co-author of a book on Holocaust reparations talks about blood money, the importance of apologizing and the slavery reparations movement. -----------By Suzy Hansen July 15, 2002 | In 1995, Rabbi Israel Singer, the fiery secretary general of the World Jewish Congress, launched the now-famous campaign for Holocaust restitution. Singer, along with billionaire Edgar Bronfman, started pressuring Swiss banks -- many of which hoarded the dormant accounts of Holocaust victims, feeding billions of dollars into the Swiss economy -- to release those funds to the survivors. But Singer, whose Austrian Jewish parents were once forced by the Nazis to scrub the streets of Vienna, had a much grander plan. As John Authers and Richard Wolffe explain in "The Victim's Fortune," their intricate account of the global fight for the repayment of Holocaust debts, Singer "hoped the battle with those who had profited in Switzerland would lead to a historical reckoning for Holocaust crimes throughout Europe." Along with American lawyers and politicians who brought class-action lawsuits and threatened economic sanctions, Singer largely succeeded. Grudgingly, Swiss, German and Italian companies reopened their books and faced ugly pasts. Some insurance companies had refused to pay out policies to survivors' heirs. Banks used victims' cash to trade in the stock market. Companies such as DaimlerChrysler and Volkswagen had profited from slave labor. None of them wanted to pay; fewer would ever issue a formal apology. And, ultimately, despite the billion-dollar agreements and promised compensation that resulted from the campaign, many survivors ended up profoundly unhappy with the process. As coauthor Richard Wolffe, the Washington deputy bureau chief for the Financial Times, explained in a recent interview, the belief that victims should be paid for their suffering is a modern and complicated one. What does a $7,500 check really do for a Holocaust survivor? The conclusion of the obviously painful process of getting the companies to pay wasn't the end of the survivors' suffering either. Many of them still haven't seen a dime, and infighting among Jewish groups about what to do with the millions, maybe billions of dollars left over still plagues the campaign. Authers' and Wolffe's book raises another haunting question: Who is entitled to speak for a victim? Wolffe spoke to Salon from Washington about whether some survivors will ever get a check, how some of the money has gone to corrupt causes and what the Holocaust debts crusade means for future reparations cases. Before the lawsuits of the '90s, why do you think Holocaust reparations hadn't become a big issue? Individuals had gone after their own accounts and their families' life insurance policies without much success. The compensation agreements that had happened before were individual offers and either they were pretty low, or, as in most cases, the banks or the insurance companies or the institutions stonewalled. They said, "Show us a death certificate," which of course the concentration camps didn't issue. The companies just wanted to push the whole issue aside. Where there had been historical studies, they really significantly downplayed or underestimated the amount of money that was at stake or hidden or kept aside. A lot of people had simply been told to go away. Most importantly, there wasn't the political willpower to do something. The Western governments were more interested in fighting the Cold War and didn't really push it so hard. Even on the official war crimes stuff -- Nuremberg -- a lot of the charges were dropped. For instance, one of the key things in the book is about German industry. A lot of German industrialists were classified as war criminals and the charges were dropped. Why? Because the West was more interested in building up the German economy and using it as a buffer against the Soviet bloc. And they also had this myth that the German economy had been razed to the ground, when actually a lot of it survived and prospered and was in a good position to benefit from the Cold War. So it suited a lot of people [to leave the compensation issue alone]. Also, it suited the American Jewish community, which was the prime mover behind the [Holocaust compensations fight]. The American Jewish community was more interested in Israel and issues of survival. The final thing is that the Holocaust survivors themselves were not as visible a presence in the immediate years after the war. It really took until the '70s for people to start thinking of the war in terms of the Holocaust. It was at that moment, when a "new" generation burst on the scene -- the children of the survivors and the children of the war criminals -- and started to revisit the war years, that the Holocaust raised itself in people's consciousness. Once the American Jewish community scored some big successes with things like the campaign to free Soviet Jewry in the '80s, they showed they could flex their muscles. Then, the end of the Cold War allowed this whole new kind of international politics through the '90s where the U.S. government was prepared to take a leading role. So how instrumental do you think the Clinton administration was? Do you think it would have been different had this been attempted during another administration? They were very influential. I wouldn't overstate it, in the sense that they weren't the only political figures to get involved or to exert crucial power. But there's no question that if Edgar Bronfman [president of the World Jewish Congress] hadn't had such a good relationship with the Clinton White House, and with the first lady in particular, then the whole weight of the U.S. government would not have been brought to bear on this issue. In particular, they opened up this big historical investigation, and they ended up mediating and brokering several deals, especially the German deal. Also, there was the whole Clinton administration's focus on human rights and corporate responsibility and the global economy. But just as important, if maybe more important, were the state and local officials who exerted a tremendous amount of direct pressure. In the Swiss case, the U.S. government role sort of collapsed. The administration mediation failed. But these kind of obscure regulators and officials at the state and local level were the ones who really worried the companies and forced them in many ways to pay up. So you're talking about people like New York City Comptroller Alan Hevesi? Alan Hevesi, right, and the New York state banking people. You're seeing something similar in the insurance cases right now where state insurance regulators are the ones who have the power to really worry the companies. That brings them to the negotiating table. You have to remember: None of these companies want to pay. None of them said, "You're right. We did something wrong. We've never faced up to this -- here's the money." There needs to be that pressure. How much did the 1999 New York City boycott of Swiss banks suspected of holding the assets of Holocaust victims affect their decision to face up to this? Oh, it really worried them. The Clinton administration always said that it didn't support sanctions, but privately, they were very pleased that someone was out there threatening sanctions. They didn't want them to go ahead but the threat of sanctions was very, very effective. And that's what we're seeing all the way through with this. If a European company has a presence in America, or maybe is looking for a presence in America, these kinds of things make them go haywire. It's a very effective way to make them face up to something. It puts a value on these historical human rights issues because they can see that it will cost them something. And that's also what those class-action lawsuits do. One of the biggest things for me in the book is: How do you put a price on suffering? These kind of sanctions help to do so. It's not a perfect way, but it does give the company a way of saying, "This is how much it's worth to us." This was a problem within the Jewish community as well. Before the '90s, some of the survivors saw reparations from Germany as blood money. Yes, and in the '90s, in the German case, the big difference is really between the different kind of survivors -- between the Jews and the non-Jews. That was really emotional and really quite ugly because many on the Jewish side, including the Jewish lawyers, said there was a conflict between these two different groups of victims. The Germans just thought they were all victims. That caused a tremendous amount of racial and ethnic stereotyping. On the Jewish side, they felt that Central and Eastern Europeans who were also victims had been anti-Semitic and on the side of the Germans at one time. That was deeply insulting to some of the Central and Eastern Europeans, some of whom were Jewish themselves. Then you scroll forward to where we are currently; there is a big difference of opinion in how a lot of the money should be spent. And whether it should go to Israel or not. It's not just in the German case; it really affects the debate about what to do with the money that's left over. There's going to be millions, maybe billions, left over from this process because survivors can't be traced or they're dead. There's a big battle yet to come about how to spend that money. Should it go to Israeli projects? Should it go to needy victims who have been paid once but could do with more? Should it go to memorials or monuments or education? And who spends the money? Who is controlling the money at this point? It depends on the settlement. In the Swiss case, it's really in the control of a U.S. judge in New York, Judge Korman. The Germans, on the other hand, didn't want any of their taxpayers' money or corporate money to be in the control of a U.S. court, so it's in the hands of a German foundation which has some American and Jewish representation on that. There's a big pool of money from the insurance funds that hasn't been released; it's in limbo. The French government is holding on to its own cash. Some of it is earmarked for international organizations like the World Jewish Congress or the Claims Conference, but a lot of it is still to be disbursed. It's not as if the judge is going to hold onto this money if it's not spent by the end of this process. Those are really difficult problems to address. It took them something like three years to come up with a plan for simply how to divide up the Swiss money between the different groups of victims, and many people were not happy with that. It's costing so much and yet some people haven't been paid, right? Yes, the people who have really profited are the researchers and accountants who've done a lot of work looking through the archives. The Swiss audit cost around $600 million alone. It's the most expensive audit in history -- going to companies like Arthur Andersen, who are really deserving, and others. The insurance case [which addresses the issue of unpaid insurance policies of Holocaust victims], for instance, is still rumbling on. Lawrence Eagleburger, the International Commission on Holocaust Era Insurance Claims chairman, is drawing a salary of $360,000 a year. He's made a million dollars since he's started his work and, frankly, very few people have been paid. At the end of the book, you say that the survivors have ended up being the unhappiest in all this. Is it possible that some of them will not get any money at all? They're unhappy for two reasons. For start, a lot of people have been frustrated. They thought they had really good claims. I was talking to one survivor the other day with an insurance claim. Remarkably, she still has the paperwork of her father paying a premium to a life insurance company. It's really rare for that kind of document to survive. The insurance company says, "Well, I'm sorry, we don't have our records of this policy, so it didn't exist." But the bigger issue is that money was at the center of all of this. People were looking for money compensation all along; without the money, it would have just been an apology, and people would have thought that that was insufficient. But when they received the money, people were ultimately extremely disappointed. I think it's something about money and suffering. In some cases, it's because the money is really pretty limited. The German compensation deal was $5 billion. That's a lot of money, but when you divide it up by several hundred thousand people, the maximum pay out for the concentration camp victims was $7,500. Maybe any sum of money would be unsatisfactory. I just think there's something about the process of compensation that we kind of expect in today's society. We expect to be paid for our suffering. But for something like this, and maybe for all kinds of suffering, when you actually get the money, it's a severe disappointment. Do you think that if the corporations or governments had issued a formal apology that it would be different? Maybe if they hadn't put up such a fight? It would have made a huge difference. Absolutely. In Germany, there was a public statement by the German president and that really helped survivors a lot. Ultimately, the survivors were more interested in the fight and the struggle to get their story retold and their suffering understood. That kind of recognition was the most important thing for them. Many countries didn't want to issue an apology. The Swiss government never got involved and that's deeply disappointing for the survivors. It's disappointing from an observer's point of view that there was no reconciliation. A public apology does help to educate people again. Do you think that bringing this issue to light and reinvigorating interest in this issue was the main thing that motivated Israel Singer, the feisty secretary general of the World Jewish Congress, whose efforts, along with Edgar Bronfman's, were largely responsible for this whole thing? I think so. He certainly wanted the money because that got people to take him seriously. But definitely the fight was a big part of it. This is a guy who learned his political skills in the civil rights movement and the whole Holocaust compensation process was another civil rights march. His particular desire was to confront people and he's very confrontational. He wanted to get people worked up, angry, passionate. And yes, he wanted a resolution. He wanted one more round of compensation. It's almost like the last war crimes trials -- there's only that tiny window left before the last survivor dies. And he knew this was his moment. Some people said he was in it for himself and he wanted the money. One thing was for sure: An organization run by Edgar Bronfman, with all of his billions of dollars, doesn't really need the money. Does it hurt the cause that Jewish organizations want to see the money go to "world Jewry" rather than just to the survivors? It is hurting the cause. It's a bit like the victims' families of Sept. 11. They have a huge amount of public sympathy, they have the most important claim to this money and they also have a lot of political power because of that public sympathy. You ignore their voices at your peril. Rather arrogantly, these Jewish organizations claim to represent world Jewry -And all 6 million who died. Yes. Bronfman famously said he was there representing the people who died. Well, I mean, for a start, there's the old joke that you put 10 Jews in a room and you hear 30 opinions. There is very little agreement among Jewish groups around the world about what to do with this kind of thing. And to say you're speaking for people who died -- many survivors think that's incredibly distasteful. On the other hand, no one else is doing it. They're filling a vacuum. And without them, you're in the situation that the African-American [reparations] community's in -- without a political voice or political leadership. But they're not democratic, it's not as if someone said to them -- "you represent us." That is a problem, a big problem. Should all the money go to the people who survived to the present day? Many survivors obviously have died of natural causes since the war. Maybe these Jewish groups, if it's spent in the right way, will spend the money on the kind of reconciliation projects that I mentioned -- on education and museums. Maybe. But what kind of things could it be going to? In the insurance case, for example, Generali, an Italian company, paid a lot of money to a foundation in Israel. The money was diverted into pet projects and, frankly, it was used for corrupt causes such as dental care for the ultra-Orthodox in Israel. It's horrific. Rather than to Holocaust survivors in Israel of which there are many. So some of these Jewish groups have appalling records and some of these newly created foundations have been hijacked by people with vested interests. Have American and Israeli survivors been better compensated than other survivors? Has there been a disparity there? That was one of the most emotional disputes. The German companies wanted to pay the survivors in Eastern Europe much less than American survivors because they said the cost of living is so much higher in America and so much lower in Eastern Europe that to pay them the same was a waste in resources. Pretty early on, the Jewish groups established that this is a very important issue and survivors everywhere should be treated equally. So the $7,500 obviously means a whole lot more to someone in Central or Eastern Europe because it goes so much further. Also, a lot of the Jews in Eastern Europe never received any compensation because the West wouldn't allow any transfer of funds to the East during the Cold War. And you would have had to be suicidal to go to the Communist authority and said, "I owned a factory," or "I had a Swiss bank account," you know, "I'm a capitalist, please give me compensation." So these people are often receiving compensation for the first time. All of these people are elderly and have very few resources but when you go to Eastern Europe the level of need is much greater than it is in general in America. But the amounts going, in theory, are equal. When this process settles down, a lot of the extra funds, the funds left over, are going to go to some of these survivors, really the forgotten survivors in the former Soviet countries. Do you think that there will be survivors who will not get money? No. I think everyone who makes a claim will get money of some kind. It may be a pittance compared to what they've lost, maybe insultingly small levels. One principle that the Germans established was that if people had received any level of compensation in the past for property or insurance policies, no matter how small, they couldn't claim again. A lot of survivors will feel very disappointed and frustrated with that. The kind of payment they accepted in the '60s -- combined for their suffering, for their years in the camps and for all the property they'd lost -- may have been very, very small even then, but that was all that was on offer. The principle was established that if you had money at all at any stage at all for that kind of claim, then that's tough. How does it work for survivors' heirs? It depends on the issue. In the case of insurance, you're talking about heirs, because the policies were insuring the lives of people who died in the camps. Swiss bank accounts, the same, really. Where it's confined to living survivors is German slave and forced labor. So in that case, the families get nothing. There's a huge practical difficulty in tracing families because you get multiple claims from the same family for the same victim. There are big disputes over the names of the individuals. For example, there are dozens of variations of the name Isaac. In some cases, the companies like to raise the issue of family members who lie about the existence of other family members. They like to say it's all fraudulent because Auntie Eden never told us that another sibling had claimed 20 years ago. There are these family complications that make the whole heir question very difficult. And expensive. Particularly with Switzerland and France, people had to look at their historical records once again. It challenged the Swiss' sense of themselves as a neutral country. Did that have a significant effect on how they treated this issue? It wasn't just about money it seems. Their first reaction was always hostile. They always said, go away you horrible Americans, who the hell do you think you are telling us what to do? But it ultimately led, after the emotions died down, to most of these countries opening up historical commissions. They looked again at their own war record and many of them were shocked at what they found. That was certainly true in France's and Switzerland's cases. The reactions of a lot of these executives -- who are not war criminals themselves -- may have been at best insensitive and at worst a coverup, but many of them thought that they were acting out of good intentions. When they found out what had happened, when they discovered the real record, they were shocked to find that their own bank had spent victims' money and knowingly, in some cases, traded the bank account cash on the stock market. It was a shock to many of these countries and it was ultimately really healthy -- the process of confronting the past. They didn't like it, they didn't want to do it, they had to be dragged kicking and screaming, but what they discovered is a real eye-opener to successive generations. In France, there are a lot of records that were still out there that people never looked at. In the case of France, some of the French Jewish leaders felt that the Americans were debasing the Holocaust by going after reparations this way. That issue has come up, and maybe most famously with Norman Finkelstein. Do you believe that as Jews they really felt that way or do you attribute it more to anti-American sentiment? It was both. The French Jewish community is very substantial, and it's also very French. Very proud and independent and all the rest of it. However, they also were both horrified and inspired by what people like Israel Singer were doing. They were inspired in the sense that it made them more confident, more ready to stand up and be vocal. And they were also horrified because they thought they were caught in the middle between anti-Semitism at home and anti-Americanism and that they would be associated with the Americans ... which is almost worse than being associated with Jewish people. Anti-Americanism is a very strong trait in French politics. Having said that, they were very, very smart. They played a good cop, bad cop routine: "You better work with us or we will unleash our American cousins on you." And to the American side, they were saying, "Hold on, we're the ones that are going to suffer anti-Semitism, we're the ones caught in the middle here, you back off." So they just about held it together. They played it very cleverly. I have a lot of admiration for those people and as you know from recent news reports, anti-Semitism is alive and well in France and the French government's reaction to it isn't always reassuring for the French Jewish community. Do you think that this whole issue revived anti-Semitism in Europe? You do say in the book that anti-Semitic cartoons popped up in Switzerland. I'm European and I'm Jewish as well, and I have to say, if you say "Jew" to many people in Europe ... "Jew" is used as a term of abuse, to mean someone who is miserly and obsessed with money. I had that growing up. So the idea that Jews would go out campaigning for money does reinforce the very worst stereotypes and racial insults. However, the American Jewish community is right in many ways: By being confident and being brash, if you will, you actually flush the ugly sentiments out into the open. It's only when they're in the open that you can really confront them. And that's the civil rights message that Israel Singer brought: Anti-Semites cause anti-Semitism. It's not Jews that cause anti-Semitism. You only know you're confronting an antiSemite when you go out there in public and you hear this stuff. There's a lot of political correctness in Europe where people know that it's wrong or they speak in code or speak amongst themselves about their anti-Semitic feelings. This whole campaign certainly did flush out some of the worst of it. I don't think it ever could get rid of it. But at least people know what they were up against. Having said that, the Jewish communities in Europe are by and large much smaller and don't have the same political power [that American Jews do]. The pressure to assimilate is much greater. I don't think it's possible to do what the American Jews have done, which is to become very vocal, very public. The role models aren't there. The public Jewish figures are very few and far between. In American life, they're everywhere. But ultimately it was a very healthy process and it has made a lot of the European Jewish community much more self-confident. Do the Holocaust compensation agreements serve as a model for African-American reparations? One of the problems with African-American slavery reparations is that there are no living plaintiffs. That's a legal problem as well as a practical problem. But as I understand it, many of the lawyers in the reparations cases are broadening it way beyond slavery to include segregation-era claims and even internationally, now, to include apartheid in South Africa, to make it a melting pot of racial claims. That's useful because they have some living plaintiffs there and it increases the pressure on some of these corporations and the pool of corporations that are likely to pay. I know from speaking to some of the African-American lawyers involved that they really are deeply encouraged by what they saw in the Holocaust cases. It's all part of this modern idea of the necessity of compensation. We're seeing that with Pan Am 103, the Lockerbie bombing, where compensation figures are huge. They're seen as being central in terms of bringing some kind of closure to the legal process and the suffering that these victims' families have endured. It's an essential part of modern life in a way that I don't think it was 20 to 30 years ago. That's one reason why many of the Holocaust victims didn't want to accept money when it was offered by Germany the first time around. They thought that it would be absolving them of their guilt, they thought it was blood money, they didn't want anything to do with it. Now the consensus among people who've suffered this kind of thing is you have to pay money. Without the money there's no sincere apology. But what do you think is one of the main differences between Holocaust settlements and slave reparations in terms of the possibility of success? In many ways, they seem worlds apart. Politics. For a start, the African-American political groups are not as well organized and they don't have the same kind of access to Washington that Jewish groups have. They've come to this issue later, and obviously the history is just much more complicated. They definitely don't have access to this White House in the same way that Jewish groups had access to the Clinton White House. In fact, I don't think the Jewish groups have the same kind of access to the Bush Oval Office as they did to the Clinton Oval Office. The politics is really important. Having said all that, state and local officials can play a big role here. Some of the changes in local and state legislation that were brought about for Holocaust survivors have equal application to the slavery cases. For instance, in California they've changed insurance legislation to allow claims including slavery and it was prompted by the Holocaust issue. But it adds to the power of insurance regulators in the state to review the historical record and say, unless insurers have dealt with their past and with these human rights claims, they may not have the license to trade in their state. That's a huge club to hold over these companies' heads. Although the African-American groups don't have the same power in Washington, I can see them exerting more important power at the local levels. Since you've published the book, have there been any significant developments in the Holocaust cases? Not significant, but there have been some interesting ones. The U.S. judge in the Swiss case fired the panel of people who were dealing with claims in the Swiss case. They won a quarter billion settlement in August 1998 and only something like $16 million has been paid out. The insurance case is still going slowly, Lawrence Eagleburger is still spending lots of money. Why do you think he has handled this so poorly? I don't just blame him. They've lost sight of what they wanted to do, which was to help the victims' families quickly. They've gotten bogged down in their own politics, their own bureaucratic mess, their own personal rivalries. They used to fly first class and stay in luxury hotels, and fly dozens of delegates around the world. His basic attitude was -- it's the companies' money, not the victims'. Well, up to a point, that's true, but if the companies don't spend it on administration costs then they're going to spend on the victims. Also, he wasn't muscular enough in terms of knocking heads together. The companies on the other side are just stonewalling. Basically it's only this Italian company, Generali, that has really stepped up to the plate. The others are dragging their heels. And on the victims' side, there hasn't been a political leadership as there was with Israel Singer. They've ended up bickering between the Israelis and the Americans and the Europeans. I just think they've all lost sight of what they wanted to do -- which was to look after the survivors and the families and get this settled quickly. Does the amount of money that these companies and banks have to pay affect their bottom lines at all? Minimally, it does. Generally, these companies don't have budgets for this kind of thing so it does affect their bottom line, but it actually affects them more in terms of their public image and the management time they have to spend dealing with it. People just don't know anything about many of these companies, and suddenly they hear them in the context of the Holocaust and they think of them as war criminals. And I think you're going to see something very similar with slavery reparations. Who knew of Aetna? I suspect that many of Aetna's customers don't even know that they're insured by Aetna. Have any of the businesses suffered? Would you even be able to quantify the impact? Let me put it like this. Allianz, which is this big German insurer, is one of the highest-profile companies involved with both the insurance case and the German settlement. Now, is it a coincidence that Allianz advertises enormously on American TV, not using its American brands but using its German corporate name, Allianz? There's awareness at corporate headquarters that the name Allianz has been dragged through the mud and, particularly among Americans, they need to rehabilitate themselves. And Allianz isn't going to rehabilitate itself by explicitly saying, look, we paid lots of money for the war. So that has had an impact and that's obviously costly for them. In that sense, they've suffered. Another point of suffering -- even though the stock market just isn't the same anymore -- is that mergers and acquisitions were the big problem that European companies faced through the '90s. For example, they would try to buy an American company and their deals were being held up by state and local regulators because of the Holocaust issue. Next time around, they might face the same thing again. It might make them reluctant to come into America. They believed that this was a global economy and corporations were free to what the hell they liked. That's quite a positive thing. The global economy has allowed people to look at the human rights issues and say, you have to have a clean house wherever you trade in the world. http://archive.salon.com/books/int/2002/07/15/wolffe/index.html Racist Like Me. Why am I the only honest bigot? By Debra Dickerson, Aug. 11, 2004 In a nation riven to its very core by race, I appear to be the only remaining racist. Off and on, I'm homophobic and anti-Semitic, too, but mostly, I'm racist. Yet unlike the rest of you, I'm honest about it. I'm the only person I know who routinely admits to being a racist. When I redeemed my Mother's Day spa package, I was assigned a lovely young black woman as my aesthetician. As we chatted, I found myself searching for words. Eventually, I realized I was trying to find a way to ask about her credentials. In 20 years of spa trips, I have never had a black aesthetician, and I have never thought, let alone asked, about one's competence, even when they disappoint me. It appears that I, too, think black people are stupid, uninformed, and graceless. Criminal, too—day before yesterday, after finalizing the details of working in a public housing complex, I dreamt that night of herds of rapacious, animalistic blacks robbing, assaulting, and generally terrorizing me there. (Birth of a Nation was more subtle.) So, counting yesterday's incident, which I will recount shortly, that makes twice just this week that I was a racist. It was yesterday's incident that got me thinking about how racism is lived. The New York Times recently won a Pulitzer for a series on how race is lived, but that's not quite the same thing, is it? Most of us agree that racism is far from dead and that we're all responsible for helping to end it. And yet, so charged is the issue of race that it is virtually impossible for those who do not already agree about it to discuss it. Without a free exchange of ideas, progress is not very likely; conservatives will continue to preach to their choir and liberals will do the same. Here's an example: A gay friend was being cavalier and dismissive, I thought, about the least divergence from the gay agenda, even by a pro-gay person like me. He wouldn't even entertain the notion that, say, lesbians in a women's locker room could legitimately give one pause. It shouldn't be a long pause (given that they've always been there), but give me a break. From the look on his face, you'd have thought that I had said he was going to sodomite hell. "Oh Debra. From you?" I argued that a man would never be allowed into a women's locker room—even if he were physically incapable of either sex or violence (I also made him blind for good measure). My friend sighed deeply, looked to the heavens as if praying for patience, and then grandly "forgave" me by abruptly changing the subject. Clearly, he considered any such discussion homophobic, a designation I escaped solely on the strength of our friendship. But why couldn't we discuss it? The notion that "victim" status exempts him from the need to examine, explain, or defend his beliefs is a dangerous one indeed. That was the perfect moment both to prove to himself that he'd thought things through, and to educate someone who could go forth and spread knowledge. Instead, we just showed each other that you can love and respect someone and yet know that they can sometimes be self-righteous, intolerant, and anti-intellectual. One reason for bigotry's maddening intractability is that a determination—however knee-jerk, superficial, or unthinkingly made—that something or someone is racist ends the discussion, as happened with my friend. The verdict is "guilty" and the only punishment is forfeiture of the right to consider yourself a decent human being. Better to be a necrophiliac than an admitted bigot. Yet if we are to evolve on the issue of race, the notion that you, or someone else, is racist ought to function as the beginning of the attainment of full humanity, not the proof that you've relinquished it. Realizing with each incident that I was operating from a no-longer-quite-subconscious script about race allowed me to recognize, and then confront, the hateful notions I have internalized about blacks. Worse, it allowed me to see that having experienced racism had helped turn me into one: It turns out that I have a problem with whites, too. Yesterday, I watched a white man park his truck in my driveway and walk off down the road without even a glance to see if the owners were about so he could ask permission. The sense of entitlement and ownership he exuded pushed every race-, gender- and class-based button a black girl from the inner city has to push. Guys like that have been pushing the world (read: me) around forever. Still, I tried to shrug it off. Then, when I went out for the mail two hours later, I was furious to see his truck still on my property. In full Gloria Steinem meets Fannie Lou Hamer mode, I marched down the road to the construction site where I figured he'd gone. At the site, a gaggle of "Joe College"-type shirtless white boys were goofing off, and a grandfatherly black man halfheartedly directed nonexistent traffic. As I approached, the black man perked up, glad to see me in this extremely white part of an extremely white city in an extremely white region. Or perhaps he was glad because now he wasn't the only adult. The white guys, suddenly busy with their rakes, feigned blindness. "Whose truck—" The black man strode over and pointed gleefully at the man who was clearly in charge. "The green hat! That's his truck." How had he known what I was going to say? With happy spite, the black man watched as I exchanged a few words with my squatter and saluted me as the man who must be his boss followed me shamefacedly to move his truck. As I passed the brother, I said evilly, "If I'd parked on his property, the police would be here." "You got that right," he agreed grimly, as if I'd narrowly escaped the noose. It's a wonder we didn't flash each other black power salutes. But the moment the words were out of my mouth, I was ashamed. Worse: I felt stupid. Who am I kidding? I'm an attorney. The lots are so big in my deer-filled suburb that I had to drive from neighbor to neighbor to collect petition signatures for a local election. In fact, we rarely even use that usurped driveway because we have two. My architect husband is white as are our two children. (So far. Biracial kids often darken over time.) The local police are just as respectful of me as they are of my neighbors, whatever they might be thinking. Whether or not I should fear them, I don't. It is a testament to the enduring legacy of racism that a black grandfather still doing manual labor bothered to side with either me or my squatter. He should have said to hell with the both of you and played dumb, leaving the two of us to fight over our possessions. I'm guessing he'd also witnessed his feudal lord take arrogant possession of a stranger's property and that this had pushed all his buttons, too. The fact that I turned out to be black was the icing on the cake. In a way, I'm arguing for class warfare to replace racial warfare. Class conflict makes sense; it keeps the powerful from riding roughshod over senior citizens who can't retire from manual labor in the hot sun. The truth is, I have far more in common with the rich white man than I do with that poor black grandfather (who would never dare to park on private property in this neighborhood). A world of perfect harmony would be lovely, but until the rapture comes I'd rather blue-collar types of all races faced off against us "suits" than one race against the other. There is nothing logical, natural, or beneficial about a world organized by race—the very concept is irrational. Any system divided along racial lines, implicitly or overtly, will be immoral, inefficient, and unstable. (Take, for example, poor whites' hatred of slaves, rather than of slavery, for depressing wages.) Class conflict, on the other hand, is natural and rational. It brought us the minimum wage, OSHA, Social Security, the weekend, overtime, pensions, and the like. While none of those are unmitigated successes, a system organized along class lines acknowledges that capitalism doesn't police itself and that labor must have a voice—it wasn't the capitalists who pushed for child labor laws and the eight-hour work day. Everybody loses when societal goods are distributed on the basis of race, even those in the front of the bus. Bigotry is just plain stupid, but as long as the price of examining one's prejudices is expulsion from the human race, we're never going to be able to quash it. When I realized that I had internalized the world's loathing of blacks, my first response was, counterintuitively, relief. Finally, I have proof that blacks' obsession with racism isn't crazy. If I secretly think that many poor blacks are animalistic and stupid, you'll never make me believe that lots of other people don't, too. My lasting response has been chagrined amusement to realize that I hold such ridiculous, illogical notions. Most of all, acknowledging my own racism has given me a measure of compassion for how difficult it is to retain one's humanity in such a politicized and inhumane world. I'm black and I make my living thinking about race, but I still wasn't immune to the insidious bigotry in our world. How much harder it must be for those with far less time to contemplate and come to terms with these vexing social issues. It's not bigotry per se that hamstrings us in the struggle to achieve a just society. It's our inability to talk about and think our way through our preconceptions. We have to learn how to forgive each other, and more importantly ourselves, when we're stupid. http://www.slate.com/id/2104994/ What is an Uncle Tom? Uncle Tom is a derogatory term for a black person who is obsequiously servile to white authority, eager to win the approval of white people, or who rubber stamps white supremacist notions about the inherent superority of whites and its corrollary -- the inherent inferiority of blacks. "Uncle Toms" are perceived to take the side of whites when there is an injustice against blacks. The term Uncle Tom comes from the title character of white author Harriet Beecher Stowe's novel Uncle Tom's Cabin. The book's Uncle Tom demonstrates an honorable grace and dignity, his story of suffering being similar to that of Job, from the Bible. Tom is pitying of Simon Legree, for Legree's fearful enslavement to his wickedness; despite his wealth, he is poor in spirit by comparison to faithful, old Tom. Most blacks, however, object to Tom's passivity, willing subservience and complete lack of outrage at his enslavement, and to Stowe's paternalism in the portrayal of the loyal, patient, long-suffering Tom. They view the author's prose as patronizing, condescending, stereotypical, and emasculating. The depiction of Tom in the popular stage version of the novel also was greatly influential in popular perception of Tom as a servile, white-haired, shuffling slave who was grateful to his master. Essentially, the accusation of being an Uncle Tom or Tomming questions the accused person's integrity, or courage, or both. The implication is that the person is demeaning him- or herself or acting against the interests of blacks, generally, for their own personal benefit, out of fear, or simply because they have been brainwashed to be complicit in their own oppression. A "Tom" can be someone judged to be insufficiently outraged by, or inadequately engaged in opposition against, a status quo of white privilege and black disadvantage. Sometimes, the term is applied to individuals who simply are perceived, rightly or wrongly, as being needlessly accommodating of whites. During slavery, Tomming could be a cunning subterfuge. White masters often gave well-liked and trusted slaves coveted, less physically demanding duties to perform. "Faithful" bondsmen and women also tended to be watched less closely, allowing them opportunities to escape to freedom or engage in clandestine acts of defiance. A Tomming fieldhand who had been bullwhipped might have an opportunity to set crops on fire. An outwardly happy and generous cook whose husband or children had been sold away from her might exact a slow and agonizing death from her master by lacing his food with finely ground glass. This practice of masking defiance or rage with acquiescence and civility continues today. As in years past, Tomming can be a means of appropriating and preserving a degree of private autonomy in the face of social prejudice and institutionalized racism, an act of subversion -- or even an over-the-top, satirical or mocking response to race prejudice. Sometimes, women who Tom are called Aunt Jemima after the popular pancake mix that long depicted a kerchief-headed family cook of that name. A roughly equivalent term is Oreo, from the chocolate sandwich cookie with white filling (implying that one is black on the outside but white on the inside). Coconut has the same meaning. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Uncle_Tom What Is a "Hate Crime"? Eve Gerber, Posted Friday, Aug. 13, 1999, at 7:25 AM PT When Buford O. Furrow Jr. confessed to shooting several Jewish children, he reportedly told lawenforcement officials that he wanted to send "a wake up call to America to kill Jews." He has been charged with six "hate crimes," which makes him eligible for the death penalty under California law. What is a hate crime? Like many legal terms, "hate crime" does not mean what it seems to. If you kill your mother-in-law because you hate her, that is not a hate crime. Hate crimes are crimes motivated by racial, religious, gender, or other prejudice. Hate crime laws generally impose tougher punishments when crimes such as rape, arson, assault, intimidation, and damage of property are motivated by bias. Forty-one states and the District of Columbia have hate crime laws. The definition of a hate crime varies. Twenty-one states include mental and physical disability in their lists. Twenty-two states include sexual orientation. Three states and the District of Columbia impose tougher penalties for crimes based on political affiliation. Some states require that bias-motivation be a substantial factor in a crime; others require it to be the sole factor. The federal Hate Crimes Sentence Enhancement Act of 1994 increases maximum sentences for crimes committed because the victim was engaged in activities such as attending public school. In 1996 Congress made it a federal crime to burn a house of worship. If passed, the Hate Crimes Prevention Act of 1999 would increase the federal role in prosecuting hate crimes. Some scholars believe hate crime laws are unwise or even unconstitutional. They argue that criminals should be punished for their crimes, not for their motives, and that making a particular belief--even a repugnant one--a factor in sentencing violates the First Amendment. But the Supreme Court unanimously rejected this argument in 1993. http://slate.msn.com/id/1003404 The Real American Love Story, Why America is a lot less white than it looks. By Brent Staples, P osted Tuesday, Oct. 5, 1999, at 12:28 AM PT The PBS broadcast last month of An American Love Story--a 10-hour film about an interracial family-spawned a great deal of chatter to the effect that mixed-race couplings were the wave of the future. In fact, they are the wave of the past. Interracial marriages accounted for only 2.2 percent of all marriages in the Current Population Survey of 1992, a gain of only two-tenths of a percent over 1980, and the number of mixed couplings actually decreased slightly in 1991. The census pattern suggests that slightly more interracial couples will fall into each other's arms in the coming years but that there will be nothing resembling a dramatic acceleration of marriage across the color line. But America already has almost 400 years of race mixing behind it, beginning with that first slave ship that sailed into Jamestown harbor carrying slaves who were already pregnant by members of the crew. Americans have grudgingly accepted the fact that sex between masters and slaves such as Thomas Jefferson and Sally Hemings was frequent, leading to a many-hued race of people who do not look African at all, even though they call themselves "African-American." Outside of recent African immigrants to the United States, there are virtually no black Americans of purely African descent, which is to say no black people who lack white ancestry, left in this country. Four centuries of race mixing have had a similar impact on Americans who define themselves as white. Convincing estimates show that by 1950 about one in five white Americans had some African ancestry. This inheritance most often arrived at the bedroom door in the form of a fair-skinned black person who had slipped over the color line to live as white. Put another way, most Americans with African blood in their veins think of themselves as white and conduct themselves as such--and check "white" when they fill out census forms. How did so much "black" blood get into so many "white" people? Consider the story behind the 1967 case of Loving vs. Virginia, in which the Supreme Court overturned laws in 17 states that forbade black people and white people to marry. Richard Loving was white and Mildred Jeter was black. In 1958, weeks after the two were married, the Caroline County sheriff dragged them from their marriage bed and jailed them for the crime of being married. The Lovings were then exiled from Virginia under pain of imprisonment. In banishing the couple from the Old Dominion, the Caroline County judge said from the bench: "Almighty God created the races, white, black, yellow, Malay, and red and placed them on separate continents, and but for the interference with his arrangement there would be no cause for such marriages. The fact that he separated the races shows that he did not intend the races to mix." This statement would have been ludicrous anyplace but was especially laughable in Caroline County-and in the Lovings' hometown of Central Point, which had been an epicenter of race mixing for at least 200 years. There were many such centers in the South. In cities such as Charleston, S.C., and New Orleans, for example, white families and their fair-skinned black relatives lived so close together that they bumped into each other on the street. Mixed-race people were initially treated as a "new people" who existed in the space between white and black and deserved a status not quite as high as whites but higher than that of black people in general. This special status began to dry up just before the Civil War and evaporated when slavery ended and free blacks competed with whites for jobs and political power. White Southerners became obsessed with drawing an impossible line that would preserve white "racial purity"--another way of referring to white political dominance. The "one-drop rule" defined as black anyone who had any black ancestry at all, even if that ancestry was invisible to the naked eye or in the genealogical record. Those who fell on the black side of the law often lost the rights to vote, to hold highstatus jobs, and to defend their persons and property in the courts. The revocation of special mulatto rights accelerated the practice of passing for white. Central Point was locally known as the "passing capital of the world." Passing for white was so common there that a section of Central Point had actually been named "Passing.'' Some Central Pointers lived as negroes at home but crossed the line to seize white privileges just an hour or two away in Richmond, Va. Local children were often taken for white during excursions to nearby towns, where they shopped in stores that did not serve blacks and were admitted to the "white only" sections of movie houses. Having learned the rewards of whiteness early, these children grew up, moved away, and continued the charade. Those who entered the armed forces, which were segregated until 1948, were often classified as white and attached to all-white units. This made for dicey moments when brown-skinned classmates from Central Point turned up in all-black units. Some of these former classmates kept the secret, but a few exposed the passers as frauds. Neither Britain nor France had laws that forbade interracial marriage, and people in those countries had no clue what the Yanks were going on about when they argued over who was really white or really black. To the French and the British, race was defined by what you looked like: If you looked white, well then, you were. Back in Caroline County, soldiers who were passing were sure to travel home alone to prevent their white buddies from knowing who and what they were. The passers from Passing married white spouses, moved into white jobs, took up residence in white neighborhoods. When the couples returned to Central Point to visit, the town went along with the masquerade. Families ditched brown-skinned friends and relatives, and children stayed out of school to avoid being seen on the colored bus headed to the colored school. Principals and teachers stuck to the script. One of them told Ebony magazine in 1967 that blacks in Central Point had "infiltrated the white race more than any other group of Negroes. When a student plays hooky from school for a week and says an in-law is visiting the family, we understand. The kids just can't afford to catch the Negro school bus without giving away the racial identity." This infiltration was common not just in Virginia but all over the United States. The most interesting document listed in the amicus briefs for Loving vs. Virginia is a statistical study called "African Ancestry of the White American Population" by Robert Stuckert, a sociologist and anthropologist from Ohio State University. Stuckert's statistical models are tough going, but eye-opening for what they show. Simply put, he examined census and fertility data to arrive at estimates of how many white Americans had African blood lines and how many fair-skinned blacks had crossed over the line to live as white. Stuckert's tables show that during the 1940s alone, roughly 15,550 fair-skinned blacks per year slipped across the color line--about 155,500 for the decade. Stuckert estimates that by 1950 about 21 percent of the whites--or about 28 million of the 135 million persons classified as "white" in the census--had black ancestry within the last four generations. He predicted that the proportion would only grow in the coming decades. The belief that one's ancestors are "racially uniform" is a basic American fiction, Stuckert wrote, but a fiction nonetheless. http://slate.msn.com/id/35817 Blood Simple, The politics of miscegenation. By Eric Liu, Posted Thursday, Aug. 22, 1996, at 12:30 AM PT The "Negro problem," wrote Norman Podhoretz in 1963, would not be solved unless color itself disappeared: "and that means not integration, it means assimilation, it means--let the brutal word come out--miscegenation." Coming after a lengthy confession of his tortured feelings toward blacks--and coming at a time when 19 states still had anti-miscegenation statutes on the books--Podhoretz's call for a "wholesale merging of the two races" seemed not just bold but desperate. Politics had failed us, he was conceding; now we could find hope only in the unlikely prospect of intermarriage. Podhoretz's famous essay was regarded as bizarre at the time, but 33 years later, it seems like prophecy. We are indeed intermarrying today, in unprecedented numbers. Between 1970 and 1992, the number of mixed-race marriages quadrupled. Black-white unions now represent 12 percent of all marriages involving at least one black, up from 2.6 percent in 1970. Twelve percent of Asian men and 25 percent of Asian women are marrying non-Asians. Fully a quarter of married U.S.-born Latinos in Los Angeles have nonLatino spouses. We are mixing our genes with such abandon that the Census Bureau is now considering whether to add a new "multiracial" category to the census in the year 2000. This orgy of miscegenation has not yet brought the racial harmony for which Podhoretz longed. But recent publicity about the intermarriage figures has stirred hope once again that our racial problems might be dissolving in the gene pool. The Census Bureau's "multiracial" proposal has provoked strong reactions from civil-rights activists who fear that many African Americans will defect to the new category, thus diluting black political power. But the debate, properly framed, is not just about "light flight" from the black community. The debate is about our very conception of race. For a "multiracial" box would be an admission that the five points of our modern-day "ethno-racial pentagon" (black, white, Asian, Hispanic, Native American) are not fixed or divinely ordained, but fickle and all too man-made. Race, you see, is a fiction. As a matter of biology, it has no basis. Genetic variations within any race far exceed the variations between the races, and the genetic similarities among the races swamp both. The power of race, however, derives not from its pseudoscientific markings but from its cultural trappings. It is as an ideology that race matters, indeed matters so much that the biologists' protestations fall away like Copernican claims in the age of Ptolemy. So the question, as always, is whether it is possible to break that awful circle in which myth and morphology perpetually reinforce one another. The leaders of the fledgling multiracial movement say that their category, and more broadly, their lives, represent the way out. By marrying across the color line, by raising mixed-race children without regard to labels, they promise to obliterate our antiquated notions of racial difference. As a newlywed who has recently joined their ranks, I hope they're right. When the time comes, I won't want to infect my ChineseScotch-Irish-Jewish children with bloodline fever. I won't force them to choose among ill-fitting racial uniforms. That said, though, there are plenty of reasons to wonder whether intermarriage can ever, as one partisan put it, "blow the lid off of race." Foremost is this reality: Racialism is highly adaptive. That is, no matter how quickly demographic change proceeds, we seem to find a way to reinvent and sustain our jerry-rigged pigmentocracy. A case in point is the term "Hispanic." Ever since this category was added to the census in 1977, we've been told that "Hispanic" is merely a linguistic category, that Hispanics "can be of any race." Today, amid a boom in the Hispanic population, we hear that caveat the same way smokers read the surgeon general's warning. The story of the last 20 years is the way heterogenous Hispanics--who ought to have exposed the flimsiness of racial categories--became just another homogenous race. The square peg, by our thinking, had been rounded off. Will this happen to "multiracials"? Their numbers are still small. Despite the quadrupling of multiracial marriages since 1970, only 5 million people today qualify--and that's counting racially distinct parents as well as their mixed-race kids. This may not be enough of a critical mass for multiracials to become a race of their own. Moreover, multiracials have less reason to cohere than Hispanics ever had; they include every conceivable combination of races, and they are not bound together by language. Still, in a nation accustomed to thinking of "official races," they'll feel pressure to form an interest group: multiculturalism's latest aggrieved tribe. One possibility is that all multiracials, over time, will find themselves the intermediate race, a new middleman minority, less stigmatized than "pure" blacks (however defined) but less acceptable than "pure" whites. Their presence, like that of the "coloreds" in old South Africa, wouldn't subvert racialism; it would reinforce it, by fleshing out the black-white caste system. Again, however, the sheer diversity of the multiracials might militate against this kind of stratification. Yet this same diversity makes it possible that multiracials will replicate within their ranks the "whitemakes-right" mentality that prevails all around them. Thus we might expect a hierarchy of multiracials to take hold, in which a mixed child with white blood would be the social better of a mixed child without such blood. In this scenario, multiracials wouldn't be a distinct group--they would just be distributed across a continuum of color. Sociologist Pierre van den Berghe argues that such a continuum is preferable to a simple black-white dichotomy. Brazilians, for instance, with their mestizo consciousness and their many gradations of tipo, or "type," behold with disdain our crude bifurcation of race. Yet no amount of baloney-slicing changes the fact that in Brazil, whitening remains the ideal. It is still better for a woman to be a branca (light skin, hair without tight curls, thin lips, narrow nose) than a morena (tan skin, wavy hair, thicker lips, broader nose); and better to be a morena than a mulata (darker skin, tightly curled hair). Subverting racial labels is not the same as subverting racism. Still another possibility is that whites will do to multiracials what the Democrats or Republicans have traditionally done to third-party movements: absorb their most "desirable" elements and leave the rest on the fringe. It's quite possible, as Harvard Professor Mary Waters suggests, that the ranks of the white will simply expand to engulf the "lighter" or more "culturally white" of the multiracials. The Asian American experience may offer a precedent: As growing numbers of Asian Americans have entered the mainstream over the last decade, it is increasingly said--sometimes with pride, sometimes with scorn--that they are "becoming white." We could thus end up with three reconfigured races. In the "black" box: black-black offspring. In the "mixed" box: black-Latino, black-Asian, black-white, and Latino-Asian kids. In the "white" box: white-white, white-Asian, and perhaps white-Latino issue. Absurd? One need only recall the baroque lexicon of "quadroons" and "octoroons" to know the absurd uses to which our powers of taxonomy can be put. These cautionary scenarios demonstrate that our problem is not just "race" in the abstract. Our problem is the idea of the "white race" in particular. Scholar Douglas Besharov may be right when he calls multiracial kids "the best hope for the future of American race relations." But even as a "multiracial" category blurs the color line, it can reaffirm the primacy of whiteness. Whether our focus is interracial adoption or mixed marriages or class-climbing, so long as we speak of whiteness as a norm, no amount of census reshuffling will truly matter. We return, then, to the question of politics. Perhaps we should abolish all racial classifications. Perhaps we should supplement the five-race scheme with a "None-of-the-Above" category. Perhaps we should replace affirmative action with a class-based alternative. Perhaps we need a leader of mixed heritage-say, Colin Powell--to educate the public about the realities of race. Whatever it takes, though, we need to do more than marry one another if we are ever to rid our minds of color-consciousness. "The way of politics," Podhoretz lamented a generation ago, "is slow and bitter." Indeed. But it is the only lasting way. Our ideology of "blood," like blood itself, is too fluid, too changeable, and too easily diverted to be remade by lovers alone. http://slate.msn.com/id/2398#ContinueArticle The Legal Fiction of "Diversity" Good intentions and the unraveling of affirmative action. By Dahlia Lithwick, Posted Thursday, May 16, 2002, at 1:56 PM PT This week, the 6th Circuit Court of Appeals overturned a district court's finding that the University of Michigan Law School's affirmative action policy was unconstitutional. In upholding Michigan's affirmative action program, the Court of Appeals, by a 5-4 vote, took another jog in the twisting national highway of race and education. Because this new opinion directly conflicts with affirmative action decisions handed down by other courts of appeals—such that what's unconstitutional in Texas or Georgia is now permissible in Michigan—it raises questions that can only be answered in the U.S. Supreme Court. But the Supremes have consistently declined to revisit their own baffling affirmative action jurisprudence. Not just because the issue is fraught with political and ideological ugliness, of a sort that makes Bush v. Gore look like a walk in the constitutional park, but because the debate isn't even about "affirmative action" anymore, as most of us understand that term. Instead, the affirmative action debate has become the illusory, impossible attempt to define educational "diversity." We grow so accustomed to constitutional paradigms that we don't always stop to reflect on where they've come from. That abortion rights are rooted in the right to "privacy" is a mere accident of constitutional history; this right was conveniently planted in the fertile soil of the 14th Amendment—dug into the dirt of its "liberty" jurisprudence, as opposed to the sandy ground under the "equal protection" clause or the barren rocks of the "privileges and immunities" clause. So, too, the constitutional justification for affirmative action is, as a result of historical accident and some constitutional nose-counting, sown in the dirt of educational "diversity." It didn't have to be this way. There were other theoretical hooks to peg it on. And most defenders of affirmative action would prefer that it were otherwise. But as a result of University of California v. Bakke, the last affirmative action education case decided in 1978 by the high court, "diversity" is the only game in town. To understand the gestation and blossoming of the "diversity" rationale requires wading back through the swamp of the vote in Bakke. Because there was no majority vote for any one position in Bakke, Justice Lewis Powell, writing only for himself, became the crucial swing vote on a court otherwise split 4-4. Because he joined one group of four on one issue and the other group of four on the other, his weird solo opinion became decisive and is now seen as having laid out the "law" of affirmative action in public education. The effect of Powell's vote: While invalidating the UC Davis med school's quota system for minority enrollment, the majority of the court nevertheless concluded that taking race into account as a mere "plus" factor in admissions was constitutionally permissible. Why? Because of the compelling state interest in fostering diversity on public campuses. The oddity in Powell's vote is that it was he alone who felt that affirmative action could be justified solely by a university's compelling interest in a "diverse student body." The other four affirmative action supporters on the court were willing to promote other "compelling interests" by which affirmative action programs could be justified. In fact there were three other rationales for minority preferences that Powell might have chosen from: 1) the need to reduce a historical shortage of minority doctors; 2) the need to cure past discrimination across society; and 3) the need to increase the numbers of doctors willing to practice in minority communities. In rejecting each of these alternative rationales, Powell—and thus the entire Bakke majority—made student-body diversity the singular goal of affirmative action programs. We don't even get to talk about correcting for past racial imbalances or promoting minority advancement as reasons to favor affirmative action. Those ideas are off the table. At least they're off the constitutional table, forever. It's vital to understand both the vote count and logic of Bakke to understand the crisis facing the courts of appeals in attempting to rule on the constitutionality of school admissions policies. Judges may not hear arguments about the importance of a "level playing field," even though these are the arguments you make at your kitchen table. The only permissible question before them anymore is whether the school in question is promoting "diversity." Whatever that means. Because student diversity means both everything and nothing, the courts following Bakke have either chosen to bind themselves by the opinion or disregard it whole-hog. The latter is what the 5th Circuit did in 1996, when it invalidated the University of Texas law school's affirmative action program in Hopwood v. Texas. The 5th Circuit simply found that Bakke was not binding precedent and that diversity was not a compelling government interest. Easy. The Hopwood court laid out its more "complete" definition of "diversity": "A university may properly favor one applicant over another because of his ability to play the cello, make a downfield tackle, or understand chaos theory. An admissions process may also consider an applicant's home state or relationship to school alumni." Last August, the 11 th Circuit Court of Appeals weighed in, with Johnson v. Board of Regents of University of Georgia, invalidating the University of Georgia's admissions policy as impermissible reverse discrimination. The 11 th Circuit simply picked up where the Hopwood court left off, holding that the admirable goal of student "diversity" can as readily be achieved by disregarding race and color altogether: "A white applicant to a Georgia public university who was raised in Athens, Greece may have a much richer background and exposure to a much more unusual environment than a non-white applicant who has spent all his life in Athens, Georgia." To the cello-playing-downfield-tackle test of Hopwood, the 11th Circuit thus added the richness brought to campus by: "individuals who come from economically disadvantaged homes; individuals who have lived or traveled widely abroad; individuals from remote or rural areas; individuals who speak foreign languages; individuals with unique communications skills (such as an ability to read Braille or communicate with the deaf); and individuals who have overcome personal adversity or social hardship." To be fair, the 5th and 11th circuits are not wrong. If we're really after "diversity" in schools, we should recruit more Maori warriors. It was probably a historical inevitability that the definition of "diversity" proffered by Justice Powell, in his concurrence in Bakke, would someday be used as a weapon against minority students. What Justice Powell was calling race-neutral diversity was always known to be a code word for racial diversity. Powell wasn't really interested in filling colleges with Alsatian goat herders. He was looking for some neutral-sounding reason to give minority candidates a small "plus" in the admissions office. But subsequent courts of appeals have called him on it. Refusing to honor his code, they take him at his word. If diversity is important, they say, admit more Wiccans. This was the damaged legal universe inherited by the 6th Circuit when called upon to decide two University of Michigan cases this year. To highlight the ironies here, one lower-court judge had invalidated the University of Michigan Law School's admissions policy while another upheld the undergraduate policy at the same school. (The 6th Circuit will decide this latter case shortly.) A close reading of the majority opinion in the Michigan decision proves that the affirmative action debate no longer concerns itself with the blood-and-guts issues of racial disparity and the need for national remedies. It's about diversity, stupid. The majority spends its energy getting out from under the quota ban in Bakke by arguing that Michigan's minority admissions policy does not constitute a mathematical quota. The opinion holds that minority race and ethnicity, among other factors, count as a "plus" in student applications at Michigan but that being a minority guarantees no one a slot. The opinion even argues that schools need a "critical mass" of minority students so that minorities do not feel "isolated." (This goes well beyond diversity and starts to look like constitutional snuggliness, but whatever.) The opinion devotes some energy to slathering the love all over Powell's opinion in Bakke, insisting that his is, in fact, the majority holding. But nowhere does the majority attempt to unpack the core assumption first asserted by Powell and repeated blandly by courts in the 24 years since: that educational diversity is somehow vital for our democracy. The heavy lifting on why diversity is a compelling state interest is left to Judge Eric Clay, who, in his concurrence to the majority opinion, offers up empirical evidence proving the "positive impact of diversity in education." Clay cites studies showing that racially diverse settings allow students to "learn better"; that they "encourage intellectual experimentation"; that "[c]omplex thinking occurs when people encounter a novel situation for which, by definition, they have no script, or when the environment demands more than their current scripts provide"; and that diversity in education thus fosters positive "democracy outcomes." In conclusion, Judge Clay can justify refusing some qualified white applicants positions in the law school because the wonderfulness of diversity "provides significant benefits to all students—minorities and nonminorities alike." In other words, some white students are refused so that other white (and nonwhite) students may be enriched. This is the core of the "diversity" defense. Needless to say, the dissenters go to town on both the inherent benefits of "diversity" and on the notion that racial diversity is of greater value than diversity of the cellist-Greek-Wiccan variety. Stating from the outset that "it's not clear what [diversity] means," Judge Danny Boggs' dissent charges that the "Law School grants preference to race, not as a proxy for a unique set of experiences, but as a proxy for race itself." In other words, the dissenters want "diversity" to mean "diversity" and not "racial preferences for historically disadvantaged minorities." Ultimately, it's almost impossible to read the dissents in this case, or the majority opinions from the 5th and 11th circuits, without finding them to be on the right side of the argument. Not because affirmative action is wrong. I, for one, continue to be all for it. The problem is that Justice Powell's legal fiction of "diversity" is crumbling fast; the legal frame he crafted for Bakke does not support the work that needs to be done. The issue of affirmative action could never properly be contained within the rationale that generalized campus "diversity" was compelled by the Constitution. It could only be justified based on the historical reality of race discrimination in this country. Still, Justice Powell made his constitutional bed, and now the current Supreme Court has to lie in it. They have dodged the affirmative action bullet three times in the past. It's not at all clear that with the Michigan decision being appealed, they'll be able to do it again. http://slate.msn.com/id/2065878 George W.'s Racial Covenant, Eve Gerber, Posted Tuesday, July 13, 1999, at 6:11 PM PT George W. Bush bought a house in 1988 that came with a deed restricting its use to “white persons only, excluding bona fide servants of any race.” Matt Drudge reported this yesterday and the Texas governor's office confirmed it today. Bush sold the house in 1995. Is this a scandal? So-called “restrictive covenants” are common in property deeds. They are a way of enforcing some requirement in perpetuity, no matter how often the property changes hands. Typical covenants forbid the onsite consumption of alcohol, the raising of sheep, or even the display of colored Christmas lights. Racial covenants limit the use of the property to members of a specified race or forbid the sale of the property to minorities. Covenants “run with the land,” meaning that future buyers must abide by their terms. Racial covenants became common after the Civil War. Early this century, after the Supreme Court overturned laws that forbade blacks to live in particular neighborhoods, covenants in deeds became the only way to maintain legally enforceable racial segregation. The Federal Housing Administration, established in 1934 to spur home-ownership by providing mortgage-loan guarantees, actually required real estate developers to include racial covenants in their deeds as a condition of FHA financing. Levittown, the model for postwar suburbia, excluded blacks through racial covenanting. All the houses in the Bushes' Dallas neighborhood have racial covenants. The covenant on the Bush property dates back to 1939. A racial covenant is, in theory, a voluntary agreement between two private citizens, the buyer and seller. As such, it was argued, a covenant was not affected by the Constitution, which places limits only on government action. But in 1948, the Supreme Court held that it would be unconstitutional for any court, as a government institution, to enforce a racial covenant. The holding was 6-0; three judges opted out of the case because they lived in restricted neighborhoods. Then in 1968, the Fair Housing Act outlawed racial discrimination in housing even by private individuals. It became illegal to refuse to sell your home on the basis of a prospective buyer's race. The act specifically forbade any new racial covenants in deeds. Today racial covenants are unenforceable and irrelevant in the eyes of the law. Prospective purchasers usually don't even learn of a racial covenant until after they have contracted to buy a home. That's when they pay for a “title search,” which consists of tracing ownership back as far as possible from the seller to the person who sold the property to the seller, to that person's seller, and so on. The purpose is to make sure the seller actually has “good title” to the property and there are no unexpected restrictions or burdens on it (such as an earlier mortgage). To help this process, the law requires that deeds and claims must be “registered,” with a copy on file with the local government. Typically a racial covenant is on file with a deed of many years ago. Subsequent deeds just say that the buyer takes on any restriction that the seller took on. A title search attorney might not even mention a racial covenant to the buyer, since it has no legal effect. But CNN reports that the Bushes' title company did include the racial covenant in their report. Should Bush have insisted on expunging the racial covenant from his house's title records, even though it was meaningless? It's possible to do this. Generally, it requires that all parties with an interest in a property must agree to invalidate the covenant. That is why a Bush spokesperson claimed that Bush alone could not remove the racial restriction. Some covenants require the approval of two-thirds of neighbors or the permission of a sub-division developer to amend their terms. A deed may also be amended by filing suit for a declaratory judgment that racial covenants are null and void. That judgment would become part of the title, recorded at the registry of land records. Filing a notarized declaration with a property's deed is another means of disavowing a racial covenant. But most people decide, not unreasonably, that expunging a meaningless provision in a legal document isn't worth the trouble and expense. Other public figures embarrassed by revelations that their property was once encumbered by racial restrictions include: John F. Kennedy, Richard Nixon, Ronald Reagan, and even the senior George Bush. http://slate.msn.com/id/1003204 Miguel, Ma Belle, The racial ugliness under the Miguel Estrada nomination. By Dahlia Lithwick, Posted Thursday, Feb. 27, 2003, at 4:16 PM PT Of all the ugliness churned up by the battle over whether Miguel Estrada deserves a spot on the D.C. Circuit Court of Appeals, the fact that it strips us down to our barest racial selves is the ugliest. If the crash of Trent Lott proved that the Old South still lives in the Senate, the battle over Estrada confirms that the race virus plaguing this country isn't fading with dying senators; it's just morphing into more and more lethal strains. And it's not just Congress. You expect them to behave like petulant babies, strutting and fretting their racial outrage before the cameras. But even more depressing than the unfolding filibuster has been watching Hispanic advocacy groups eat each other alive over the nomination, running commercials attempting to influence congressional votes and accusing one another of being "anti-Latino" for disagreeing over the fitness of the nominee. This confirmation has become the affirmative action debate in different packaging: Can we ever get far enough past racism to figure out how to get past race? There are so many different strands of affirmative action and racial misunderstanding bound up in the Estrada nomination that it's virtually impossible to untangle. First, there is the Bush administration's effort to court Hispanic voters by positioning a Hispanic-American for a Supreme Court slot. This is pandering— no different from George Bush Sr.'s determination to replace Thurgood Marshall with an AfricanAmerican—and it might be permissible pandering if Bush would just cop to it and admit that he wants to put a Hispanic judge on the high court because race matters in America. Instead, it mirrors his profoundly illogical claim that he supports racial diversity in education but opposes affirmative action. Thus, the cynical Bush take on affirmative action: Race matters enough to count when it comes to re-election but not enough to deal with it honestly or systemically. Then there's the new Republican racial awareness, featuring the grotesque claim that Estrada is being blocked because he is Hispanic. Sen. Orrin Hatch recently whined that Estrada's Democratic opponents were "anti-Latino," the implication being that the real racists in Washington are the Democrats standing between Estrada and his opportunity to break down a significant racial barrier on the bench. But as depressing as all the name-calling among white lawmakers is, the worst feature of this confirmation is the backbiting among Hispanic-Americans, who can't make up their minds whether it's more important to get a certified Hispanic judge onto the bench—regardless of his views or ideology—or to make sure that their Hispanic judge meets some idealized standard of authentic Hispanicness (preferably demonstrated by mentoring Hispanic children and rising up out of squalor). As the debate grows uglier, it's now becoming a contest among Mexicans, Cubans, and Hondurans about who—to paraphrase Snow White—is the most Hispanic of them all. Robert de Posada, the president of the Latino Coalition, a Washington policy group that supports Estrada, told reporters last week that the MexicanAmerican Legal Defense and Education Fund only opposes Estrada because he is not from Mexico, which is where they believe the first Hispanic Supreme Court justice ought to come from. De Posada also had some choice words for Robert Menendez, one of the congressional Democrats who opposes Estrada. "Menendez" he said, is "a Cuban-American who looks completely white. I wonder: Has he faced the racism and isolation that other Hispanics have faced?" This, then, is what the discussion has come to: a battle about who is Hispanic enough to warrant the racial preferences that most Americans oppose in the first place. What the Hispanic groups on both sides don't seem to understand is that, with all this infighting, they are managing to dismantle every single argument for affirmative action and making the case that race should play no role at all in public life. On the one side, we have the Estrada supporters—including one of the country's largest Hispanic lobbies, the Texas-based League of United Latin American Citizens (LULAC), as well as the Hispanic National Bar Association, the U.S. Hispanic Chamber of Commerce, and the Hispanic Business Roundtable. Their spokesmen seem to muster little beyond the tired argument that it's always better to have someone with brown skin in positions of power than to have someone white. This was the philosophy of Brent Wilkes, director of LULAC who told NPR last fall, "If we vote him down just because he's Latino and we're holding him to a higher standard, then how will that get the community anywhere when we'll probably end up with another white conservative rather than, in this case, I guess Latino conservative?" And in an interview with Hispanic Business.com last week, Hector Flores, president of LULAC, said, "The battle isn't whether he's conservative; it's that he represents Latinos, whether we like him or not." This attitude reflects several justifications for affirmative action: Break down racial barriers, remedy past discrimination, and create minority role models. All these arguments decline to look past skin color in the interest of getting the bodies onto the bench. But this argument has boomeranged badly in the past, not only because the Clarence Thomases have simply not been better for blacks than the David Souters, but because this kind of single-minded race-consciousness can only denigrate the minority in question. By ending the discussion at skin color, it sets up the implication that minorities succeed only because of preferences, that they couldn't have achieved such successes on their own merits. Could Miguel Estrada or any other minority candidate really sleep at night knowing that half his supporters would support a Honduran Hannibal Lecter as readily as they support him? What about Estrada's opponents in the Hispanic community? Are they being any less simplistic for their insistence that the nominee match up to some preconceived template for Hispanicness? Groups that oppose the Estrada nomination include the Mexican-American Legal Defense and Education Fund, the Puerto Rican Legal Defense and Education Fund, and the Southwest Voter Registration Project. In the past weeks, the California state delegation of LULAC has broken away from the national group to oppose Estrada as well. But the most vocal objections come from the Congressional Hispanic Caucus, a group of 20 House Democrats who, unable to evaluate Estrada based on his judicial experience (he has none) or legal writings (which are not being produced) met with him for an hour last June, in the basement of the Capitol. Their conclusion? According to Rep. Robert Menendez of New Jersey, Estrada "shares a surname" with Latinos but has done little to help them. Menendez complains that Estrada had not set up internships or mentorship programs specifically aimed at helping young Latino lawyers, and he told Democrats that his ethnicity would be irrelevant to his day-to-day work as a judge. But Menendez's sort of thinking decimates the only other justification for affirmative action (and the only one that now counts as a matter of law)—the argument that racial preferences automatically generate "diversity" of experience. To his detractors, Estrada's principal failing is that his privileged upbringing in Honduras and beyond were too "white" somehow—too Columbia and Harvard Law and Gibson, Dunn, and Crutcher. He was not born in squalor, nor did he rise from the barrio. As a result, he does not represent the "Latino experience." By making this argument, Estrada's detractors are merely proving that race is indeed not a proxy for diversity—and that if you really want to guarantee diversity of experience, favoring minority candidates over poor or rural ones is the absolute wrong way to go. In the end, Miguel Estrada's supporters cannot see past his skin color, and his detractors cannot see past his ideology. As a result, the "debate" over his qualification is happening, yet again, in the weary key of black-and-white. There are good arguments for affirmative action, but the Estrada fight is not the place to find them. We can only hope that the Supreme Court can bring more nuance and sophistication to their consideration of affirmative action next month than we have brought to the debate over Miguel Estrada. http://slate.msn.com/id/2079445 Supreme Court Fudge, By Michael Kinsley, Posted Tuesday, June 24, 2003, at 12:30 PM PT Admission to a prestige institution like the University of Michigan or its law school is what computer types call a "binary" decision. It's yes or no. You're in, or you're out. There is no partial or halfway admission. The effect of any factor in that decision is also binary. It either changes the result or it doesn't. It makes all the difference, or it makes none at all. Those are the only possibilities. For any individual, the process of turning factors into that yes-or-no decision doesn't matter. Any factor that changes the result has the same impact as if it were an absolute quota of one. It gets you in, or it keeps you out. And this is either right or it is wrong. The process of turning factors into a result doesn't matter here, either. In this sense, the moral question is binary, too. For 25 years, since Justice Powell's opinion in the Bakke case, moderates on the Supreme Court and well-meaning people throughout the land have been pretending that it is possible to split a difference that cannot be split. This week's court ruling, in which Justice O'Connor contrasts the college and law-school admissions systems at Michigan and essentially reaffirms Bakke, shows how laughable that pretense has become. Michigan's college admissions policy at the time this suit began was strictly numerical: You needed 100 points to get in, and you got 20 points for being an officially recognized minority. Flatly unconstitutional, the court declared. Michigan's law school, by contrast, "engages in a highly individualized, holistic review of each applicant's file." It "awards no mechanical, predetermined diversity 'bonuses' based on race or ethnicity." Instead, it makes "a flexible assessment of applicants' talents, experiences, and potential …" blah blah blah. This is how it should be done, the court said. Yes, but does the law school give an advantage in admissions to blacks and other minorities? Well, says the court, quoting the law school's brief, it "aspires to 'achieve that diversity which has the potential to enrich everyone's education.' " The law school "does not restrict the types of diverse contributions eligible" for special treatment. In fact, it "recognizes 'many possible bases for diversity admissions.' " Yes, yes, yes, but does the law-school admissions policy favor minorities? Well, since you insist, yes: "The policy does … reaffirm the Law School's longstanding commitment to 'one particular type of diversity,' " i.e., "racial and ethnic diversity." But O'Connor's opinion immediately sinks back into a vat of fudge, trying not to acknowledge that "racial and ethnic diversity" means that some people will be admitted because of their race and others will be rejected for the same reason—exactly as in the undergraduate admissions system the court finds unconstitutional. By ignoring the similarities, the court avoids having to explain coherently why it sees such profound differences. The court actually seems to be in denial on this point. Although it forbids explicit racial quotas or mathematical formulas to achieve racial balance, it is happy enough to measure the success of its preferred fuzzier approaches in statistical terms. If a selection system is going to be judged by its success in approximating the results of a mathematical formula, how is it any different from using that formula explicitly? Elsewhere, arguing for the social value of affirmative action, O'Connor's opinion cites dramatic statistics about how few minority students there would be if it were ended. But don't those statistics imply that affirmative action is having an equal-and-opposite effect now? And isn't that good to exactly the extent that ending affirmative action would be bad? And if that extent can be measured and judged using statistics, why is it wrong to achieve the statistical goal through statistical means? The majority opinion says that its preferred flexible-flier style of affirmative action does "not unduly harm members of any racial group." Well, this depends on what you mean by "unduly," doesn't it? As noted, we're dealing with an all-or-nothing-at-all decision here. Every time affirmative action changes the result, a minority beneficiary benefits by 100 percent and a white person is burdened 100 percent, in the only currency on issue, which is admission to the University of Michigan. This burden may be reasonable or unreasonable, but it is precisely the same size as the burden imposed by the mathematical-formula-style affirmative action that the court finds objectionable. The Supreme Court took these Michigan cases to end a quarter century of uncertainty about affirmative action. What it has produced is utter logical confusion. The law-school dean testified that "the extent to which race is considered in admissions … varies from one applicant to another." It "may play no role" or it "may be a determinative factor." O'Connor cites this approvingly, but it is nonsense on several levels. First, "no role" and "determinative factor" are in fact the only possible options: There cannot be an infinite variety of effects on a yes-or-no question. Second, when race is determinative for one applicant, it is determinative for one other applicant, who may or may not be identifiable. Third, the same two possibilities—no factor and determinative factor—apply to any admissions system that takes race into account in any way, including by mathematical formula and even including an outright quota system. So, it says nothing special about the law school's admissions policy compared with any other. Finally, the court is confused if it thinks that a subjective judgment full of unquantifiable factors is obviously fairer than a straightforward formula. But confusion seems to be a purposeful strategy. The court's message to universities and other selective, government-financed institutions is: We have fudged this dangerous issue. You should do the same. http://slate.msn.com/id/2084805 Gorilla Warfare, Does a sexually integrated military make sense for a primate species? By Robert Wright, Posted Friday, June 20, 1997, at 12:30 AM PT The current effort to sexually integrate the U.S. military is not without precedent. Consider the natives of New Caledonia in the South Pacific, who earned their place in military annals by subduing and then eating the crew of a French survey ship in 1850. The men and women typically headed off for war in unison, although their roles did differ once the fighting began. The women would fall back to the rear; then, as one 19th-century observer put it, "whenever they see one of the enemy fall, it is their business to rush forward, pull the body behind, and dress it for the oven." OK, so these women aren't quite the role models that proponents of sexual integration would order up from central casting. But history has provided few candidates for that job. As Maurice Davie noted in 1929 in his cross-cultural survey, The Evolution of War, "war is the business of half the human race." As a rule, the fact that women have not traditionally performed a given role has no bearing on their competence to perform it now. Centuries of female exclusion from academia or civil engineering haven't rendered modern women unfit for those professions. However, male dominance of the killing business seems to have been going on for a lot longer than a few centuries--maybe long enough to have influenced human evolution, shaping the biological foundation of human psychology. If so, does that mean male and female psychology are so different that the sexual integration of the military is misguided? The question breaks down into three subquestions. 1 Are men designed by natural selection for warfare? As regular "Earthling" readers may recall, the premise of evolutionary psychology is simple: Those genetically based mental traits that, during evolution, consistently helped their possessors get genes into the next generation became part of human nature. Careful thought experiments have shown that, in a context of regular violence, mental traits conducive to killing would do more for your genes than mental traits conducive to getting killed would. So if during human evolution men often fought in wars and women didn't, then indeed men might be naturally better warriors than women. Of course, the frequency of war in prehistory is not well recorded. (Hence the term "prehistory.") But various hunter-gatherer societies--the nearest real-life models of the social environment of human evolution, and thus the purest observable expression of human nature--have been known to engage in intervillage raids. Australian Aborigines of the 19 th century, according to one chronicler, made it a point "to massacre all strangers who fall into their power." In some of these societies, more than a fourth of the males die violently. And whether or not our distant male ancestors often participated in actual "war," they probably fought other males and sometimes killed them. The warless !Kung San hunter-gatherers of the Kalahari Desert, once romanticized as The Harmless People, were found a few decades ago to have homicide rates between 20 and 80 times as high as industrialized nations. (And some of this killing is coalitional--two brothers and a friend gang up on an enemy, etc.) So, ethnographic evidence alone suggests that men could well be designed by natural selection to fight, and perhaps to do so in groups. There is more evidence, which we'll get to shortly. However, the policy implications of any male propensity to fight would depend on other questions. For example: 2 Are women by nature shrinking violets, innately repulsed by war, incapable of violence? Hardly. Feuding Australian Aborigine women would sometimes square off and whack each other with yam sticks until somebody intervened. Among the Ainu, the indigenous hunter-gatherer people of Japan, women would go to war and actually fight, though only against other women. Even when women aren't combatants, they hardly shy away from the thought of war, or from its gore. Among the Dayak of 19th-century Borneo, women would surround a returning warrior, singing songs of praise, while the head of one of his victims sat nearby on a decorative brass tray. Among the Yanomamo of South America, women watch the one-on-one "club fights" that sometimes escalate into intervillage conflicts, screaming insults and egging their men on. Among the Ba-Huana of the Congo, one 19thcentury ethnographer reported, "the chief instigators of war are the women." If their men are insulted by other men and don't retaliate, "the women make fun of them: 'You are afraid, you are not men, we will have no more intercourse with you! Woma, woma [afraid]! Hu! Hu! Hu!' Then out go the men and fight." All told, though women as a group are less combative than men, they are not wholly averse to combat. And plainly, some women are more eager and capable fighters than some men. (I'm male, but no one has ever confused me with Charles Bronson.) So why deny high-testosterone women an opportunity to join in the fun? If there is a good reason, it has to do with our final question. 3 Why do men fight so much? Here we come to a problem that will prove stubborn if the military tries to sexually integrate ground combat forces such as the infantry. The problem isn't so much that men are designed by natural selection to fight as what they're designed to fight over: women. Even today, Yanomamo men raid villages, kill men, and abduct women for procreative purposes. Moreover, tough, mean men enjoy high social status, which attracts women and helps the men get genes into the next generation. The anthropologist Napoleon Chagnon has shown that Yanomamo men who have killed other men have more wives and more offspring than average guys. It's not just a question of men disinclined to violence getting killed off. Two men might fight over a woman until one man submits and the winner gets the woman. Or, men might fight for seemingly nonsexual reasons, but the winner still enjoys the high social status that wows the ladies. Indeed, it's possible that non-lethal violence has done more to shape the male propensity for violence than simple killing has. Male combat is common among primates. It is the reason that, in many primate species, males are so much bigger and stronger than females. Indeed, the more polygynous the species--that is, the more females a dominant male can sexually monopolize--the larger the size difference between the sexes. The toughest male gorillas get a whole harem of females to themselves, and the wimpiest get zilch. Eons of combat over such high genetic stakes have led to males that are about twice the size of females. In our species, the more modest but still marked difference in size and strength between men and women is hard evidence that violence, whether lethal or non-lethal, has paid off for men in Darwinian terms. Among the other evidence is the fact that testosterone makes people aggressive. The problem with fielding a sexually integrated army of gorillas wouldn't be that the females can't fight. Try stealing a female gorilla's baby and see how you fare. The biggest problem is that if you put three male gorillas together with one unattached female, esprit de corps will not ensue. Yes, of course human males are better at controlling their hatreds and rivalries than gorilla males are. But are humans so good that it makes sense to sprinkle a few women into a group of infantrymen and send them all off to war, where everyone's prospects for survival will depend on their solidarity? Hoping (even subconsciously) that one of your comrades will die seems a poor frame of mind to carry into battle. Does the same argument apply to nonmilitary workplaces? Doesn't sexual integration sow dissension there as well? I'd say that any downside to sexually integrating nonmilitary workplaces is not severe enough to restrict the rights of women (or men). And--in many workplaces--there may be a big upside to sexual integration. But the military is special. The cost of dissension is death, not lower earnings. (And during big wars, when the draft is on, many of the victims are people who didn't volunteer for the job. That's one big difference between this issue and the issue of sexually integrating police forces.) This logic has no direct bearing on the currently topical issue of sexually integrated basic training. The troops that take basic together don't go off to war together, so their bonding isn't a matter of life and death. Still, basic training is meant to model some of the rigors of war, and it turns out to be a useful model indeed: The complaints of sexual harassment that deluged the Army after the Aberdeen scandal (which itself didn't involve basic training) show how male and female psychology can complicate life for a sexually integrated army. Obviously, the more conspicuous problems--men propositioning women, for example--can be minimized with sufficiently harsh punishment. But the underlying psychological forces will still be there, taking their toll. And remember: When soldiers go from training camps to actual war, things get more primitive, not less. One can imagine combat roles for women that wouldn't fly in the face of human nature. (Why not try allfemale infantry battalions?) But reflecting on human nature doesn't seem to be a common pastime at the Pentagon. Sexually integrating ground combat forces is now favored by one assistant secretary of the Army. The secretary himself, Togo West, has said he is open to the idea. And already combat forces are somewhat integrated in the Air Force (squadrons of pilots) and Navy (ship crews). (These things, though, aren't as dubious as integrating the infantry would be.) Given the stakes, shouldn't such decisions be informed by some knowledge of sexual psychology? Or, instead, we could just wait for a war and use 20year-olds as guinea pigs in a poorly researched social experiment. http://www.slate.com/id/2023 Why Can't a Woman Be More Like a Man? Deborah Blum's Sex on the Brain. By Steven Pinker, Posted Wednesday, Aug. 27, 1997, at 12:30 AM PT Sex on the Brain: The Biological Differences Between Men and Women By Deborah Blum, Viking Press; 352 pages; $24.95 Imagine a tropical island on which some of the girls, at adolescence, magically turn into men. Think of the scientific possibilities! Finally, we could tease apart nature and nurture and see whether men and women differed because of how they were brought up as children. As the twig is bent, we say, so grows the branch; we expect these teens to have girls' minds in boys' bodies and to suffer from a painful confusion of gender roles. As it happens, this is not a thought experiment. In a few Dominican villages, some families carry a gene that leaves newborn boys with undescended testicles and a stunted penis resembling a clitoris. They are raised as girls until puberty, when the new rush of androgens gives them normal male genitals and a masculine body, complete with facial hair. The villagers call them guevedoces: "eggs [or balls]-at-12." The child switches genders, wears male clothing, begins to date, and turns into a normal man, without fuss or trauma. So much for bending the twig. Gender identity comes either from the effects of hormones on the brain or from the way people are treated as adults, or both; childhood nurture makes little difference. Balls-at-12 is just one of the fascinating discoveries brought to light in Deborah Blum's excellent book Sex on the Brain: The Biological Differences Between Men and Women. This is the real Everything You Always Wanted to Know About Sex (or The Sexes). Why are there sexes? To change our biochemical locks every generation and keep a step ahead of the rapidly evolving pathogens that try to pick them. How different are men's and women's brain structures? Not very. Do raging hormones turn men into testosterone-poisoned rapists and women into weepy premenstrual husband-stabbers? No both times. Are men and women biologically different in ways other than the obvious anatomical ones? Yes--men are shorter-lived, more cerebrally lopsided, more violent, better at some spatial abilities, worse at verbal abilities, more competitive but more forgiving of their competitors, more sexually jealous, more socially obtuse, and more promiscuous (at least, they'd like to be). Not only are we learning more about sex differences, but we also have an elegant theory to explain them. In the 1970s the biologist Robert Trivers showed how all the major differences between the sexes in the animal kingdom flow from a difference in the size of their investment in offspring. The female begins with the bigger ante--an egg that is far bigger than a sperm--and usually commits herself to even more, such as yolk; or, in mammals, blood and milk. The male contributes a few seconds of copulation and a teaspoon of semen. The number of offspring in each generation is limited by the female's contribution: one for each egg she produces and nurtures. That has two momentous consequences. First, a single male can fertilize several females, forcing other males to go mateless. Males must compete for access to females by beating each other up, cornering the resources necessary to mate, or persuading a female to choose them. Second, a male's reproductive success depends on how many females he mates with, but not vice versa; for a female, one mating per pregnancy is enough. That makes females more discriminating in their choice of sexual partners. Humans have added some twists to the mammalian pattern. Men generally invest in their children by providing food, protection, and care. So females also compete for mates, though they look for the ones most willing and able to invest, not the ones most willing to copulate (those are never in short supply). Females, like males, may be tempted by infidelity, though their genetic motive is quality rather than quantity. A discreet adulteress can get the genes of the fittest male and the investment of the most generous male. An easily cuckolded male would devote his efforts to the genes of a competitor, which is Darwinian suicide; hence men's intense sexual jealousy. Blum is a superb science reporter who presents just the right amount of complexity, tries to explain findings rather than just report them, and writes in a consistently clear and pleasant style. Sex on the Brain is such a good window on the state of the art that its only flaws are the flaws of the researchers themselves. Unlike Robert Wright and Matt Ridley, who have also written excellent recent books on the biology of sex, Blum does not ground her own story in rigorous evolutionary biology, but rather lets the laboratory scientists speak for themselves. Unfortunately, many good bench scientists are mediocre theorists, often by choice. "Why" questions are thought to be an indulgence, appropriate only for musings over beer at the end of the day. Blum reports (and occasionally echoes) some sloppy evolutionary "explanations," including casual analogies between arbitrary species and Homo sapiens, the equation of evolution with progress, the idea that contemporary changes in Western society are the vanguard of future evolution, and repeatedly, the error that our adaptations are for the good of the species. Adaptations are for the good of the genes that implement them, and one of the best demonstrations is right in Blum's territory: the 50-50 ratio of males to females. If organisms were designed to benefit the species, they would not waste half the available food on sons, who can't directly replenish the species with babies. Any necessary genetic variation could easily be supplied by a few studs. Organisms pump out sons because whenever females are more plentiful, the genes of mothers and fathers who bear sons have a reproductive field day, and the mixture settles at 50-50. If the species suffers, that's just too bad. Blum not only fails to share these explanations, but also sometimes repeats ones that are downright wrong--such as that men die young because the species needs them less. A better explanation is that males' reproductive fate depends more strongly than females' on competing when they are young. So any gene that builds a man with a strong young body at the cost of a weak old body will prosper. Blum's informants also mislead her in their appeal to chemistry as an ultimate explanation of sex differences. Blum masterfully explains why the effects of hormones are more complicated than pop science would have us think. They are produced by several organs in both sexes, may be converted into one another, and can have varying effects in different species, sexes, and individuals. The moral is that it is not hormones themselves but the neural circuitry, shaped by natural selection and modulated by the hormones, that explains our thoughts and feelings. The role of particular hormones may be like the role of green wires in an electronic device. The answer to the question "How does the device work?" depends on which wires connect which chips, not on the fact that a given wire is green. This undermines explanations that assume ironclad effects of hormones. Take the idea that men became less competitive because women insisted on monogamy, which lowers testosterone. Natural selection is a resourceful tinkerer and could have rewired men's brains to respond to lowered testosterone in any number of ways, not necessarily by becoming less competitive. A better answer would appeal to the tradeoffs males face between investing in their current offspring vs. competing with other males to sire new offspring with other females. In many circles, "The Biological Differences Between Men and Women" are fighting words. It seems a short step from saying that men and women are biologically different to saying that women are inferior. Moreover, if obnoxious behavior like aggression, rape, and philandering are biological, that would make them "natural" and hence good--or at least in the genes, where they cannot be changed by social reform. The result has been an angry rejection of the research Blum reports and an attempt to disseminate a feelgood alternative in which boys and girls are identical and infinitely malleable. Blum rejects these non sequiturs. She does recount the sexist pre-1950s research, which is occasionally hilarious (as when scientists were obsessed with testosterone, which they treated as the essence of masculinity) and sometimes tragic (as when hare-brained theories led to horrifying surgical procedures on women). Blum dismisses bad research with the right touch of scorn, but does not feel a need to neutralize it with politically palatable agitprop. She believes that science can approach the truth, and that we are best off if we know it and deal with it thoughtfully--which she does. Sex differences, she points out, offer no support to invidious stereotypes, are not a guideline for what is right, do not apply to every individual, and never justify the restriction of opportunity. The ignoble impulses of both sexes are part of a complex mind that can often override them; and social arrangements, from individual marriages to entire legal systems, can change for the better. http://www.slate.com/id/3005 Don't Take It So Personally, Feminism's boundary problem. By Judith Shulevitz Posted Saturday, Oct. 3, 1998, at 12:30 AM PT About 130 years ago in England, an unlikely coalition of feminists, trade unionists, and clergymen transformed the sexual mores of the day. The alliance began progressively enough, as a campaign against a law authorizing the police to round up prostitutes--and other women suspected of loose morals-and force them to submit to pelvic exams. The law was repealed. Thrilled at their newfound clout, feminists looked around for another issue. They found it in white slavery, or "traffic in women." The cry went out. Newspapers took it up, running story after story about virgins sold to drooling aristocrats. New laws were passed. The "social-purity" movement was born. Things spun quickly out of the feminists' control. Whipped into a frenzy, citizens formed the National Vigilance Association, but rather than protecting impoverished virgins the vigilantes conducted a crusade against prostitutes, homosexuals, music halls, theaters, paintings of nudes, and French novels (which they burned). At first, feminists joined in the fun. But when the misogyny and terror of the social-purity movement became impossible to ignore, they withdrew into the background. Which is where they remained for the next 20 years, discredited and humiliated, until the next wave of feminist activism came around. Feminist historian Judith Walkowitz published an essay about this incident back in 1983, during the height of feminist anti-pornography fervor. She wanted to show what can happen when feminism joins forces with the public-decency crowd. Now what can happen has happened. The social-purity movement that is the Clinton sex scandal has at least some of its roots in feminist thought, and the embarrassed mumbles of Gloria Steinem, et al., on the Lewinsky question show that feminists know it. For instance: Why were Paula Jones' lawyers able to depose Clinton on every sordid detail of his sex life? Because of sexual harassment laws that say a man's entire sexual past may be considered relevant in a lawsuit, even though a woman's may not. This arrangement was one of the triumphs of feminism over the past two decades. Like its 19th century counterpart, the women's movement will be forced to retreat from the field, confused and in disarray, if it doesn't come to terms with its mistakes. The biggest one (as many have pointed out) was blindly following the lead of that most illiberal of thinkers, Catherine MacKinnon. With her belief that unwanted sexual advances and utterances (and even, in some cases, wanted ones) degrade women so profoundly that it's worth limiting free speech to prevent them, MacKinnon laid the intellectual groundwork for today's sexual harassment laws. Before today, the most egregious outcome of MacKinnonism was the Clarence Thomas hearings. Liberal feminists (myself included, I'm sorry to say) were so eager to "educate the public" about sexual harassment, to say nothing of wanting to get rid of an anti-abortion Supreme Court candidate, that they were willing to overlook the frightening precedent being set. A man's political career was nearly ended and his private life pawed through while an entire nation watched, even though the charges against him were never subjected to the rigorous standards of evidence that would have prevailed in a court of law. Back in the 1960s and 1970s, before feminism came to mean anti-pornography statutes and laws against "hostile work environments" and other forms of censoriousness, there were all kinds of feminists. There were the liberal kind, such as Betty Friedan, who believed in the Equal Rights Amendment, day care, birth control, and abortion. There were the libertarian kind, such as Walkowitz, who argued for sexual freedom, no matter how troublesome the consequences. (There were also feminists who just seem goofy in retrospect, such as women's-music types and flannel-wearing lesbian separatists.) The healthy diversity of feminist life was killed off by two things: 1) In the late 1970s, after the Equal Rights Amendment failed to pass, the women's movement deliberately switched from the political arena to the courts. A legal strategy for change had worked for Thurgood Marshall of the NAACP Legal Defense Fund, so why not? The answer is as true for women's rights as it has been for civil rights: A movement always suffers when it fails to subject its ideas to wide public debate. 2) Influenced by MacKinnon and others, what the women's movement decided to seek in the courts was equal protection plus: the right to work plus special protection against nasty people in the workplace; the right to make their own sexual decisions plus special protection against older, savvier guys who take advantage. But rights are not necessarily cost-free. A relentless expansion of my rights usually ends up imposing burdens on your rights, or even on other rights of my own. The fury that followed some of the more questionable expansions of women's rights has made it difficult to talk about anything else. During a debate on feminism, the philosopher Hannah Arendt once passed a note to a colleague that said, "What do we lose when we win?" It was the sort of dour remark that made Arendt unpopular among her female peers. That's a shame, because Arendt's thought offers a way out of feminism's current jam. She stood for the clear separation of the public from the private sphere, a distinction dismissed as patriarchal a long time ago by feminists who thought it denigrated domestic life. But failing to see the importance of this distinction has got feminism into the trouble it's in today. To Arendt, the elimination of the public-private distinction is what distinguishes 20th century totalitarianism from earlier and lesser forms of oppression. Even in the days of absolute monarchs, a person's home was his (or, to a lesser degree, her) castle. But totalitarian governments want to control your private life down to your psyche and to mold you into a New Man or New Woman on whatever model they're peddling. Conversely, Arendt's public realm is the exact opposite of the private realm: It's where you're not protected and shouldn't be. A classicist, Arendt saw the public arena as a version of the Athenian agora-a world of political theater, where the harsh light of publicity shines upon fierce debate. Arendt's conception of the public was phrased in quasimilitaristic language almost expressly designed to irritate feminists (it didn't, but only because they had stopped listening). She declared that, for the public realm to function effectively, participants must display a love of glory. It is a hunger for glory and all that comes with it--a willingness to sacrifice one's personal desires to the common good; a sense of honor, dignity, and fair play--that allows politics to rise above a mere squabbling among interests. This is a spirit feminism lacks, which is why it has allowed women's interests as a class to trump the common interest in privacy. Rediscovering Arendt's public-private split wouldn't necessarily entail abandoning the feminist notion that the personal is political. We're all better off because feminists turned hitherto private topics into subjects of public debate. Who'd want to go back to the days when you couldn't even talk about condoms? The problem is that we've reversed the phrase: We've made the political personal. It's one thing to put sensitive subjects out there for discussion. It's another thing to welcome jurists, reporters, and the rest of the American public into our bedrooms. As it turns out, it may not be such a good idea to welcome them into our workplaces and schools either, at least not as warmly as we have. So should we do away with all forms of sexual harassment law? Or just parts of it--the hostile work environment clause, say, or the gender-biased evidentiary rules? It will take years to find the best place to draw the line, and we'll never get it perfectly right. The important thing is to realize that it's way past time to move it. http://www.slate.com/id/2360 Junkie Justice, Are drug addicts covered under the ADA? By Dahlia Lithwick, Updated Friday, Oct. 10, 2003, at 8:50 AM PT Raytheon v. Hernandez has, on one side, Joel Hernandez, recovering addict fighting for his old job after he finds God and gets sober. On the other, Raytheon, huge defense contractor, which—along with the federal government—is defending its no-second-chances-for-cokeheads policy. Hernandez is, not to put too fine a point on it, screwed from the word go. …Raytheon is represented by D.C.'s Carter Phillips. The facts: Hernandez worked for Hughes Missile Systems (later acquired by Raytheon) for 25 years. He got in trouble in 1986 for absenteeism and admitted to being an alcoholic. He underwent treatment, then tested positive for cocaine. He resigned in lieu of termination, and a note to that effect went on his file. It did not specify that he was an addict. Hernandez bottomed out, gave up drugs, and joined AA. In 1994, he asked for his job back. Hughes rejected his application immediately. Hernandez says this was because he was an addict. Hughes says it was because of their unwritten zero-tolerance policy of never rehiring employees terminated for misconduct. Hernandez sued Hughes under the Americans With Disabilities Act claiming his application was rejected as a result of his drug use, which constitutes discrimination. The Supreme Court agreed to hear the case because thousands of businesses have similar no-rehire policies, and if they all violate the ADA, warns Raytheon, we'd have federal law giving addicts a mandatory second chance. One other piece of legislative weirdness to note: The ADA does, in fact, define addiction as a disability, but only recovered and recovering addicts qualify. The ADA offers no protection to current users of drugs, which means that you are only an addict for ADA purposes once you're either being treated or cured. The court took the case to tackle the thorny issue of whether drug addiction really does constitute a disability under the ADA, rendering all zero-tolerance policies invalid. But they can't quite get past the factual dispute about whether Raytheon had such a policy. And the fact that there's a factual dispute suggests this case wasn't a good candidate for summary judgment. Justice O'Connor: "I might agree with you that the no-hire policy is lawful," she says, but there seems to be a genuine issue of fact about whether there even was such a policy in this case. The allegedly neutral "policy" may have been a pretext for discrimination against addicts. Phillips insists that there is no dispute that the policy exists, pointing to Footnote 17 in the 9 th Circuit opinion, which seems to concede this point. Stephen Montoya represents Hernandez, and gets into hot water when Justice Scalia asks him to reconcile his contention that Hughes had a no-rehire policy with Reinhardt's Footnote 17, finding they did. "I can't," confesses Montoya, and it is indeed unfair that the 9th Circuit decided the case on a different theory than his own. The court wants Montoya to argue Reinhardt's theory. Montoya wants simply to convince them that Hughes' policy was a pretext. Montoya squirms while Scalia levels with him: "We didn't take this case to decide whether or not there was a policy," he says. "We assume the policy exists. It's an important proposition, whether such a policy violates the ADA. You care about it, I know. But that's not what's important to us.” It takes a brave man to screw the little guy, but it takes a braver one to tell him that he's totally immaterial to the case he's brought. Finally, the court seems to agree that Hernandez has never even recovered from his cocaine addiction. So let's recap: We were supposed to be hearing a case about whether blanket bans on rehiring drugaddicted workers violate the ADA. But instead, we go nine rounds on whether the plaintiff is recovered enough to be discriminated against as an addict, under a policy that may or may not have existed, for purposes of a law that plainly cannot protect him. It's a good thing Joel Hernandez has found Jesus. Because the meek and downtrodden are not the concern of the court today. http://slate.msn.com/id/2089534/ s e x u a l__h a r a s s m e n t__l a w: ____RELAX AND TRY TO ENJOY IT DESPITE ITS OCCASIONAL EXCESSES, SEXUAL HARASSMENT LAW HAS IMPROVED THE WORKPLACE, LAURA GREEN REPORTS AFTER ATTENDING A MAJOR SYMPOSIUM AT YALE. -----BY LAURA GREEN | I have to begin with a confession: The topic of sexual harassment wearies me. I've done my best to avoid this 1990s cultural cataclysm as much as possible. By using extreme caution when opening the newspaper or turning on the television, I've managed to avoid precise knowledge of what revealing detail of presidential anatomy Paula Jones possesses. I'm still confused about why someone would tape telephone conversations with a friend. If I didn't think it would destroy my cultural credentials, I would even confess to not having watched a single moment of the 1991 Anita Hill-Clarence Thomas hearings. Given this attitude, I spent much of this weekend's Sexual Harassment symposium at Yale University longing for some green, remote planet -- a planet with no America, no lawyers and no talking heads -where words like "unwelcomeness," "accountability" and "dispositive" have never been uttered. The symposium -- a gathering of some 40 law professors, federal judges and other experts on sexual harassment law including Catherine MacKinnon, a Yale J.D./Ph.D. -- marked the 20th anniversary of the publication of MacKinnon's monograph "Sexual Harassment of Working Women." Groundbreaking though it was, MacKinnon's work, with its dedication to a stark male/female opposition, partly explains my distaste for the subject. On the one hand, we have MacKinnon, for whom sexual harassment is just one more instance of the principle that men unilaterally and everywhere dominate women. She has written that "male and female are created through the erotization of dominance and submission. The man/woman difference and the dominance/submission dynamic define each other." In her opening remarks at the conference, she summed up her view of the achievements of sexual harassment law in typically polemical terms: "Droit de seigneur is dead. Women are citizens." On the other hand, we have critics of sexual harassment like New Yorker writer Jeffrey Toobin, who seem to think that the most likely victims of sexual harassment are men oppressed by the law's scrutiny of sexual behavior. These two positions form the shrill, point/counterpoint battle of the sexes that is what I object to about the public debate over sexual harassment. In that context, the academic seriousness of the symposium made a refreshing change. Its 72 hours of citations of case law, cautious policy recommendations and illustrative anecdotes erred, in fact, on the side of sobriety. The opening session took place in a wood-paneled, mullion-windowed auditorium filled with nicely dressed academics. In her opening remarks, MacKinnon's fellow anti-pornography activist, Andrea Dworkin, voice trembling with rage, decried the fact that "when [in prosecuting pornography] we try to go after a bunch of pimps, everyone rears up and says no, no, no." The audience clapped politely. Later, when appellate Judge Guido Calabresi paternally reminded the audience that "women have represented some things that have been essential to society," the audience clapped politely again. But this very gentility, however soothing, belies the volatility of opinion on sexual harassment. From the reverence with which speaker after speaker at the symposium paid her or his respects to MacKinnon, for example, you wouldn't have known that many pundits view her as a cross between Jesse Helms and Valerie Solanas. After all, MacKinnon first became publicly recognized not for her work on sexual harassment, but for her anti-pornography activism. The Minnesota anti-pornography ordinance that she co-authored with Dworkin in 1983 defined pornographic representation as "a practice of sex discrimination, a violation of women's civil rights, the opposite of sexual equality." In other words, pornography and the unwelcome workplace proposition are, in MacKinnon's schema, the same kind of violation of women's civil rights. Since her anti-pornography stance makes liberals generally, and First Amendment advocates in particular, very uneasy, her association with sexual harassment law probably contributes to its current unpopularity. This conference certainly demonstrated the availability of sexual harassment law for parody. The legal doctrine produces ludicrous hypotheticals of the kind lawyers seem to love. Take the problem of the "bisexual harasser," for example. Is it discrimination based on sex if a bisexual supervisor sexually harasses male and female subordinates equally? Or consider the six scenarios of ascending complexity presented by William Eskridge, a Georgetown law professor. These scenarios culminate in the case of "Mechelle Vinson, bank teller, [who] is groped and threatened with rape by her bank supervisor, Sidney Taylor, after he finds out that Mechelle is a male-to-female transsexual." Has Taylor harassed a woman? Is sexual difference necessary for sex discrimination? If so, are we sure we know what sexual difference is? More seriously, as Eskridge also pointed out, the ambiguity of the word "sex" in "sexual harassment" can make apparently non-sexualized forms of harassment, such as letting the air out of a co-worker's tires, hard to adjudicate. Does the word "sex" refer to gender differences or erotic interaction? More recent criticisms of sexual harassment law focus not on its conundrums, however, but on allegations that it interferes with routine sexual interchanges. This criticism has been made not only by journalists such as Toobin, but also by feminist academics such as Jane Gallop, herself once the target of sexual harassment charges. Symposium participants spent a lot of time attempting to defuse and reverse this claim. MacKinnon suggested that it's critics of sexual harassment law, not its advocates, who assume that "if sex must be equal, the end of sex must be at hand." Dworkin went for sarcasm, characterizing opponents of sexual harassment law as "millions of men [who] want to have a young woman in the workplace to suck their cock." Others, like social psychologist Louise Fitzgerald, look to experimental data that suggest that "men are more likely to perceive sexual motives and intentions." So yes, sexual harassment law is open to confusion and parody. It probably doesn't help that one of its architects is a polemicist and provocateur, who began "Sexual Harassment of Working Women" with the statement: "Intimate violation of women by men is sufficiently pervasive in American society as to be nearly invisible." Nevertheless, after listening to 72 hours of earnest legal discussion, I did leave feeling that sexual harassment exists, harms women predominantly and can and should be redressed by law. It may be hard not to hold the advocates of sexual harassment law responsible for cluttering the airwaves with unsavory and ultimately tedious details of everything from presidential priapic anatomy to pornographic preferences in the highest court in the land; with creating a new and ugly plot line in that long-running soap opera of "he said, she said"; with providing new occasions for litigation and lamentation. But as MacKinnon herself wrote over a decade ago -- in a formulation reiterated by many of the conference speakers -- "Sexual harassment, the event, was not invented by feminists; the perpetrators did that with no help from us." SALON | March 3, 1998 http://archive.salon.com/mwt/feature/1998/03/cov_03featurea.html Harassment backlash When Angelo Armenti embarked on a witch hunt for professors accused of indiscretions, he became a case in point for why sexual harassment policies just don't work. I BY MATTHEW DALLEK | n May 1992, the board of governors in charge of the university system in the state of Pennsylvania plucked Angelo Armenti Jr. -- then a dean at Villanova University -- from the ranks of college officialdom and installed him as president of the California University of Pennsylvania, a mid-size, oddly named state school on the banks of the Monongahela River 30 miles outside Pittsburgh. At the time the move seemed like a shrewd one: California was in need of money and students, and Armenti seemed a good bet to provide both. The director of planning at Villanova, he had a reputation as a superlative fund-raiser, a can-do administrator and an affable, articulate up-and-comer in the world of higher education. But the newly minted president soon found himself embroiled in controversy. In 1992, the year Armenti arrived on campus, a female professor at California's business school and two department secretaries accused Arshad Chawdry, a highly regarded professor, of making crude advances toward them -- playing with their hair, kissing and hugging them, touching their breasts. At the time, the university lacked procedures for investigating such complaints, and at first Armenti adopted an evenhanded, if mediagenic, approach to the case, mixing strident pronouncement about the evils of sexual harassment with fretful laments about the decline of "collegial relationships" on campus. But when the Justice Department sued California in April 1996 for failing to follow up on the women's claims, Armenti abandoned his middle-of-the-road stance and announced a war on sexual harassment. In July of that year, the president fired Chawdry, awarded $600,000 to two of his victims and announced new sexual harassment policies for the campus. Armenti was also busy investigating other complaints, and before the year was out the president had suspended, dismissed or demoted four professors accused of sexual harassment. Then the roof caved in on him. In 1997, outside arbitrators began to review all four harassment cases, including Chawdry's, and in recent months they have all ruled against Armenti. They derided the president's decisions as arbitrary and vengeful and ordered him to rehire the professors and cough up back wages. Since then, things have gone from bad to worse for Armenti. Three of the president's targets slapped him and the university with hefty civil suits; California's faculty -- one of the better-paid in the nation -- is clamoring for his resignation; and a spate of articles in the Pittsburgh Post-Gazette has kept the imbroglio in the public eye. But what happened at California, remarkable though it may be, is far from anomalous. At universities nationwide, male professors charged with groping, fondling and smooching are seizing the offensive, blistering accusers, suing university higher-ups and winning large legal settlements. A University of Maine professor accused of pawing a female student (he touched her on the shoulder and helped her put on her coat) received $500,000 in damages from his institution, while the University of Puget Sound recently had to pay a whopping $1.5 million to a professor wrongly accused of harassment. Such stories may have seemed surprising a few years ago, but not now. A burgeoning nationwide backlash against sexual harassment is under way, and events at California show why. California seems an unlikely center of sexual harassment controversy. Situated in a one-stoplight town in rural southwestern Pennsylvania, the 5,300-student college boasts grassy knolls and a venerable history of higher learning in placid environs. "For almost 150 years," Armenti writes in his welcome letter to prospective students, "this institution has been a beacon of hope and an island of tranquillity in a very turbulent world. This university has witnessed and survived the Civil War, two World Wars, the Great Depression and countless other challenges in its long and magnificent history." With his mane of gray hair, Ph.D. in physics and predilection for silk suits, the middle-aged Armenti hardly seems a likely champion of women's issues. But in recent years he has become an ardent crusader against sexual harassment on campus. There are several reasons for this. Like many of his colleagues around the country, in the 1990s Armenti became increasingly afraid of lawsuits. In 1991 Congress amended Title VII of the Civil Rights Act to allow plaintiffs in sexual harassment cases to sue their employers. Chilled by the thought of mammoth attorneys' fees and bankbusting legal settlements, administrators and trustees decided that it was better to err on the side of caution, adopt stringent rules against sexual harassment and move swiftly at the first whiff of scandal. "It wouldn't take many more settlements like that to bankrupt us," Armenti said after shelling out $600,000 to settle the Chawdry case. "When we don't follow the Justice Department order and take sexual harassment on campus seriously, we can expect six figures taken out of our operating budget." Armenti had also grown increasingly sensitive to women's issues. Soon after taking office he hired as his special assistant Dolores Rozzi, a onetime sexual harassment expert in the Clinton administration and a big believer in the need for more female deans. In recent years Armenti has made repeated statements about protecting university women from Bob Packwood wannabes and other campus lechers, and he also came to see a sexual harassment crackdown as a way of endearing himself to students, satisfying university trustees worried about their institution's financial health and getting back at faculty critics who have accused him of interfering with undergraduate grades and admitting student athletes with criminal pasts and shoddy academic records. But in his drive to expel "predators" from campus, the president made several serious missteps, running roughshod over professors' rights, sullying their reputations and violating fundamental tenets of due process. Take, for instance, the case of Bob Brown. In early 1996, Cheryl Gray, a graduate student in the school's Education Counselor program, accused Brown, a professor, of cavorting in public with one of his students. When Brown got wind of the accusation, he confronted Gray after one of her classes. Most witnesses said Brown was restrained during the encounter, but Gray thought otherwise and complained to administrators that Brown had threatened her. Armenti conducted what by most accounts was a hasty investigation into the matter, and on May 9 of that year, a month after the Justice Department filed suit in the Chawdry case, he fired Brown. "I am persuaded that whatever mental or personality condition may have led you to the despicable behavior described above," the president wrote the professor that day, "it is not something that is easily treated or rectified ... and is one of the most evil things that someone can do at an institution of higher learning." Nor did Armenti stop there. Shortly after firing Brown, he suspended William Parnell, Brown's colleague in the Counselor Education program, for giving Gray an F, allegedly by way of retaliation. Then Armenti did something really strange: Using money from the president's discretionary fund, Armenti hired a private investigator to investigate the two professors' pasts. While the P.I. was digging for dirt, Dolores Rozzi began calling former students to see if Parnell had ever harassed them sexually. When the dust had settled, Armenti had charged Parnell with four counts of sexual harassment. The only problem was that the charges were between seven and 19 years old, the Department of Education had already investigated and dismissed one of them and another had been lodged by a felon convicted of killing her husband. Critics have also accused Armenti of acting too hastily in the case of Phil Hayes, California's longtime dean of students. In 1995, a California undergraduate complained to the president that a male student had raped her and that Hayes had rebuffed her requests for help and instead sided with her alleged attacker. Armenti again turned to an outside investigator, this time spending $4,500 on Caroline Roberto, a Pittsburgh lawyer. Roberto subsequently found that Hayes had discriminated against the woman, concluding -- wrongly as it turned out -- that the dean had helped the alleged rapist raise bail money. She recommended that Hayes be replaced with a female judicial officer. Roberto's report, apparently, was all the evidence Armenti needed. On the first day of fall classes in August 1996, the president stripped Hayes of his deanship and reassigned him to the school's purchasing department, a bureaucratic outpost that held little appeal for the former dean. The firings and demotions stunned the campus community, and left many faculty members dumbfounded; what, they wondered, was Armenti doing? The president has repeatedly argued that what he was doing was making the campus safe for students. "[I have a] responsibility to create a safe haven here," he explained at one point. "I won't tolerate sexual harassment." Based on his statements, Armenti seems genuinely committed to stamping out sexual harassment, and for that he should be commended. But in his mad-dash drive to extirpate predators from California, the president showed what can happen when an overzealous administrator decides to take sexual harassment matters into his own hands. In the last year and a half, Chawdry, Brown, Parnell and Hayes have all won vindication from arbitrators who have ruled that in his rush to judgment, Armenti relied on faulty facts, shoddy investigations and trumped-up charges. The decision in the Hayes case was typical. In his report, arbitrator Myron L. Joseph argued that the allegations against Hayes "were based on rumor and innuendo" and called Roberto's Report "a particularly unreliable hearsay document" riddled with errors. "She ... has no independent memory of what any of the interviewees told her," Joseph wrote. "She did not retain her notes and did not record her interviews. The people she interviewed were misled concerning why they were being questioned, and ... the record established that the questioning was not objective and that the individuals who were questioned were pressured to give answers that satisfied the interrogators ... The president's action was based on unfounded allegations, and an inadequate and grossly flawed investigation." Life at California these days continues much as it has for the past 145 years. Professors teach classes, students attend them and deans and administrators file papers, hear complaints and keep the campus up and running. Armenti is also back to work. Despite the arbitrators' findings, the president remains a relatively popular figure on campus. Students describe him as friendly, approachable and a leader in touch with their concerns, while trustees, pleased with Armenti's fund-raising prowess and administrative abilities, recently rewarded him with a three-year contract extension. Yet the controversies there have raised several important questions about sexual harassment policies at American universities: How, for example, should college administrators respond to charges of sexual harassment? Should presidents and deans be responsible for gathering evidence, holding hearings, investigating faculty members and adjudicating claims? Or would they be better off recruiting outside lawyers to do those jobs? Should select administrators, versed in the nuances of harassment law, preside over judicial tribunals? Or should professors be allowed to sit in judgment of their peers? There are few easy answers here. Sexual harassment is one of the most vexing issues confronting American universities, but all the reforms in the world seem unlikely to alter that fact. Still, campus judicial systems need improving. As the controversies at California show, administrators often fail to strike a balance between the claims of accusers and the rights of the accused. These are basic responsibilities of college presidents. Angelo Armenti may not have grasped them as such; but perhaps his colleagues will. SALON | Dec. 14, 1998 http://archive.salon.com/it/feature/1998/12/14feature.html Sexual Harassment Salon magazine: Laura Miller on two new books that explore the ambiguous terrain of sexual harassment. By Laura Miller ---------May 14, 1997 | few contemporary controversies resemble the legendary Gordian Knot so much as the issue of sexual harassment, but beware anyone who claims the ability to cut through it with the sharp swords of law or theory. Alexander the Great died 2,300 years ago -- and besides, sorting this one out is no job for a soldier. The American military's own inability to cope with the intricate shiftings of modern sexual politics proves that. One day the drill sergeants in Aberdeen, Md., are carrying on as if their trainees are some kind of commissioned personal harem, the next Staff Sgt. Delmar Simpson is being sentenced to 25 years of military prison for "raping" several women who admit to having "consented" to sex with him. For everyone who considers that penalty extreme, there's someone else who believes that boot camp is an artificial environment where ordinary notions of autonomy and responsibility don't apply, and therefore the Army is entitled to its own peculiar definition of rape. Of course, in this case, there's also the matter of race (Simpson is black and some, but not all, of his accusers are white), the Army's recent history of embarrassing sexual harassment scandals, the quarrel over whether women belong in combat units to begin with, the possibility that the women involved might have used their relationships with Simpson to advance their standing in his unit, and so on. Every sexual harassment case seems to resemble a Talmudic text, a puzzle of multiple facets and infinite complexity, something that could be studied for years and still yield new angles, insights and interpretations. Freud observed that every time a couple goes to bed, six people actually participate -- phantoms of the lover's parents play a role in the tryst, as well. Sexual harassment cases multiply this crowd: By the time a charge goes public, the entire citizenry has piled into the room, ready to duke it out in earnest. Confronted with such a mess, sensible people are likely to tear their hair, toss up their hands and despair of ever finding a way to apply the law fairly. But in case you haven't noticed, sensible people are rarely consulted in these matters. They're so much less entertaining than the ranters and grousers, the feminist ideologues with their hothouse analyses and the coot pundits with their soft spot for the Bad Ol' Days. Universities, in particular, have seen some pitched battles over sexual harassment, and as a result, it's in academia that reasoning feminists are colliding with their more fanatical sisters. Those tortuous collisions are sparking some fascinating new books. "i've become a spectacle," writes Jane Gallop, a professor at the University of Wisconsin at Milwaukee and the author of "Feminist Accused of Sexual Harassment," a slim volume describing her response to finding herself in that odd situation. Gallop, a veteran of the Women's Studies movement of the 1970s, was found innocent of harassing the two female students who accused her, but still censured for engaging with one of them in a "consensual amorous relation." (Her university, like an increasing number of others, prohibits any such relationship between teachers and students.) That relation consisted of flirtation and sexual bantering, culminating in one passionate, exhibitionistic kiss before a group of colleagues in a lesbian bar. Gallop argues that the teacher-student relationship, especially at its most fertile and exciting, is by nature one with erotic qualities. Like the dynamic between a therapist and her patient, it stirs up intense, often infantile emotions (what psychologists call "transference"). She believes that the campus feminists and affirmative action administrators who reprimanded her seek to divorce the intellect from the libido, a prospect she finds dehumanizing and dull. This argument initially makes Gallop a sympathetic figure; she's the lone proponent of passionate, risky, vital teaching squared off against a passel of life-denying PC puritans. And the charges leveled against her were ludicrous and overwrought, smelling suspiciously of sour grapes and hurt pride. But Gallop's personality, as revealed in "Feminist Accused of Sexual Harassment," is disturbingly reminiscent of the professor's in David Mamet's play "Oleanna," about a female student who accuses her male professor of sexual harassment. In the play, it's clear that the professor never did hit on the student, but it's also clear that he handled the girl's emotions with a thoughtless brutality that shattered her already fragile ego. She had a legitimate gripe, but one she could never prosecute; her sexual harassment charge is metaphorically appropriate. Although Gallop also never technically seduced her students, she evinces much of Mamet's professor's complacency, with her sense of her own importance, her smug assumption of her flawlessness. She's the kind of swashbuckling, provocative academic theory "star" post-structuralist graduate students swoon over almost as breathlessly as teenage girls sigh for pop idols. She's not so much angered that anyone could be charged with sexual harassment on such flimsy pretexts as she is outraged that she should be. She mostly seems irritated at being interrupted in the act of contemplating her own "bold," "clever," "sassy," "smart," "sexy" baaad feminist self. Although her memories of being "turned on" -- intellectually, socially and sexually -- by her adventures in the early women's movement are tonic reminders of headier times, she never ponders why so many young academic women today are gravitating toward a grim, fearful, "protectionist" version of feminism instead. She never asks herself why the field of women's studies -- the institution she helped build -- attracts such personalities and fosters such behavior, and what her own responsibility might therefore be. Not a whiff of self-questioning ever enters the hermetically sealed righteousness of "Feminist Accused of Sexual Harassment." Quite the opposite is true of Helen Garner's "The First Stone," an account of a sexual harassment scandal that roiled the exclusive Ormond College at the University of Melbourne. The Australian novelist and journalist's book is subtitled "Some Questions About Sex and Power," and mostly that's what it is: a squirming mass of meditations that eat their own tails -- reactions, second thoughts, third thoughts, probing interviews, bitter arguments, soul searching and confession. In that, it feels both closer to the daunting realities of the sexual harassment controversy and -- in its fearless commitment to expressing the truth and fostering a just relationship between the sexes -- more feminist than anything I've read in a long time. Garner strikes me as trustworthy precisely because she doesn't pretend to have figured it all out, to have a one-size-fits-all theory for what sexual harassment is and what should be done about it. Briefly, the Ormond College scandal ignited when two female students accused a male administrator at the school of harassing them (touching their breasts and, in one case, talking suggestively) during a somewhat drunken campus party. For months after the party, various officials bumbled around with the charges while the man himself, Colin Shepard, remained uninformed. Long after the event, he was brought into the local police station and charged with "indecent assault." When Garner read about Shepard's arrest, she felt a "jolt" at the rage and severity of the response to what sounded like a "clumsy pass" by a "poor blunderer," the kind of thing feminists of her generation (now "pushing 50") shrugged off. Shepard's career was ruined, and his family (who Garner found decent and unembittered) traumatized by the trial and its aftermath. To Garner, who had spent her youth campaigning for abortion rights and against sexual discrimination, the case felt like a "destructive, priggish and pitiless" travesty of feminism's original, expansive quest for social justice. Garner's investigation of the case introduced her to the tut-tutting old boys' network that once reigned supreme in Ormond's pre-coed era, and to a new breed of feminists, "cold-faced, punitive girls" bent on, in their own words, "retribution," like the vengeful God of the Old Testament. She had long, surprising talks with her friends, filled with revelations of past rapes and sexually predatory teachers and bosses. She worried about being out-of-date politically, of inviting the "scorn" of her daughter's generation for her soft position on the vagaries of sexual power. She juxtaposes Shepard's offense with the horrific reports of sexual violence that studded the daily papers at the time. But one thing she never did was talk to Colin Shepard's accusers. The two women, and nearly all of their supporters, utterly stonewalled Garner after branding her as unsympathetic. Much of "The First Stone" relates Garner's multifarious, exasperating efforts to get these women to tell their side of the story. She writes letters that plead and others that fulminate about the need for "open discourse," all to no avail. Even so, the case grows whole new annexes of possible meaning as she goes. Did the college fail to back Shepard up because he was considered a somewhat gauche outsider, and a relatively painless sacrifice to a troublesome and vocal campus minority? Could the conflict have been resolved without the police if the college had had a mandated procedure for such cases? Who circulated the inflammatory anonymous leaflets suggesting that Shepard was a potential rapist and urging women students not to "panic"? Garner raises many intriguing questions, but perhaps the most pressing is this: What causes "the mysterious passivity that can incapacitate a woman at a moment of unexpected, unwanted sexual pressure"? At the party in question, after being allegedly fondled by Shepard, one complainant quietly retreated to a group of friends. "The spontaneous collective response was to make it look as if nothing untoward had happened ... Everything they did was directed at protecting him from knowing that he had offended her." Was the wrath finally unleashed on Shepard the pent-up result of dozens of other incidents with many other men, none of whom were confronted with the disagreeableness of their advances? Does vanishing into a group -- whether friends on a dance floor or a cadre of anti-sexual harassment activists -ever help a young woman achieve the kind of self-possession that makes deflecting unwanted passes less than a federal case? When "The First Stone" was originally published in Australia, it raised what Garner calls (in the afterword to the American edition) a "primal" furor, and, predictably, Garner was falsely accused of making all sorts of ridiculous statements. The book, she observes, "declines -- or is unable to present itself as -- one big clonking armour-clad monolithic certainty." This inflames readers who "located their sense of worth in holding to an already worked-out political position ... permanently primed for battle, they read like tanks." Fortunately, the book found many more readers who were "relieved that ambiguity might be re-admitted to the analysis of thought and action." Perhaps it's no coincidence that, as these passages indicate, Garner writes with so much more fluidity, color and eloquence than Gallop, whose stilted prose suggests a jargon-jockey awkwardly playing to the bleachers. One writer trusts the average, intelligent reader with the raw, confusing truth; the other simply seeks to consolidate her position as prophet of the One True Feminism. One demonstrates the strength of her convictions by her willingness to re-examine her politics; the other is miffed at being challenged at all. To help us find our way to just, humane policies on sexual harassment, we need thinkers able to describe the terrain as it really is. http://dir.salon.com/books/feature/1997/05/14/harassment/index.html?sid=558002 Too sexy for my shirt It's spring, a time for many men to sexually harass women on the streets in the crudest of terms. Should there be a law against it? By Debra Dickerson ---------May 21, 1999 | WASHINGTON -- I am a spectacular beauty. It's May now, and I walk the streets of the nation's capital free from my shrouding winter coat, making it impossible for male passersby to concentrate on their conversations. Cars slide to a precipitous halt at the mere sight of me, fishtailing as their brakes lock. Heads swivel on necks made suddenly rubbery by the merest glimpse of me. Eyes goggle. The glint of my ankle bracelet, the hint of a thigh as my skirt blows around -- it's unfair, really, and I know I need to stop showing off "them fine legs." At least that's what the helpful truck driver yells after swooping to a stop in his deuce-and-a-half mere inches from me. My perfume, mingled with the inchoate sorcery that is moi, produces a fragrance so entrancing, so beguiling, it can only be called eau de Debra and it drives men to lunacy. How could they not sniff and snort with orgasmic pleasure, lips loudly smacking, nostrils piggily flaring, lest I fail to notice their gyrations? What good are offerings made to a goddess who notices not? So by all means, come a little closer. After all, I am woman and therefore a natural wonder. Like a waterfall or a pretty stand of trees. Feel free to waylay me. Block my path to inform me that you heartily approve of my "tight-ass" dress. Thank God that's settled. And don't forget to thrust your pelvis at me while you address my breasts. We beauties like it. Why else would we dress "that way"? Don't just scream at me from the far side of a four-lane road (across which I am apparently supposed to jog so that our destiny can be fulfilled at the bus stop named Federal Triangle). Come up from behind and whisper intimately, preferably Ebonically, in my ear. Mais oui, I'd love to "get witchou" ce soir, cherie. And you, Mr. Businessman. Come right on over and "accidentally" rub your penis against my "gorgeous ass," as you put it, as we wait at a light. Then look at me expectantly, waiting for the nooner which will no doubt now ensue. I can take a compliment. And you, in the beat-up Pontiac: Should I cruelly refuse to answer your catcalls of love, by all means get out of your car and dog me for three blocks expressing your pain. I have now become a "fat, fucking skank," not a beauty, but I understand. You have every right to be angry. And don't worry. No one will intervene. But don't ask me for spare change while you're at it: Panhandling is strictly regulated and the cops will be all over you. I am a vision. I must be. God, I love spring. "It was spring for me, too," chuckles Northwestern University law professor Cynthia Bowman. "That's when I got the idea for the article." Well, that and Thelma & Louise. It was 1991, two years before her controversial article ("Street Harassment and the Informal Ghettoization of Women") would appear in the Harvard Law Review and cause a national sensation. Already interested in the subject of sexual harassment, she saw that infamous movie and came away struck by the audience's approving blood lust when the movie stars blew up the pig truck driver's rig. An article was born when she ran afoul of her own pig truck driver shortly thereafter. She was captive at a red light with her windows rolled down to enjoy the beautiful weather when the two men in the next vehicle laid into Bowman with a stream of sex talk and ridicule that crushed her. The confluence of events made her realize that she'd been repressing a lifetime of such incidents. Canvassing her friends, she found that she was far from alone. Hooray for Hollywood; the professor decided to fight back. In her article, Bowman labels street harassment a grueling, humiliating and frightening fact of women's lives "that has not generally been viewed by academics, judges or legislators as a problem requiring legal redress, either because these mostly male observers have not noticed the behavior or because they have considered it trivial and thus not within the proper scope of the law." It's certainly the case that many men haven't noticed it. When I discussed this article at our staff meeting, a male colleague asked, "Are you saying that when you leave this office, say to go to lunch, you'll be harassed?" He was shocked. In her first-of-its-kind academic article, Bowman proposed an anti-harassment ordinance, featuring a $250 fine, "but, if I had it to do again," she said, "I might leave that out. It was an afterthought. Everyone fixated on the ordinance, but that's just the kind of thing you do in a law review article, you propose a remedy. I just wanted to stimulate discussion of how the law too often ignores women." Stimulate discussion she did. She was denounced from one corner of America to another as the epitome of political correctness and feminism run amok, then held aloft as an icon by legions of pissed-off women who wanted her to go even further. "I was astonished by the response," the rueful professor said this week, tired from grading end-of-year exams. She wouldn't have been astonished if she lived here in D.C. "Women who've lived lots of places tell me it's worse here than anywhere else," says Denise Snyder, executive director of the D.C. Rape Crisis Center which offers training in dealing with street harassment. Quantifying an essentially untraceable phenomenon is extremely difficult, but it's certainly true that street harassment is a historically controversial topic here. In 1990, a summer series of three Washington Post articles on street harassment -- one journalistic, one essayistic, and one op-ed -- caused a firestorm. But it wasn't until 1993, the year of Bowman's law review article, that war broke out, first locally, then nationally. Washington Post writer Phil McCombs wrote "StareMasters: Every Day at Noon They Sit and Watch Their Dreams Go By," detailing a benign week of girl-watching at a construction site. The lettersto-the-editor pages and phone lines at the Post were so clogged with responses that the paper's ombudsman had to weigh in. D.C. Men Against Rape staged a protest at the construction site and national columnists took sides. ABC and CBS called. Maury Povich even wanted to fly McCombs and the construction workers to New York for a show. "Don't they have construction workers in New York?" he sensibly mused in a follow-up piece. Filmmaker Maggie Hadleigh-West believes D.C.'s street harassment is among the worst. "My hard-on about street abuse formed when I lived in D.C.," she said. By the time she was living in New York, she had become so fed up she made a documentary about it, "War Zone," in which she confronts men who harass her. The original was shown in 1993 and caused the same kind of explosion that Bowman's article had. The sequel debuts Friday at Chicago's Facets Cinematheque. Some of the men she confronts become quite abusive. "When we oppose street harassment and speak up, we make them suddenly selfconscious, we make them give up a privilege. They don't like it." Indeed they do not. And on this issue, women's anger crosses ideological lines. Amy Holmes, a policy analyst with the conservative Independent Women's Forum and a widely featured political commentator, frequently fights back. Recently harassed by a small group of men as she left her office alone at 10 p.m., they cursed her when she ignored their "hey, baby"s. "I was so mad, I whirled around and yelled, 'That's why I don't talk to guys like you!' I've even flipped some of these guys off, and I'm a polite, normal young woman. It's just gotten so bad." So bad in fact that TLC, a popular R&B trio of young women recently recorded a song, "No Scrubs," about the losers who hassle women on the streets. Why do they do it? We're not talking about gallantry, or playful flirting or simple, unfrightened compliments. Why the abuse, the privacy invasion, the intimidation? Why do the construction workers on my block, for instance, make sudden loud noises with their machinery as I pass so they can laugh when I jump? I don't ask them. I'm afraid of escalation. When I lived in San Francisco, panhandling/drug addict/psychotic bums supported by asshole tourists congregated in my North Beach neighborhood and figured out my name and apartment. Remembering them tapping on my windows, I go to a different neighborhood and ask street harassers why they do it. "Aw! There y'all go, there y'all go!" one man goes off. "Always complainin' when you should be happy. We like you, get it? We human men. We like your bodies. We like your ... your ... okay, I'll say it and it's your fault because I don't even talk like this -- we like your titties! We like titties. We men. We like women, ain't no fags round here." "Can't please a woman these days less you ready to go to jail," opined one man, fury twisting his features and making his nostrils flare. "It's a compliment, alright, jeez," another said, eyes rolled heavenward in disgust. "Why is it so wrong to tell you that you're pretty? How much time you spend getting dressed this morning? How much makeup you got at home? Huh? It's for me, right? For men." And if I don't care what random men think? "Maybe you're gay. Maybe that's all the problem, right there?" His buddy, a quieter type who, alone among the five, had said nothing as I passed, added tentatively, "I'm a human being, too. All you have to do is say hi." And if we don't want to? He thought for a minute. "Why not just say it?" "It's a big miscommunication," Hadleigh-West says. "What they think they're sending is not what we're receiving. They say they're trying to tell us we're attractive, desirable, sexy. We feel assaulted." Says Snyder, "Men claim they do it to meet women. That's bullshit. There's a power dynamic at work with street harassment. It's at the base of any sexual harassment. They don't really think they'll get dates that way." Adrian Davis, law professor at Washington College of Law at American University says street harassment has to be understood as on a continuum with sexual assault and stalking. "Women's impulse is to react. We want to respond when insulted but we fear assault. Sexual harassment in the workplace tells women they can't have an 'economic personality.' Sexual harassment on the streets prevents women from being able to fully enjoy the public sphere. If you leave home 'inappropriately,' i.e. to work or without a man, you are disciplined with sexual harassment." As does Bowman in her article, Davis points out (rightly, in my experience) that women are much less likely to be harassed while with old people or children or, of course, a man. If I'm so devastatingly gorgeous, why is this never pointed out while I'm with my fianc? "Because they know it's wrong," says Snyder flatly. Does it matter that this is most often pointed out to me (in graphic detail) by black men? Courtland Milloy, in one of those three 1990 Washington Post pieces, lamented the "black men who [make] the district a living hell for their sisters." Many of the female letter-writers made the same claim. Julianne Malveaux as well has written about her own abuse from black males and the "contempt" some of them exhibit for black women. "We are at the low end of the food chain for them," she writes. So, yes, it matters if only because 95 percent of the harassment I receive comes from them. If that's group loyalty, I can live without it. This summer, the New York chapter of NOW's anti-violence committee is planning a campaign against street harassment. "A lot of street harassment comes from men working on the streets -- movers, delivery men. If a woman can identity the company the harasser is working for, NOW will send them a letter describing the incident and asking them to take action," says Joanna Perlman of NOW. Holmes disagrees with this tactic. "It's not a legal or employer problem. It's a social problem and that tattletale approach will only exacerbate the problem. We need to ask why these guys feel entitled to say these things, why men have forgotten to be civil and gentlemanly. The people who witness these incidents, men especially, need to speak up. We need social pressure. If the police or companies are the enforcers, people can tell themselves that harassers will be ticketed, it's not their responsibility." I won't hold my breath until the people of America rise up and shame street harassers. I'll just keep hiding behind my sunglasses and Walkman until winter comes again and I can disappear into my big, shapeless coat. http://dir.salon.com/news/feature/1999/05/21/harassment/index.html?sid=62002 In a misguided attempt to alleviate racial and sexual tensions, corporate America is turning the workplace into a giant therapy couch Illustration by Tracy Cox By JOAN WALSH As the nation struggled through its group therapy session on race last fall, courtesy of O.J. Simpson, Mark Fuhrman and Louis Farrakhan, I found myself wondering why corporate America didn't have more wisdom to share, based on its decade-long experiment with diversity training, the booming mini-industry designed to cleanse the workplace of racism and sexism. Two-thirds of big employers now run some kind of diversity program. From government agencies like the FBI and the Federal Aviation Administration to firms including IBM, GE, AT&T and the New York Times, American employers have been rushing their workers into diversity training since 1987, when a Labor Department study projected that 85 percent of new workforce entries after the year 2000 would be women or minorities. Have these company-paid field trips to the front lines of race and gender conflict yielded a model for the nation? Hardly. Never before have so many people been sharing their deep, dark feelings about race and sex, with so little positive impact. Diversity training is everywhere because it plays into our American predilection to talk our troubles to death, but do nothing about them. It reflects a laziness about change on both sides of the race and gender divide. Whites, and men, want to be instructed on how to treat women and other racial groups, instead of using common sense, curiosity and compassion to figure out how they want to be treated. And women and people of color are looking for a quick-fix answer to discomfort in the workplace, an alternative to the tiresome but necessary task of making clear how they expect to be treated. Perhaps most damaging, the solemn, moralistic tone of most trainings sends a destructive message -- Diversity Is a Drag -- rather than helping companies, and individuals, see the creativity that's unleashed when cultures mix well. While most criticism to date has come from conservatives and beleaguered white men, there's a scathing critique to be made by advocates for women and racial minorities, in whose name such training is sold. "Training is becoming a substitute for dealing with the real issues that prevent women and minorities from succeeding," says Aileen Hernandez, a former NOW president, Equal Employment Opportunity Commission director and veteran corporate trainer. That became clear to me after I spent 18 months examining the ambitious diversity training program of a mid-sized California software maker, The Santa Cruz Operation, Inc. (SCO), for a Glamour magazine feature. A national diversity expert recommended the program as "a model of what these programs should be." It began in a time of crisis: the firm's founder and CEO, known for his wandering hands, was sued by four secretaries for sexual harassment. Diversity training was SCO's answer to the public relations and morale crises that ensued. To its credit, SCO set out to develop a diversity initiative that went beyond talk. It got 110 employees involved in diversity task forces, looking at how the firm could advance women by subsidizing childcare, increasing flextime for mothers, even recruit a woman for SCO's white, male board of directors. But those ideas hit internal roadblocks and went nowhere. The centerpiece of the effort turned out to be what it usually is: diversity workshops for managers. The workshop I attended was typical: middle managers squabbling about who's to blame for race and gender inequities at the firm. The session got hot when a facilitator pointed out that all but one of the Fortune 500 CEOs are white men. A white manager I'll call Tim erupted in anger. "Do you think every white guy in America is going to be CEO?" he shouted. "Eighty to 90 percent of CEOs are Episcopalian; I'm Irish Catholic. The Irish had it rough here, too! Now I'm being categorized as a white guy!" A woman from Human Resources I'll call Rita responded in a soft voice, near tears. "Tim, how do I deal with the fact that in my department, everyone knows that the men are being promoted ahead of women who've been there longer? We don't know why, except that all the men go golfing and sailing together, and make all the rules. And I'm watching good women leave the company. What should I do?" Tim stared down at his tasseled loafers, uncomfortable. "Go to Human Resources," he said, apparently forgetting that was the division she was complaining about. "I believe you, Rita, but I don't think it's about being a woman, it's about being perceived as weak." The dramatic conflict went unresolved. But Rita returned to work to learn her frank comments had been reported to her boss; Tim, by contrast, was within months promoted to director. In another tense training moment, an accounting supervisor named Lynn went head to head over sexism with a human resources manager I'll call Rick. Again, they argued to a draw. A few months later Lynn sued the firm, charging she was sexually harassed by a supervisor, and Rick was named in the suit for failing to address her complaint properly. Clearly diversity training didn't help Lynn and Rick communicate about sexual harassment. Not long after the training I attended, SCO's initiative unraveled completely. Its co-director, Gail Garrow, resigned in anger, complaining the effort was just window dressing. Garrow claimed that she herself had been sexually harassed just before the lawsuit against SCO's founder was filed, a charge the company denies. "We used the sexual harassment scandal to our benefit, and management used us, as damage control," she says now. SCO's affirmative action effort left untouched vast discrepancies between male and female managers' salaries, Garrow charged, as well as a glass ceiling that meant only two of 19 vice presidents were women. SCO's juicy scandals make good reading, but is the outcome of its program typical? Aileen Hernandez thinks its troubles are common in the field, thanks to the vexing paradox at the heart of diversity training. "To have a successful program, you need to have some diversity already -- women and people of color who are ready to advance -- and you need top management committed to advancing them," Hernandez notes. "But if you have that, you probably don't need these programs. And if you don't, all the seminars in the world can't make a difference." The truth is that, as the SCO debacle painfully demonstrated, corporate diversity programs are patronizing, quick-fix solutions to workplace tension. And they cause more backlash than positive change. http://archive.salon.com/30dec1995/features/diversity.html Terms: Compromise of 1850--First, California would be a free state and the rest of the Southwest territory would be subject to popular sovereignty. Finally, interstate slave trade was safe from congressional interference, and a fugitive slave law would return runaway slaves. Missouri Compromise--Missouri admitted as a slave state, and Maine a free state. Congress drew an imaginary line across the middle of the United States running from the east coast to the Pacific Ocean. This imaginary line separated the states into free and slave states. Any new state entering the Union that was south of the line would be a slave state. Any state north of the line would enter the Union as a free state. Wilmot Proviso-- Proposal in the U.S. Congress to prohibit the extension of slavery to the territories. Ordinance of 1787 (Great Northwest Ordinance)—a law that clearly indicated the western lands north of the Ohio River and east of the Mississippi River would be settled and become states on a par with existing ones. No fewer than three, or more than five, states would be formed. Civil rights and liberties be guaranteed. Slavery and involuntary servitude be prohibited. Three-Fifths Compromise—Counting slaves in the population for figuring representation that established that three fifths of the slaves should be counted in apportioning representation; slaves were to be treated as property in assessing taxes.